Skip to main content

Biolaw, Liberalism and Cognitive Enhancement: Identifying Harms

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Biolaw and Policy in the Twenty-First Century

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 78))

Abstract

In this chapter, some of the articulated criticisms against cognitive enhancement through the use of pharmacological agents as well as some ways of counteracting them will be examined. In the argumentation , the institutional apparatus of a liberal democracy of capitalist production will be supossed. While each of these factors (liberalism , democracy , and capitalism ) admits different interpretations, the argument is not played in their specification . One important conclusion will be that uncertainty about the consequences of cognitive enhancement in health should also be considered in the equation. If there is no damage in its use, there is no reason to restrict access. But if it causes harm , or is likely to produce it, this consideration may change. As a general rule: the more dangerous the enhancement , or the more uncertain the health consequences, the better it is to control and restrict access. However, if it has no serious consequences on health, there would be no reason , from a liberal perspective , to restrict its use.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    According to empirical research on the prevalence of cognitive enhancement , breeders are now widely used by academics, as well as college and university students, to improve their cognitive abilities. For an overview of its use, compare Repantis et al (2010), Glannon (2008), Chatterjee (2004), Dubljevic (2012, 2013); Jotterand and Dubljevic (2016). For a review of the literature on use in Latin America , compare Loewe (2016).

  2. 2.

    Questions about margins are difficult. There are the synchronous margins. As is known here are humans who are not—still or will never be—persons (fetuses, severe mentally deficient, etc.), and persons who are not human (exemplarily the case of nonhuman animals ). In addition, there are the diachronic margins, which refer to persons who do not yet exist and even do not exist, and perhaps to those who no longer exist. Here the themes of intergenerational and anamnética justice arise. While I have addressed these issues (Loewe 2010b, 2011a, 2014, 2015a), the arguments in this text do not suppose or prejudge any answers to those questions.

  3. 3.

    For this line of argument against enhancement , compare Sandel (2007).

  4. 4.

    According to a survey by the National Academy of Sports Medicine in Chicago, 195 of 198 performance athletes surveyed would have no reserves in doping. To the question, “would you take a prohibited substance that would make you gain all the powers in the next five years, even though it later makes you die?” More than half of the athletes responded positively (Sport Illustrated, April 1977, quoted in Gesang 2007: 90).

  5. 5.

    This implies that cognitive enhancers can promote equal opportunity as a kind of compensation for impaired natural cognitive abilities. For an argument for enhancement that is grounded in considerations of egalitarian justice , compare Loewe (2016).

  6. 6.

    The application of the fair principle of equal opportunities is also criticized. Buchanan, for example, proposes a model of normal limited function of equal opportunities. According to this conception, the goal of medicine is to keep individuals close to normal functioning. The disease is morally relevant because “limits on the most serious cases, at least by preventing persons from developing the threshold of abilities necessary for being a “normal competitor” in social cooperation .” (Buchanan 1995; Buchanan et al. 2000: 74). For a discussion of this model , compare Loewe (2016).

  7. 7.

    Even the Chicago School of Economics recognizes that there must be something like “self-paternalism .” Something like I want to be forced to do something (enter a social insurance, use a motorcycle helmet, etc.), because I know, that if I were not forced, I would opt for short and not long term maximizations. Just as Odysseus attaches himself to the mast, people can choose to self-bond. For a critical position against the paternalism of the Chicago School, compare Kronman and Posner (1979).

  8. 8.

    In this respect I follow Raz (1988).

  9. 9.

    Sandel criticizes human enhancement by reference to the “ethics of the given” (2007). A critique of this position in Loewe (2010a). I will return to this argument in Sect. 6.

  10. 10.

    The usual demonstrations resort to mental experiments. Compare the well-known machine of experiences presented by Nozick (1974: 42–45). A discussion in Loewe (2011b).

  11. 11.

    For a discussion on these arguments , compare Loewe (2015b).

References

  • Agar, N. (2010). Humanity’s end. Whay we should reject radical enhancement. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kronman, A. T., & Posner, R. A. (1979). The economics of contract law. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appel, J. (2008). When the Boss Turns Pusher: A proposal for employee protections in the age of cosmetic neurology. Journal of Medical Ethics, 34, 616–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, K. A. (2005). The ethics of identity. Princeton, Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (2005). Why social justice matters. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom, N. (2003). Human genetic enhancement: A transhumanistic perspective. Journal of Value Inquiry, 37(4), 493–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom, N., & Sandberg, A. (2009). Cognitive enhancement: methods, ethics, regulatory challenges. Science and Engineering Ethics, 15, 311–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A. (1995). Equal opportunity and genetic intervention. Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation, 1, 105–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., Brock, D., Daniels, N., & Wikler, D. (2000). From chance to choice. Genetic and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chatterjee, A. (2004). Cosmetic neurology—the controversy over enhancing movement, mentation, and mood. Neurology, 63(6), 968–974.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jongh, R., Bolt, I., Schermer, M., & Olivier, B. (2008). Botox for the brain: Enhancement of cognition, mood and pre-social behavior and blunting of unwanted memories. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 32, 760–776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2005a). Enhancement technologies and human identity. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 30(3), 261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2005b). Human identity and bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević, V. (2012). Toward a legitimate public policy on cognitive enhancement drugs. AJOB Neuroscience, 3(3), 29–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubljević, V. (2013). Prohibition or coffee shops: Regulation of amphetamine and methylphenidate for enhancement use by healthy adults. The American Journal of Bioethics, 13(7), 23–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engels, F. (1962). Dialektik der Natur. Anteil der Arbeit an der Menschwerdung des Affen. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1988). The importance about what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gesang, B. (2007). Perfektionierung des Menschen. New York, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glannon, W. (2008). Psychopharmacological enhancement. Neuroethics, 1, 45–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glover, J. (2006). Choosing children. The ethical dilemmas of genetic intervention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottfredson, L. (1997). Why G matters: The complexity of everyday life. Intelligence, 24(1), 79–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottfredson, L. (2004). Life, death, and intelligence. Journal of Cognitive Education and Psychology, 4(1), 23–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2001). Die Zukunft der menschlichen Natur. Auf dem Weg zu einer liberalen Eugenik?. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. (2007). Enhancing evolution. The ethical case for making better people. Princeton, Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, J. (2004). Citizen Cyborg: Why democratic societies must respond to the redesigned human of the future. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husain, M., & Mehta, M. A. (2011). Cognitive enhancement by drugs in health and disease. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15, 28–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jotterand, F., & Dubljevic, V. (Eds.). (2016). Cognitive enhancement. Ethical and policy implications in international perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Juengst, E (1988): What does enhancement means? In: E.Parens (ed.): Enhancing human traits. Ethical and social implications. Washington, Georgetown University Press, 29–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraybill, D. (1989). The riddle of Amish culture. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraybill, D. (Ed.). (1993). The Amish and the state. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe, D. (2010a). The case against perfection. Ethics in the age of genetic engineering de Michael J. Sandel. Signos Filosóficos, 12(23), 207–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe, D. (2010b). Obligaciones hacia generaciones futuras: el caso Contractual. Veritas, 55(1), 21–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe (2011a). Der Umfang der moralischen Gemeinschaft. In L. Kovács & C. Brand (Eds.), Forschungspraxis Bioethik (pp. 155–158). Freiburg/München: Alber Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe (2011b): La felicidad y el bienestar subjetivo. In: Carmen Trueba Atienza (ed.): La felicidad: Perspectivas antiguas, modernas y contemporáneas. México, Siglo XXI, 362–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe, D. (2014). Justicia y memoria: obligaciones de justicia anamnética. In A. Stefane & G. Bustamante (Eds.), La Agonía de la convivencia (pp. 87–99). Santiago: Ril editores.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe, D. (2015a). Justicia contractual y los seres del futuro. In M. Figueroa (Ed.), Liberalismo político. Problemas y desarrollos contemporáneos (pp. 205–245). Santiago: Ril editores.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewe, D. (2015b). Liberalismo político, educación y particularismo religioso: Wisconsin v. Yoder y el valor de la educación. Revista de Estudios Políticos, 170, 121–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewe (2016). Cognitive Enhancement and the leveling of the playing field: The case of Latin America. In F. Jotterand & V. Dubljevic (Eds.), Cogmitive enhancement: Ethical and Policy implications in international perspectives (pp. 219–236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maslen, H., Faulmüller, N., & Savulescu, J. (2014). Pharmacological cognitive enhancement—how neuroscientific research coul advance ethical debate. Fontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 8, 107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merkel, R., Boer, G., Fegert, J., Galert, T., Hartmann, D., Nuttin, B., et al. (2007). Intervening in the brain. Changing psyche and society. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (2000). On liberty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1987). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quante, M. (2002). Personales Leben und menschlicher Tod. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Randall, D., Shneerson, J., & File, S. (2005). Cognitive effects of modafinil in students volunteers may depend on IQ. Pharmachology Biochemistry and Behavior, 82(1), 133–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1988). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Repantis, D., Schlattmann, P., Laisney, O., & Heuser, I. (2010). Modafinil and methylphenidate for neuroanhancement in healthy individuals: A systematic review. Pharmacological Research, 62, 187–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salkever, D. (1995). Updated estimates of earning benefits from reduced exposure of children to environmental lead. Environmental Research, 70(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (2007). The case against perfection. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schermer, M. (2006). On the argument that enhancement is “Cheating”. Journal of Medical Ethics, 34, 85–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schöne-Seifert, B., & Talbot, D. (Eds.). (2009). Enhancement. Die ethische debatte. Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, M. (2002). Does technological enhancement of human traits threaten human equality and democracy? San Diego Law Review, 39, 769–842.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, L., Noll, R., & Mordkoff, D. (2009). Cognitive enhancement in human beings. Gender Medicine, 6(2), 338–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H., & Sunstein, C. R. (2009). Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trnka, J. (2009): The ethics of cognitive enhancement: Is it wrong to take ‘smart drugs’? http://www.academia.edu/2914861/The_Ethics_of_Cognitive_Enhancement. Accessed February 2, 2018.

  • Whalley, L., & Deary, I. (2001). Longitudinal cohort study of childhood IQ and survival up to age 76. British Medical Journal, 322, 819–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Loewe .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Loewe, D. (2019). Biolaw, Liberalism and Cognitive Enhancement: Identifying Harms. In: Valdés, E., Lecaros, J. (eds) Biolaw and Policy in the Twenty-First Century. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 78. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-05903-3_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics