Skip to main content
Log in

Respect in Neo-Republicanism: A Good Too Rich or Too Thin?

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The article critically examines the neo-Republican conception of respect put forward by Philip Pettit in Robust Demands of the Good (RDG). The paper argues that Pettit’s treatment of respect as a rich good in RDG is too thin in some ways, but too rich in others. There are four critical claims to support this argument. First, that (a) both invading the domain of basic liberties, and failing to protect and resource the capacity to exercise choice, constitute individually sufficient conditions for disrespectful treatment, and (b) that the protection and resourcing of basic liberties are both relevant domains over which an appropriate disposition is also necessary for the provision of the rich good of respect. Second, that it is unnecessary and undesirable to rely on local conventions to provide a specification of the treatment that the status of respect requires. Third, that providing respect as a rich good in conditions of reasonable pluralism implies treating minorities in a disrespectful way. Fourth, that the role given to law in supporting the provision of the rich good of respect leads to a difficult dilemma for Pettit: either the full enjoyment of respect is not possible in nearby worlds, or it is only possible in ideal conditions that are far from nearby worlds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For these criticisms see e.g. Larmore (2003).

  2. For good discussions of respect in the literature see Carter (2011), Darwall (1977) and Eyal (2005) and for a good discussion of Pettit's work see Lovett (2010, 2016).

  3. By resourcing the ability to exercise choice e.g. by means of a system of social insurance, national health and legal assistance (Pettit 2012, pp. 112–114).

  4. On the meaning of arbitrary interference compare Pettit (1999, p. 52) with Pettit (2014, p. 58).

  5. For how such a disposition enhances civic virtue and hence good government see Efthymiou (2017).

  6. For a Kantian critique of Pettit’s Republicanism see Forst (2013).

  7. It is not clear to me whether acting from an appropriate disposition to provide the rich good of respect is sufficient for a person to be civically virtuous. See also ‘Respect as an Aspirational Ideal’ for a discussion of the relationship between motivation and respect.

  8. The aim of the example is not to judge that particular policy as a policy of resourcing but to illustrate how denying resourcing constitutes a case of disrespect.

  9. Or in cases where such policies are not implemented or where they could not easily, reliably and robustly reach their target population.

  10. Here I deal with the rather simple and straightforward case of willed lack of resourcing. But willingness on the part of an agent may not constitute a necessary condition for invasion. Pettit is ambivalent on this point (see Pettit 2012, pp. 39, 44).

  11. See Cohen (2008, pp. 361–362, pp. 381–386) and for a good discussion of Cohen’s dual criticism of Rawls, chapters 5 and 6 of Vrousalis (2015).

  12. This revision of the theory, however, undermines the structural integrity of respect as a rich good; that is the idea that the provision of one thin good along with the presence of one particular disposition are individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for the provision of one rich good. Hence, rendering respect consistent with the aforementioned two dimensions violates its structural integrity. It requires doubling the thin good and conceding that the same disposition (i.e. that of respect) could motivate the provision of two distinct thin goods. These problems, therefore, cannot be easily solved without abandoning the very notion of a rich good. See also ‘Respect as a Rich Good Versus Respect as a Disposition’ below.

  13. An example shows what is at stake here normatively speaking. Do citizens of Norway, Sweden, or the Netherlands enjoy more robust protections of their basic liberties, and hence a greater likelihood of enjoying the rich good of respect, than those of Switzerland, Germany or the UK? Did citizens of Sweden enjoy more robust protection in 2012 than 2017 etc.? An approach that can neither make nor inform inter-societal nor intra-societal comparisons of that sort is clearly too indeterminate. To counter such objections, Pettit draws a parallel in his work between his emphasis on justified variances in the level of entrenchment of basic liberties and the capability approach and its sensitivity to local standards (Pettit 2012, p. 104). But it is worth noting that the Human Development Index (HDI) (as an index heavily influenced by the capability approach) ranked the U.S. 10th in the world for 2016 whereas Sweden and Finland were 14th and 23rd respectively. The inequality adjusted HDI ranks the U.S. 19th, Sweden 8th and Finland 10th. Pettit’s Republican theory must surely be able to provide us with some guidance as to which of the two HDI indexes is a better proxy for the enjoyment of Republican freedom and its associated rich good of respect. An approach that can neither make nor inform inter-societal nor intra-societal comparisons of that sort is clearly too indeterminate. Pettit’s theory contains resources that are not deployed here (see e.g. his diminishing marginal productivity argument for equality as a means to reducing social domination in Pettit 2012, p. 91).

  14. See also Ismene’s plea to Antigone quoted above.

  15. See e.g. Hamlin and Stemplowska (2012) for how the use of indifference curves of feasible sets could serve that purpose as well as Efthymiou (2015, forthcoming).

  16. By partial compliance I mean incompliance due to unfavorable economic conditions that make it difficult for a society to meet the highest possible standards whereas by non-compliance I mean incompliance under favorable economic conditions that make meeting the highest possible standards for a particular type of society not excessively burdensome (see e.g. Rawls 1999a, p. 5).

  17. By reasonable disagreement here I mean disagreements among well-informed and well-intentioned persons (see Rawls and Erin 2001; Rawls 2005) who value basic liberties and their entrenchment rather than disagreements over the weight of basic liberties and their level of entrenchment due to conflicts of interest. The latter I treat as cases of non-compliance to the requirements of respect that do not call for respectful treatment (see previous section). For the relationship between disagreement, non-domination and respect in Pettit’s theory see e.g. Larmore (2003, pp. 115–117).

  18. See also ‘Disagreement and (Dis)respect’ section.

  19. It also possibly reflects a deeper problem with Pettit’s consequentialist approach to respect. If neo-Republicans like Pettit think that the reasons for acting respectfully matter constitutively for respect then for reasons of consistency Pettit may need to abandon a thoroughly consequentialist account and embrace a version of Republicanism that allows more room for deontological considerations (see e.g. Forst 2013).

  20. See e.g. Dalloy’s quotation above.

  21. This is broadly in line with Rawls’s view that respect for persons is the foundational value of his theory of justice (Rawls 1999a, b, 2005). ‘Respect of persons’ for Rawls is not a rich good but implies an even deeper commitment to recognizing the inherent worth and dignity of every person. It is an attempt to provide a more determinate interpretation of ‘respect for persons’ that constitutes the moral foundation on which Rawls’s theory of justice is built (Rawls 1999a, p. 513). See also Gosepath (2015).

  22. This first revision of the theory follows from the criticisms raised in ‘Disagreement and (Dis)respect’ and ‘Respect as an Aspirational Ideal’ section of the paper.

  23. This second revision is in line with the criticisms discussed earlier in the paper (in ‘Respect as a Richer Good’ and ‘Determining the Domain of Respect’ sections) that call for a more complex and determinate theory of respect.

References

  • Benn, S.I. 1988. A Theory of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., and P. Philip. 2004. The Economy of Esteem: An Essay on Civil and Political Society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, G., and P. Philip. 2005. The Feasibility Issue. In The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, ed. Frank Jackson and Michael July Smith, 258–279. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, I. 2011. Respect and the Basis of Equality. Ethics 121(3): 538–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2008. Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, R.S. 1995. Dignity, Character, and Self-Respect. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, R.S. 1997. Self-Respect: Moral, Emotional, Political. Ethics. 107(2): 226–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downie, R.S., and E. Telfer. 1969. Respect for Persons. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S.L. 1977. Two Kinds of Respect. Ethics 88(1): 36–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Efthymiou, D.E. 2015. Sen’s Idea(l) of Justice. Jurisprudence 5(2): 352–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Efthymiou, D.E. 2017. The Value of Partisanship: When and Why Partisanship Matters. Political Studies.

  • Efthymiou, D.E. forthcoming. EU migration, Out-of-work Benefits and Reciprocity. European Journal of Political Theory.

  • Eyal, N. 2005. ‘Perhaps the Most Important Primary Good’: Self-Respect and Rawls’s Principles of Justice. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 4(2): 195–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. 2013. A Kantian Republican Conception of Justice as Non-domination. In Niederberger, Andreas & Schink, Philipp, ed. Republican Democracy, 281–292. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gosepath, S. 2015. On the (Re) Construction and Basic Concepts of the Morality of Equal Respect. In Do All Persons Have Equal Moral Worth? On’Basic Equality’and Equal Respect and Concern, ed. Uwe Steinhoff, 124–141. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, A., and Z. Stemplowska. 2012. Theory, Ideal Theory and the Theory of Ideals. Political Studies Review 10(1): 48–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Human Development Index report (HDI). (2016). United Nations Development Programme. http://hdr.undp.org/sites/default/files/2016_human_development_report.pdf. Accessed on 8th February 2018.

  • Larmore, C. 2003. Liberal and Republican Conceptions of Freedom. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 6(1): 96–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lovett, F. 2010. A General Theory of Domination and Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lovett, F. 2016. Civic Republicanism and Social Justice. Political Theory 44(5): 687–696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 1999. Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 2012. On the People's Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 2014. Just Freedom : A Moral Compass for a Complex World. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 2015. The Robust Demands of the Good: Ethics with Attachment, Virtue, and Respect. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. 2016. Freedom and Other Robustly Demanding Goods. In Philip Pettit: Five Themes from his Work, ed. Derpmann Simon and Schweikard David, 3–16. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999a. A Theory of Justice, Rev ed. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999b. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 2005. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J., and K. Erin. 2001. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 2011. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vrousalis, N. 2015. The Political Philosophy of G.A. Cohen: Back to Socialist Basics. New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the two anonymous referees for their comments. I am grateful to Dorothea Gädeke, Kristina Lindemann, Philippe Pettit, Nicholas Vrousalis for comments and discussions. I am also particularly grateful to Rainer Forst and Stefan Gosepath for their support as directors of ‘Justitia Amplificata’.

Funding

The funding was provided by Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (Grand No. 1206).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dimitrios E. Efthymiou.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Efthymiou, D.E. Respect in Neo-Republicanism: A Good Too Rich or Too Thin?. Res Publica 26, 103–122 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-019-09423-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-019-09423-6

Keywords

Navigation