Skip to main content

Extrinsic Denomination and the Origins of Early Modern Metaphysics: The Scholastic Context of Descartes’s Regulae

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Ontology, Psychology and Axiology of Habits (Habitus) in Medieval Philosophy

Part of the book series: Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action ((HSNA,volume 7))

Abstract

An assessment of Descartes’s relation to his Aristotelian contemporaries in his Regulae ad directionem ingenii—and more specifically his relation to the theory of scientific habitus—has never been undertaken and is long overdue. Despite broad scholarly consensus that Descartes rejected the scholastic theory of scientific habitus in the Regulae, I will show that, in fact, he redefines a centuries-old scholastic debate about the unity of science, and that he does so by employing, not rejecting, the concept of scientific habitus. For Descartes, the sciences are collectively one in virtue of a habitus which inclines the intellect to regard all things, not as they are in reality, but rather as they are relative to the intellect alone. Descartes establishes the unity of science via what Suárez refers to as “extrinsic denomination” in Disputationes metaphysicae 44.11.64. This creates a serious problem. As he no doubt knew and as Suárez would have rightly pointed out, the extrinsic denominations that Descartes employs in the Regulae have no ontological basis in the things denominated. Descartes’s method creates, arguably for the first time, a chasm between how things can be known by the intellect and how they are in reality—i.e., between “epistemology” and “ontology”—that motivates him to pursue metaphysics after the Regulae.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    All references to AT are to the Oeuvres de Descartes, edited by Charles Adam and Paul Tannery (Descartes 1996). All references to CSM or to CSMK are to The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, edited by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and (for volume 3) Anthony Kenny (Descartes 1985–1991).

  2. 2.

    This is the strategy of Marion (1975).

  3. 3.

    Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae (ST) I, q. 1, art. 3 (Leonina 4: 11–12; 1997, 7–8). On the genealogy of the concept of theology as a rational science in the thirteenth century, see Chenu 1957.

  4. 4.

    See Thomas Aquinas, ST I–II, q. 54, art. 4 (Leonina 6: 344; 1997, 410–412).

  5. 5.

    See Scotus , Quaestiones super libros metaphysicorum Aristotelis VI, q. 1 (Wadding 7: 302–321; 1997, 2: 5–40), Ockham, Expositio super viii libros Physicorum, Pr., (Gál et al. 4: 3–14; 1964, 1–16), Suárez , Disputationes metaphysicae (DM) 44.11.18 (1965, 699), Conimbricenses , Commentari in universam dialecticam Aristotelis Stagaritae, cap. XXIII, q. 1 (1607, 675–680). For an overview of the medieval scholastic debate about the unity of science, see Maurer (1974). On Scotus’s concept of the unity of science, see Demange (2004; 2009a; 2009b). On Ockham’s concept of habitus and the unity of science , see Maurer (1958), Miralbell-Guerin (1990), Perini-Santos (2006, 144–159), and Pelletier (2013, 13–17, 26–38). On Suárez’s concept of the unity of science, see Doyle (1991).

  6. 6.

    Suárez, DM 44.11.69 (1965, 715).

  7. 7.

    On problems involved in the historiographical concept of the Scientific Revolution, see Shapin (1996, 3).

  8. 8.

    On Beeckman, see van Berkel (2013). On the mechanization of natural philosophy in the seventeenth century, see Garber and Roux (2013).

  9. 9.

    The literature on Suárez’s definition of metaphysics is vast and controversial. See Courtine (1990), Gracia (1991; 1993), Volpi (1993), Doyle (1997), Darge (2015).

  10. 10.

    See Beck (1952) and Marion (1975, 25–30).

  11. 11.

    Cf. Ariew 1990.

  12. 12.

    Garber (1992, 15); cf. Garber (1992, 30–63; 2001, 33–52). See also Schuster (2013, 251).

  13. 13.

    The relaxation of Aristotle’s ban on cross-generic metabasis in fourteenth-century physics (see Livesey 1982) does not, it seems to me, amount to a suspension of the ban, for two reasons: (1) fourteenth-century physicists like Grosseteste continue to distinguish sciences by reference to their object, and (2) they continue to operate according to a modified Aristotelian paradigm of subalternation. As Ariew (1990, 299) convincingly argues, both subalternation and the differentiation of sciences by object are rejected by Descartes in Regula 1.

  14. 14.

    See note 10 above.

  15. 15.

    Aristotle and Aquinas are the only two figures that Beck and Marion discuss.

  16. 16.

    See, e.g., Regula 6, AT 10: 381, 382, CSM 1: 21, 22; Regula 9, AT 10: 401, 2–5, CSM 1: 34; Regula 12, AT 10: 424, CSM 1: 47; Regula 15, AT 10: 452, CSM 1: 65.

  17. 17.

    Thomas Aquinas, Super Boetium De Trinitate, q. 5, art. 1, ad 1 (Leonina 50: 139; 1963, 15–16).

  18. 18.

    For thorough discussions of Aristotle’s ban on cross-generic metabasis, see Livesey (1982) and McKirahan (1992).

  19. 19.

    Extrinsic denomination first explicitly appears in Descartes in Meditation 6 and his First Replies (to Caterus). In the former case, Descartes defines it as a “denomination which depends on my thought (denominatio a cogitatione mea… dependens); it is quite extraneous to the things of which it is said (rebusque de quibus dicitur extrinseca).” Such denominations are not “really to be found in the things themselves (revera in rebus reperitur)” (AT 7: 85).

  20. 20.

    Doyle (1991, 327–328). On extrinsic denomination in Suárez , see Doyle (1984).

  21. 21.

    Garber (2001, 48; 1992, 15).

  22. 22.

    Schuster (2013, 251).

  23. 23.

    AT 3: 722–723; CSMK 3: 144. On the role played by the concept of eruditio and industria in Descartes’s concepts of method and science, see Kambouchner (2009) and Kambouchner (2016; provided courtesy of the author).

  24. 24.

    AT 10: 371–374; CSM 1: 16–17: “Per methodus autem intelligo regulas certas et faciles, quas quicumque exacte servaverit, nihil unquam falsum pro vero supponet, et nullo mentis conatu inutiliter consumpto, sed gradatim semper augendoscientiam, perveniet ad veram cognitionem eorum omnium quorum erit capax.”

  25. 25.

    See, e.g., Regula 6, AT 10: 384, CSM 1: 22–23; Regula 9, AT 10: 400, 401, CSM 1: 33, 34.

  26. 26.

    Cf. Kambouchner (2016): “The aim of the directio ingenii consists in making ingenium capable of reaching its own fullness; and Rules 9 and 10, which one could consider of minor epistemological significance, will be here of major importance. […] [T]he cultivated ingenium will be the most perspicacious as well as the most sagacious.” Gauvin (2011, 330) makes an excellent case for why perspicuitas and sagacitas are habitus in the Regulae.

  27. 27.

    See Heidegger (1967, 101): “Only one who has really thought through this relentlessly sober volume [Regulae ad directionem ingenii] long enough, down to its remotest and coldest corner, fulfills the prerequisite for getting an inkling of what is going on in modern science.”

References

Primary Literature

  • Conimbricenses. 1607. Commentarii in universam dialecticam Aristotelis Stagiritae. Cologne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francisco Suárez. 1965. Disputationes metaphysicae, 2 vols. Hildesheim: Olms.

    Google Scholar 

  • John Duns Scotus. 1997. Questions on the Metaphysics of Aristotle. Trans. Girard J. Etzkorn and Allan B. Wolter. 2 vols. St. Bonaventure: Franciscan Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Opera omnia: editio minor, ed. Giovanni Lauriola. Alberrobello: ABA.

    Google Scholar 

  • René Descartes. 1985–1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ed. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny. 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Œuvres de Descartes, 11 vols, ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. 11 vols. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. 1888–1896. Summa theologiae, ed. Commissio Leonina. 9 vols. Opera Omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita 4–12. Rome: Ex Typographia Polyglotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. The Division and Methods of the Sciences: Questions V and VI of His Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius. Trans. Armand A. Maurer. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Super Boetium De Trinitate, ed. Commissio Leonina. Opera Omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita 50. Rome: Commissio Leonina; Paris: Éditions du Cerf.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, 2 vols. Trans. Anton C. Pegis. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • William Ockham. 1967–1988. Guillelmi de Ockham opera philosophica et theologica, ed. Gedeon Gál et al. 17 vols. St. Bonaventure: Franciscan Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Philosophical Writings: A Selection. Trans. Philotheus Boehner and Stephen F. Brown. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

Secondary Literature

  • Ariew, Roger. 1990. Christopher Clavius and the classification of the sciences. Synthese 83 (2): 293–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, John Leslie. 1952. The Method of Descartes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chenu, Marie Dominique. 1957. La théologie comme science au XIIIe siècle. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Courtine, François. 1990. Suárez et le système de la métaphysique. Paris: Vrin.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darge, Rolf. 2015. Suárez on the subject of metaphysics. In A Companion to Francisco Suárez, ed. Victor M. Salas and Robert L. Fastiggi, 91–123. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demange, Dominique. 2004. Objet premier d’inclusion virtuelle: Introduction à la théorie de la science de Jean Duns Scot. In Duns Scot à Paris (1302–2002), ed. Olivier Boulnois, Elizabeth Karger, Jean-Luc Solère, and Gérard Sondag, 89–116. Turnhout: Brepols.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009a. La théologie est-elle une science? La réponse de Duns Scot à Godefroid de Fontaines dans le prologue des Reportata Parisiensia. Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 20: 547–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009b. Structure et unité de la science selon Duns Scot. Itinerarium 55: 329–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doyle, John. 1984. Prolegomena to a study of extrinsic denomination in the work of Francisco Suárez, S.J. Vivarium 22 (2): 121–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. Suárez on the unity of a scientific habit. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 63 (3): 311–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Between transcendental and transcendental: The missing link? The Review of Metaphysics 50: 783–815.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ Metaphysical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Descartes Embodied: Reading Cartesian Philosophy Through Cartesian Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel, and Sophie Roux, eds. 2013. The Mechanization of Natural Philosophy. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauvin, Jean-François. 2011. Instruments of knowledge. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy in Early Modern Europe, ed. Desmonde M. Clarke and Catherine Wilson, 315–388. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gracia, Jorge. 1991. Suárez’s conception of metaphysics: A step in the direction of mentalism? American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 65 (3): 287–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Suárez and metaphysical mentalism. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 67 (2): 349–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1967. What is a thing? Trans. W.B. Barton, Jr. and Vera Deutsch. South Bend: Gateway Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kambouchner, Denis. 2009. Descartes et le problème de la doctrine. In Vera Doctrina: Zur Begriffsgeschichte der Lehre von Augustinus bis Descartes, ed. Philippe Büttgen, Ruedi Imbach, and U.J. Schneider, 365–379. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Methodical invention: Cartesian ingenium at work. Unpublished

    Google Scholar 

  • Livesey, Steven J. 1982. Metabasis: The Interrelationship of the Sciences in Antiquity and the Middle Ages. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Jean-Luc. 1975. Sur l’ontologie grise de Descartes: Science cartésienne et savoir aristotélicien dans les Regulae. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, Armand A. 1958. Ockham’s conception of the unity of science. Mediaeval Studies 20: 98–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. The unity of a science: St. Thomas and the nominalists. In St. Thomas Aquinas 1274–1974: Commemorative Studies, ed. Armand A. Maurer, 269–291. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKirahan, Richard. 1992. Principles and Proofs: Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstrative Science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miralbell-Guerin, Ignacio. 1990. Rational science and real science in William of Ockham (an introduction to Ockham’s philosophy of science). In Knowledge and the Sciences in Medieval Philosophy: Proceedings of the Eighth International Congress of Medieval Philosophy (S.I.E.P.M.), Helsinki 24–29 August 1987, ed. Reijo Työrinoja, vol. 3, 134–143. Helsinki: Annals of the Finnish Society for Missiology and Ecumenics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier, Jenny E. 2013. William Ockham on Metaphysics: The Science of Being and God. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perini-Santos, E. 2006. La théorie ockhamienne de la connaissance evidente. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuster, John. 2013. Descartes-Agonistes: Physico-Mathematics, Method, & Corpuscular-Mechanism, 1618–33. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 1996. The Scientific Revolution. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Berkel, Klaas. 2013. Isaac Beeckman on Matter and Motion: Mechanical Philosophy in the Making. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volpi, Franco. 1993. Suárez et le problème de la métaphysique. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 3: 396–411.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tarek R. Dika .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Dika, T.R. (2018). Extrinsic Denomination and the Origins of Early Modern Metaphysics: The Scholastic Context of Descartes’s Regulae. In: Faucher, N., Roques, M. (eds) The Ontology, Psychology and Axiology of Habits (Habitus) in Medieval Philosophy. Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action, vol 7. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-00235-0_21

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics