Skip to main content

The Role of Truth-Values in Indirect Meanings

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Language, Music and Computing (LMAC 2017)

Abstract

The problem of truth-values of indirect meanings is discussed within the semantic theory of indirect meaning proposed by the present authors in a dialogue with Hintikka’s and Sandu’s theory. The authors preserve the key notion of the latter, the meaning line, but putting it into different semantics (non-Fregean situational) and logic (paraconsistent). Like the contradictions, the indirect meanings tend to an explosion (there are always such possible worlds where they are true); to make them meaningful, there is a need of singling out the only relevant transworld connexion among the infinite number of the possible ones. The meaning line serves to this purpose. An analysis of the simplest semantic constructions with indirect meaning (tropes, humour, hints, riddles, etc.) is proposed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In our previous article [35], we have shown this, among others, with a demonstration borrowed in the so-called theorem of Putnam [45]. Putnam’s result in his demonstration by contradiction of the untenability of the Fregean semantics (Putnam’s example: the sentence “a cat on a mat” is true if and only if there is a cherry on a tree) ceases to be absurd if we replace, in his demonstration, the Montague intentions with the meaning lines: there could be a metaphorical sense in what this result is meaningful, e.g., if Cherry is a name of a cat. This fact proves that the meaning lines are not possible in the Fregean semantics where the denotation of a sentence is its truth-value. Therefore, the meaning lines belong to situational semantics, where the denotation of a sentence is the situation it refers to. We have demonstrated further that, in the case of indirect meanings, this semantics is similar to the situational semantics by Roman Suszko (cf. [54]) but even weaker. Moreover, the so-called “metaphorical logic” proposed by Vladimir Vasjukov [57] for formalising the ontology by Alexis Meinong is applicable to the poetical tropes of the natural language. If Hintikka and Sandu are right in insisting that the sentences containing indirect meanings and those that do not have the same formal semantics (we agree with them on this point), then, the semantics of natural language as a whole is non-Fregean and situational. See Appendix for a more formal summary.

  2. 2.

    We can consider this nick as a metaphor regardless of its possible usage as a personal name of a pet, because, in the case of the cat called Cherry, the metaphor is certainly not dead, in contrast with so-called dead metaphors such as “hot dog”.

  3. 3.

    “Impossible world” is a kind of possible worlds where are broken the logical laws that are presumed to be in force in this world.

  4. 4.

    Here we avoid a discussion of semantics of natural language in general and a detailed distinction between direct and indirect meanings. In our previous paper [35], we have briefly discussed incompatibility of Hintikka—Sandu’s approach with the Fregean semantics of natural language (in the wake of Richard Montague and David Lewis), despite their own intention to overcome a “crisis” in this discipline.

  5. 5.

    Cf. his hypothetical “Thesis of Extensionality” [8, pp. 245–247].

  6. 6.

    Unless humour and jokes become a constituent part of the therapist’s technics, serving, most often, to reduce patient’s paranoid sadistic impulses and aggression. In such cases, humour and jokes are used for restoring patient’s personality (transforming the transference-countertansference relationship between him and the therapist). If this succeeds, the patient starts to realise the humoristic nature of therapist’s words. For a discussion of this complicated matter, s. [4].

  7. 7.

    In his 1927 article “Humour” (“Der Humor”) [16]. For placing the Freudian psychoanalytic approach to the humour into the context of the 20th-century interdisciplinary humour studies, s. [38].

  8. 8.

    For a larger than Freudian psychoanalytic approach to the humour, s. [41]. This approach, inspired, in a large part, by Ignacio Matte Blanco, could be the most interesting for a logician.

  9. 9.

    From his 1905 book “Jokes and their relation to the unconscious” (“Der Witz und seine Beziehung zum Unbewußten”) [17, p. 120].

  10. 10.

    The corresponding chapter is entitled “Freud’s Rhetoric and Symbolics” [56, pp. 247–254].

  11. 11.

    Cf. a detailed and rich monograph [6].

  12. 12.

    This Grice’s seminal paper has been written in 1967 and first published in 1975; cf. also its 1987 continuation [23, pp. 53–54].

  13. 13.

    Ralph Müller [40] provides a concise introduction to the problem, albeit without any specific logical theories and attention to the truth-values either. Salvatore Attardo [3] implies a cognitive (Lakoff-styled) theory of metaphor, which undermines its interest to our purpose.

  14. 14.

    Ivan Panaev’s poem Будто из Гейне (As if from Heine), a parody on the Russian poetical translations from and imitations of Heinrich Heine. With the music by N. D. Dmitriev (1848)—which Panaev himself called “beautiful” in 1855,—it became a famous romance Густолиственных кленов аллея… (The alley of thick-foliage maples…), and this despite its obviously humoristic wording, alliterations, and paronomasias. Paradoxically, as a parody, the poem was unusually successful: it “killed” (as contemporary critics said) the epigonous lyrics it was aimed at. See, for the text and a commentary, [26, pp. 650, 1040]. We are grateful to Eleonora I. Khudoshina for having pointed us out this story.

  15. 15.

    Story I, 12 [44, pp. 105–111].

  16. 16.

    For an orientation in the ocean of literature on the riddle by folklorists and anthropologists, s., e.g., [1]. The most of this literature could be of only tangential interest for a logician. Among the recent most comprehensive studies, s. especially those of Savely Senderovich [52, 53].

  17. 17.

    In the most archaic structures of riddle, there are not two but three situations involved, thus establishing the transworld connexion between three possible worlds; cf. more on them below, Sect. 8.

  18. 18.

    [55, pp. 203.26–204.2]: αἰνίγματός τε γὰρ ἰδέα αὕτη ἐστί, τὸ λέγοντα ὑπάρχοντα ἀδύναται συνάψαι· κατὰ μὲν οὖν τὴν τῶν ἄλλων ὀνομάτων σύνθεσιν οὐχ οἷόν τε τοῦτο ποιῆσαι, κατὰ δὲ τὴν μεταφορῶν ἐνδέχεται.

  19. 19.

    Beside Senderovich’s monorgaphs [52, 53], the most interesting, from a logical point of view, is the chain of three articles [5, 27, 37] by Ian Hamnet, who elaborated the topic on the role of inconsistency and ambiguities in various kinds of human interaction, not only the riddles. He specified, moreover, that the kind of ambiguity involved here is not vagueness but indetermination: it results not from lack of specification, as vagueness, but because the text or ritual “fails to indicate which of two (or more) references is intended, though each possible reference may be fairly specific in itself” [27, p. 383]. In this way, Hamnet distinguished, even though without strict logical terminology, between the subcontrary and contrary oppositions, stating that only the first is involved in the archaic rituals, riddles etc.

  20. 20.

    We will quote the first publication [15]; cf. French and German translations [13, 14].

  21. 21.

    Who does not mention [15] in his [52, 53].

  22. 22.

    “…вопрос загадки и ее ответ суть тавтологии, но построенные таким образом, что обе тавтологические части разнонаправлены (по крайней мере на поверхностном уровне): разведение этих двух структур на максимально возможное расстояние не только «скрывает» аспект тождества, но и представляет собой своего рода аналог выведения смысла мира вовне или, точнее, удержание предельно большого расстояния между смыслом (ответом загадки) и вопросом о нем, в других терминах — сохранение такого максимального напряжения между тавтологическими членами, когда сама тавтологичность предельно скрыта” [15, pp. 16–17]. “Из этого принципа вытекает, что, по сути дела, решением загадки должен считаться не просто ответ (загадка вообще менее всего связана с угадыванием и импровизацией, но со знанием и искусством его порождения), а ответ как свернутый знак всей процедуры экспликации скрытого тождества обеих частей загадки” [15, p. 38, n. 7]. The passage starts in the main texts and continues in an endnote, but we do not interrupt the textual flow in our translation.

  23. 23.

    See, for details, [27, 52, 53].

  24. 24.

    See Martin Gardner’s note 5 to ch. 7 in [9, pp. 71–73]. Lewis Carroll himself wrote about his answer (ibid.): “This, however, is merely an afterthought; the Riddle, as originally invented, had no answer at all.” Our question is whether this “at all” means to be absolute (ontological) or merely epistemological.

  25. 25.

    For the transworld meaning lines, we can postulate a specific (im)possible world, where the meaning lines belonging to the “anti-humour” of type (2) do not exist.

  26. 26.

    Cf. a comparative study of several hermeneutic traditions: [58].

  27. 27.

    Origen, On the Principles, books III and IV; cf., on this feature of the traditional Christian exegesis, Henri de Lubac’s studies, starting from [11].

  28. 28.

    For the use in the exegesis, s. [22].

  29. 29.

    For a logical analysis, s. especially [48,49,50].

  30. 30.

    In the context of the present paper, the most relevant literature on Sarbiewski are [19, 30, 34, 43].

  31. 31.

    For the sake of brevity, we apply, in Table 1, truth-values “true” and “false” to the situations and the relations, taking in mind that they are applicable to the propositions that describe situations and relations.

  32. 32.

    For a detailed explanation, s. [35].

  33. 33.

    See, for a detailed bibliography, [12].

References

  1. Abrahams, R.D., Dundes, A.: Riddles. In: Dorson, R.M. (ed.) Folklore and Folklife: An Introduction, pp. 129–143. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Aronsson, K.: Language practices and the visibility of language. Reflections on the great divide in the light of ethiopian oral traditions. In: Säljö, R. (ed.) The Written World: Studies in Literate Thought and Action. Springer Series in Language and Communication, vol. 23, pp. 73–83. Springer, Berlin (1988)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  3. Attardo, S.: Humorous metaphors. In: Brône, G., Feyaerts, K., Veale, T. (eds.) Cognitive Linguistics and Humor Research. In: Applications of Cognitive Linguistic, 26, pp. 91–110. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Baker, R.: The Delicate balance between the use and abuse of humor in the psychoanalytic setting. In: Barron, J.W. (ed.) Humor and Psyche: Psychoanalytic Perspectives, pp. 109–130. The Analytic Press Inc., Hillsdale (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Barley, N.F.: Structural aspects of the anglo-saxon riddle. Semiotica 10, 143–175 (1974)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Bell, N.: We are not amused: failed humor in interaction. In: Humor Research, 10. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Boyarin, D.: Sparks of the logos: essays in rabbinic hermeneutics. The Brill Reference Library of Judaism, 11. Brill, Leiden (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Carnap, R.: The Logical Syntax of Language, tr. A. Smeaton (Countess von Zeppelin). International Library of Psychology, pp. 245–247. Routledge, London (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Carroll, L.: The Annotated Alice. The Definitive Edition. Introduction and notes by M. Gardner. W. W. Norton & Co., New York (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Davidson, D.: What Metaphors Mean. In: Idem, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, pp. 245–264. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1984) [repr. 1991]

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  11. de Lubac, H.: Histoire et Esprit. L’intelligence de l’Écriture d’après Origène, Théologie, 16; Paris: Aubier (1950); 2nd edn. Cerf, Paris (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Deutsch, H.: Relative identity. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), forthcoming https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/identity-relative/

  13. Elizarenkova, T.Ya., Toporov, V.N.: L’énigme védique du type brahmodya. In: Permiakov, G. (ed.) Tel grain tel pain: Poétique de la sagesse populaire, pp. 207–251. Progrès, Moscow (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Elizarenkova, T.Ya., Toporov, V.N.: Zum vedischen Rätsel des Typs brahmodya. In: Eismann, W., Grzybek, P. (eds.) Semiotische Studien zum Rätzel: Simple forms reconsidered II. Bochumer Beiträge zur Semiotik, 7, pp. 39–73. Studienverlag Brockmeyer, Bochum (1987)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Elizarenkova, T.Ya., Toporov, V.N.: On vedic puzzle brahmodya. In: Permyakov, G. (ed.) Paremiologicheskie issledovania. Issledovania po folklore i mifologii Vostoka. Moscow: Nauka, 14–46 (1984); reprinted in: Nikolaeva T.M. (ed.) Iz rabot Moskovskogo semioticheskogo kruga. Yazyk, semiotika, kultura, pp. 303–338. Yazyki mirovoy kultury, Moscow (1997). (in Russian)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Freud, S.: Humour. In: [18], vol. 21, pp. 159–166

    Google Scholar 

  17. Freud, S.: Jokes and their relation to the unconscious. In: [18], vol. 8

    Google Scholar 

  18. Freud, S.: The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Translated from German. Ed. by Strachey, J. Freud, A., 24 vols. The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, London (1956–1974)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Fullenwider, H.F.: Concors discordia: Sarbiewski’s De acuto et arguto (1627) and Jean de Serres’ Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus (1587). Bibliothèque d’Humanisme et de Renaissance 46, 619–624 (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Gärdenfors, P., Löhndorf, S.: What is a domain? Dimensional structures versus meronomic relations. Cogn. Linguist. 24, 437–456 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Gärdenfors, P.: The Geometry of Meaning: Semantics Based on Conceptual Spaces. MIT, Cambridge (2014)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Girma, M.: Whose meaning? the wax and gold tradition as a philosophical foundation for an ethiopian hermeneutic. Sophia 50, 175–187 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Grice, P.: Further notes on logic and conversation. In: [25], pp. 41–57

    Google Scholar 

  24. Grice, P.: Logic and Conversation. In: [25], pp. 22–40

    Google Scholar 

  25. Grice, P.: Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Gusev, V.E.: Songs and Romances by Russian Poets: Introduction. Sovetskiy pisatel’, Moscow. (in Russian) (1965)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Hamnett, I.: Ambiguity, Classification and Change, vol. 2, pp. 379–392. The Function of Riddles, Man, N.S (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Hintikka, J., Sandu, G.: Metaphor and other kinds of nonliteral meaning. In: Hintikka, J. (ed.) Aspects of Metaphor. Synthese Library 238, pp. 151–188. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (1994). Repr. in: J. Hintikka, Selected Papers, vol. 4: Paradigms for Language Theory and Other Essays, pp. 274–310. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (1998)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  29. Jabbur, J.S., Jabbur, S.J.: Bedouins and the Desert, transl. L. Conrad. State University of New York Press, Albany (1995)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Lachmann, R.: ‘Problematic Similarity’: Sarbiewski’s Treatise De acuto et arguto in the Context of Concettistic Theories of the 17th Century. Russ. Lit. 27, 239–252 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Lakoff, G.: The contemporary theory of metaphor. In: Ortony, A. (ed.) Metaphor and Thought, 2d edn, pp. 202–251. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1993)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  32. Levine, D.N.: The Flight from Ambiguity: Essays in Social and Cultural Theory. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1985)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  33. Levine, D.N.: Wax and Gold: Tradition and Innovation in Ethiopian Culture. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1965)

    Google Scholar 

  34. Li Vigni, A.: Poeta quasi creator. Estetica e poesia in Mathias Casimir Sarbiewski. Aesthetica Preprint, Supplementa, 13; Palermo: Centro Internazionale Studi di Estetica (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Lourié, B., Mitrenina, O.: Semantics of poetical tropes: non-fregeanity and paraconsistent logic. In: Arkadiev, P., et al. (eds.) Donum semanticum: Opera liguistica et logica in honorem Barbarae Partee a discipulis amicisque Rossicis oblata, pp. 177–191. LRC Publishers, Moscow (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Mahmud, H.A.-S.: Classical Arab Poetic convention by the Umayyad period: a psychological study of imagination. Asian Afr. Stud. 21, 35–69 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Maranda, E.K.: Structure des énigmes. L’Homme 9(3), 5–48 (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  38. Matte, G.: A psychoanalytical perspective of humor. Humor 14, 223–241 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Menken, M.J.J.: Old Testament Quotations in the Fourth Gospel: Studies in Textual Form, Contributions to Biblical Exegesis and Christology, 15. Kok Pharos Publishing House, Kampen (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  40. Müller, R.: Metaphorical perspective on humour. In: Brône, G., Feyaerts, K., Veale, T. (eds.) Cognitive Linguistics and Humor Research. Applications of Cognitive Linguistic, 26, pp. 111–128. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Newirth, J.: Jokes and their relation to the unconscious: humor as a fundamental emotional experience. Psychoanal. Dialogues 16, 557–571 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Nosnitsin, D.: Sämǝnna wärq. In: Uhlig, S. (ed.) Encyclopaedia Aethiopica, vol. 4, pp. 507–509. Harrassowitz, Wiesbaden (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  43. Otwinowska, B.: “Concors discordia” Sarbiewskiego w teorii konceptyzmu. Pamiętnik Literacki 59(3), 81–110 (1968)

    Google Scholar 

  44. Panchatantra and Hitopadesha Stories. Translation and Introduction by A. S. P. Ayyar. 2nd rev. and enlarged ed. Madras: V. Ramasvamy Sastrulu & Sons (1960)

    Google Scholar 

  45. Putnam, H.: Reason, Truth, and History. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1981)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  46. Raskin, V.: The sense of humor and the truth. In: Ruch, W. (ed.) The Sense of Humor: Explorations of a Personality Characteristic. Humor Research, 3, pp. 95–108. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  47. Sarbiewski, M.C.: O poezji doskonałej czyli Wergiliusz i Homer (De perfecta poesi, sive Vergilius et Homerus). Opracował S. Skimina. Biblioteka Pisarzów Polskich; Wrocław: Wyd. PAN (1954)

    Google Scholar 

  48. Schumann, A.: Logical cornerstones of judaic argumentation theory. Argumentation 27, 305–326 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Schumann, A.: Qal wa-homer and theory of massive-parallel proofs. Hist. Philos. Log. 32, 71–83 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Schumann, A.: Talmudic Logic; Studies in Talmudic Logic, 6. College Publications, London (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  51. Searl, J.R.: Metaphor, in idem, Expression and Meaning. Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts. Cambridge UP, Cambridge (1979). [repr. (2005)]

    Book  Google Scholar 

  52. Senderovich, S.: The Riddle of the Riddle: A Study of the Folk Riddle’s Figurative Nature. Kegan Paul Ltd., London (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  53. Senderovich, S.: Morphology of a puzzle. Studia Philologica. Yazyki slavyansloy kultury, Moscow (2008) (in Russian)

    Google Scholar 

  54. Suszko, R.: The abolition of the Fregean axiom. In: Parikh, R. (ed.) Logic Colloquium: Symposium on Logic Held at Boston, 1972-73. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 453, pp. 169–239. Springer, Berlin (1975)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  55. Tarán, L., Gutas, D.: Aristotle, Poetics. Editio maior of the Greek Text with Historical Introductions and Philological Commentaries. Mnemosyne, Supplements, 338. Brill, Leiden (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  56. Todorov, T.: Theories of the Symbol. Tr. by C. Porter. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  57. Vasjukov, V.L.: A Non-Fregean Guide to Husserl’s and Meinong’s Jungles. I-II (in Russian), Logicheskie issledovaniya No 11, 99–118 (2004); No 12, pp. 146–161 (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  58. Visotzky, B.L.: Midrash, Christian Exegesis, and Hellenistic Hermeneutic. In: Bakhos, C. (ed.) Current Trends in the Study of Midrash, Supplements to the Journal for the Study of Judaism, 106, pp. 111–131. Brill, Leiden (2006)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Basil Lourié .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Lourié, B., Mitrenina, O. (2019). The Role of Truth-Values in Indirect Meanings. In: Eismont, P., Mitrenina, O., Pereltsvaig, A. (eds) Language, Music and Computing. LMAC 2017. Communications in Computer and Information Science, vol 943. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-05594-3_15

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-05594-3_15

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-05593-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-05594-3

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics