Skip to main content

Intentionality – Evolution of a Concept

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 187 Accesses

Abstract

If there is a common theme through the rich diversity of Max Charlesworth’s academic life and works, it is the quest to understand human action as meaningful, significant and subject to interpretation rather than reducible to the explanatory techniques of positivistic science. This orientation is summed up in the philosophical concept of intentionality. Intentionality is a key notion for continental philosophers whose ideas formed the subject-matter of Max’s legendary course in ‘Contemporary European Philosophy’ at Melbourne University and later, of the foundation philosophy programs at Deakin University. The origins of the concept of intentionality are to be found in mediaeval philosophy – another of Max’s teaching areas, and a commitment to intentionality is deeply implicit in his engagement with the religious and the spiritual as well as with ethics.

In this essay I trace the changing conceptions of intentionality in recent philosophy and in doing so, indicate developments within the continental philosophical tradition and its shifting relations with the analytical tradition in Australian philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is the popular slogan used to summarise Simone de Beauvoir’s thesis in Le Deuxième Sexe (1949).

  2. 2.

    The “posthuman” refers to those currents of thought which, following Foucault’s “death of Man” and thinkers like Deleuze, Derrida, and Irigaray, have initiated a critique of the concept of “Man” or “the human” inherited from post-Enlightenment thinking. Posthumanist thinkers and fields of study show how these concepts mask important assumptions and biases relating to gender, race, colonialism, and our relationship to nature including the role of science and technology. They seek new ways of thinking about what it means to be human, enlisting perspectives of those minorities traditionally excluded from our Eurocentric, gendered, and anthropomorphic approaches (Braidotti and Hlavajova 2018).

  3. 3.

    Especially in the form espoused by prominent thinker on this topic, Rosi Braidotti, who argues for a new (posthuman) way of preserving subjectivity without the implicit biases (Braidotti 2013, p.12).

  4. 4.

    Smith and McIntyre (1982), Mohanty (1982), and Harney (1984).

  5. 5.

    For example, “it is necessary that…” These are said to be intensional contexts – characterised by failure of substitutivity salva veritate. See Caston 2001, for entailment patterns that are violated by intensionality.

  6. 6.

    See, for example, Siewert 2011.

  7. 7.

    For present purposes, I am confining the discussion to Avicenna’s theory of perception with particular reference to his account of the estimative faculty (wahm) and intention (ma‘nā) as these are developed mainly in his Al-Najat (Avicenna 1952) and his Al-Shifā (Avicenna 1959). Averroës, along with others contested many of Avicenna’s ideas including the status and scope of the estimative faculty. A full discussion of these debates is beyond the scope of this paper.

  8. 8.

    Other inner senses include the common sense (sensis communis) responsible for integrating the individual sensations such as touching and seeing into a unity; imaginative power (imaginativa), imagination (phantasia), and memory (memoria).

  9. 9.

    Wahm is a highly contentious notion which stimulated lively debates amongst Avicenna’s contemporaries, and continues to do so in contemporary scholarship.

  10. 10.

    McGinnis (2010, pp.97–99) also adopts this terminology.

  11. 11.

    There are, of course, developments of this in scholarly research as well. See in particular, Hoffmeyer 2012.

  12. 12.

    Sheets-Johnstone (2010, p. 219) points out: “Husserl wrote of action, but he did not write of active or enactive organisms; he wrote of bodies, but he did not write of embodied organisms…”

References

  • Aristotle. (1961). De anima. Edited, with introduction and commentary by W. D. Ross. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avicenna. (1952). Psychology (Kitāb Al-Najat Book Two, Chapter VI) (F. Rahman, Trans.). London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avicenna. (1959). De anima. Being the psychological part of Kitāb Al-Shifā’ (F. Rahman, Ed.). London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (1993). Estimation (Wahm) in Avicenna: The logical and psychological dimensions. Dialogue, XXXII, 219–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (2004). Psychology: soul and intellect. In Peter Adamson & Richard C. Taylor (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Arabic philosophy (pp. 308–326). Cambridge companions to philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (2010). Intentionality in mediæval Arabic philosophy. Quaestio, 10, 65–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braidotti, R. (2013). The Posthuman. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braidotti, R., & Hlavajova, M. (Eds.). (2018). Posthuman glossary. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1973) [1874]. Psychology from an empirical standpoint (C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and Linda McAlister, Trans.) (from the second edition, of 1924) (first edition, 1874.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (2001). Connecting traditions: Augustine and the Greeks on intentionality. In D. Perler (Ed.), Ancient and medieval theories of intentionality (pp. 23–48). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Beauvoir, S. (1949). Le Deuxième Sexe (The second sex). Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernst, G. (2014). Tommaso Campanella. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition). (Edward N. Zalta, Ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/campanella/. Accessed 27 Aug 2016.

  • Føllesdal, D. (1969). Husserl’s notion of the noema. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 680–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1970) [1892]. On sense and reference (Uber Sinn und Bedeutung). Translated by M. Black. In P. T. Geach & M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 56–78). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendlin, E. T. (2012). Line by line commentary on Aristotle’s De Anima (Books I, II and III). Spring Valley: The Focusing Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harney, M. J. (1984). Intentionality sense and the mind. The Hague: Dordrecht Martinus-Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harney, M. (2015). Naturalizing phenomenology – A philosophical imperative. Journal of Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 19(2). Special theme issue on Integral Biomathics. Guest edited by P. Simeonov, S. Rosen and A. Gare.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasse, D. (2000). Avicenna’s De anima in the Latin West. London: Warburg Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller-Roazen, D. (2007). The inner touch: Archaeology of a sensation. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2012). The natural history of intentionality: A biosemiotic approach. In T. Schilhab, F. Stjernfelt, & T. Deacon (Eds.), The symbolic species evolved (Biosemiotics 6) (pp. 97–116). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1965 [1910–1911]). Philosophy as rigorous science. In Phenomenology and the crisis of philosophy (Quentin Lauer, Trans.). New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1969 [1913]. Ideen I (Ideas). (W. R. Boyce Gibson, Trans.). London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998). Intentionality and sensation. In Discovering existence with Husserl (pp. 135–150). Edited, and chapter translated by, Richard A. Cohen and Michael B. Smith. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinnis, J. (2010). Avicenna. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (Phénoménologie de la perception) (Colin Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The visible and the invisible (Le visible et l’invisible). Edited by Claude Leforte, translated by Alphonso Lingis. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Nature: course notes from the Collège de France. (La nature: notes, cours du Collège de France, Paris: Gallimard, 1995.) Compiled with notes by Dominique Séglard (Robert Vallier, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern Unversity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohanty, J. N. (1982). Husserl and Frege. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahman, F. (1952). Avicenna’s psychology. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seager, W., & Bourget, D. (2007). Representationalism about consciousness. In M. Velmans & S. Schneider (Eds.), Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 261–276). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2010). Body and movement: Basic dynamic principles. In S. Gallagher & D. Schmicking (Eds.), Handbook of phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 217–234). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Siewert, C. (2011). Consciousness and intentionality. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition) (Edward N. Zalta, Ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/consciousness-intentionality/

  • Smith, D. W., & McIntyre, R. (1982). Husserl and intentionality: A study of mind, meaning, and language. Dordrecht/Boston: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. (1957) [1934]. A stroll through the worlds of animals and men. In Instinctive behavior: The development of a modern concept (pp. 5–80). Edited and translated by Claire H. Schiller. New York: International Universities Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maurita Harney .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Harney, M. (2019). Intentionality – Evolution of a Concept. In: Wong, P., Bloor, S., Hutchings, P., Bilimoria, P. (eds) Considering Religions, Rights and Bioethics: For Max Charlesworth. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 30. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18148-2_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics