Skip to main content
Log in

The Allusion of the Gene: Misunderstandings of the Concepts Heredity and Gene

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Life sciences became Biology, a formal scientific discipline, at the turn of the nineteenth century, when it adopted the methods of reductive physics and chemistry. Mendel’s hypothesis of inheritance of discrete factors further introduced a quantitative reductionist dimension into biology. In 1910 Johannsen differentiated between the phenotype, which defines traits, and their genotype, the hereditary essence of such traits and their entities—the genes. The efforts to characterize these entities culminated in 1953, in Watson–Crick’s physico-chemical double helix model of DNA, the hereditary matter. However, the more molecular biology advanced the less real were its entities: Genes became generic units of heredity. The increasing role of science in society, and the mutual interdependence of the two on each other augmented the urge of the public at large to find in science icons of authority; the generic nature of the gene concept allowed scientists to offer it as the bait, even though advances in research made it clear that a distinction must be maintained between advances in reductive methodologies and the progress of systems’ conceptions. Genes out of context are meaningless. There are no “genes for” a trait: even if a specific change in a site on the DNA sequence may end in a conspicuous change in a trait, it must be realized that many sites in the DNA, in the cell, and in the organism as a complex integrated system in its environment, determine or rather, condition traits. The role of science is asking questions by putting up hypotheses and suggesting methods of testing them rather than in providing definite answers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, physiologists introduced quantitative models already at the beginning of the nineteenth century, mainly by adopting the methodology of chemists (see, for example, Lenoir 1982).

  2. Symbolically, astronaut David Scott recreated Galileo's famous experiment, at the Apollo 15 mission, on the moon, where no air hampers the free fall of a feather. Indeed on the moon, a feather and a hammer dropped simultaneously reached ground simultaneously.

  3. See, however, the “early nineteenth century German biologists” who outlined “a powerful program of empirical research” (Lenoir 1982).

References

  • Barnes, B., & Dupré, J. (2008). Genomes and what to make of them. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, G. W., & Tatum, E. L. (1941). Genetic control of biochemical reaction in Neurospora. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, Washington, 27, 499–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. H. C. (1958). On protein synthesis. In: Symposium of the society for experimental biology. The biological replication of macromolecules (Vol. 12, pp. 138–163). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Crick, F. H. C. (1970). Central dogma of molecular biology. Nature, 227(5258), 561–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebstein, R. P., Israel, S., Chew, S. H., Zhong, S., & Knafo, A. (2010). Genetics of human social behavior (review). Neuron, 65, 831–844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (1986). What is a gene? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 17(2), 133–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2000). The gene—A concept in tension. In P. J. Beurton, R. Falk, & H.-J. Rheinberger (Eds.), The concept of the gene in development and evolution: Historical and epistemological perspectives (pp. 317–348). Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2006). Mendel’s impact. Science in Context, 19(2), 215–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2008). Wilhelm Johannsen: A rebel or a diehard? In O. Harman & M. R. Dietrich (Eds.), Rebels, mavericks, and heretics in biology (pp. 65–83). New Haven & London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2009). Genetic analysis: A history of genetic thinking. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R. (2010). What is a gene?—Revisited. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science, 41(4), 396–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1960). The design of experiments ((1935, 1st) 7th ed.). Edinburgh: Oliver & Boyd.

  • Friedberg, E. G. (2011). Sydney Brenner: A biography. Cold Spring Harbor, NY: Cold Sprig Harbor Laboratory Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. (1875). A theory of heredity (revised version). Journal of the Anthropological Institute, 5, 329–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. (1877). Typical laws of heredity. Proceedings of the Royal Institution, 8, 282–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F., & Monod, J. (1961). Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. Journal of Molecular Biology, 3, 318–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (2010). The mirage of a space: Between nature and nurture. Durham & London: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lenoir, T. (1982). The strategy of life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCorquodale, K., & Meehl, P. E. (1948). On distinction between hypothetical constructs and intervening variables. Psychological Review, 55, 95–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. (2002). Naming Biology. Journal of the History of Biology, 35(1), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McShea, D. W. (2011). Untangling the Morass. Book review: The mirage of space between nature and nurture. American Scientist, 99(2), 154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, H. J. (1922). Variation due to change in the individual gene. The American Naturalist, 56, 32–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, H. J. (1955). Life. Science, 121(3132), 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D., & Lindee, M. S. (1995). The DNA Mystique. The gene as a cultural icon. New York: W. H. Freeman and comp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumann-Held, E. M., & Rehmann-Sutter, C. (Eds.). (2006). Genes in development: Re-reading the molecular paradigm. Durham and London: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pauling, L., Itano, H., Singer, S. J., & Wells, I. (1949). Sickle cell anemia, a molecular disease. Science, 110, 543–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reardon, J. (2008). Race without salvation: Beyond the science/society divide in genomic studies of human diversity. In B. A. Koenig, S. S.-J. Lee, & S. S. Richardson (Eds.), Revisiting race in a genomic age (pp. 304–319). New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salsburg, D. (2001). The lady tasting tea: How statistics revolutionized science in the twentieth century. New York: W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1944 (1962)). What Is Life? The physical aspect of the living cell. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Stadler, P. F., Prohaska, S. J., Forst, C. V., & Krakauer, D. C. (2009). Defining genes: A computational framework. Theory in Biosciences, 128(3), 165–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stent, G. S. (1968). That was the molecular biology that was. Science, 160, 390–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stent, G. S. (1969). The coming of the golden age: A view of the end of progress. New York: Natural History Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stent, G. S. (1970). DNA. Daedalus, 99, 909–937.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1972). Human understanding. The collective use and evolution of concepts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. D., & Crick, F. H. C. (1953a). Molecular structure of nucleic acids. Nature, 171, 737–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. D., & Crick, F. H. C. (1953b). The structure of DNA. Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology, 18, 123–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Sam S. Schweber, Diane B. Paul, and an anonymous reviewer for their critical, incisive, and most helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Raphael Falk.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Falk, R. The Allusion of the Gene: Misunderstandings of the Concepts Heredity and Gene. Sci & Educ 23, 273–284 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9510-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9510-4

Keywords

Navigation