Skip to main content

General Conclusion: What Can Social Science Practitioners Learn from Philosophies of Science?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Social Philosophy of Science for the Social Sciences

Part of the book series: Theory and History in the Human and Social Sciences ((THHSS))

  • 1005 Accesses

Abstract

This volume was born in a six-semester collective teaching effort in Norway, but its implications go far beyond the mundane expectations of a “mandatory course” on philosophy of science to any cohort of social science aspirants for Ph.D. degrees. What is at stake in our twenty-first century is the new nature of knowledge construction in the social sciences—where the input from different social power holders into the kinds of knowledge our sciences create becomes increasingly immediate. This normative control is put into practice by rapid growth of the administrative structures of universities, the role of which is to exercise control over the actions of researchers via the legitimate guarantees of the rightful expenditure of research grant funds and protection of the rights of the human research participants. Researchers themselves also contribute to this social guidance of their work—by accepting the administrative demands to publish in “Scopus-listed” journals of “high impact factor.” The main results from the volume are brought together into the proof that social sciences need philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The invention of new administrative frameworks for the highest study level in our twenty-first-century—doctoral—“schools” is an indication of administrative takeover of control of the social construction of potential new knowledge that is happening all over the world in universities at our twenty-first century (see Valsiner, Lutsenko, & Antoniouk, 2018). The introduction of mandatory units for aspirants toward their highest degrees in university is an example of turning the realm of intellectual inquiries into that of socially enforced transfer of knowledge. Needless to add that the very first act I undertook as coordinator of the seminars in Oslo over the six semesters was to make certain that—aside from the formal “mandatory” status—the seminars were free of such administrative straightjacket.

  2. 2.

    For Kepler any curved line was a version of the tension of two opposites—zero curve (straight line) and full curve (circle). This oppositional unity was elaborated into another kind of unity of subsuming the straight line as a part of the curvature only in the nineteenth century—in the Riemann-Lobachevsky synthesis of geometry—that the unity of linear and curvilinear forms became established by including the less general (line) in the more general (circle). That eliminated the oppositional tension that Kepler—based on alchemy’s symbolic transformations stemming from opposites—was conceptualizing. In terms of basic meta-codes, the contrast between non-oppositional (monological) and oppositional (dialogical) worldviews remains present in the Wissenschaft over the past five centuries providing rise to harmony-based in contrast to tension-based theoretical constructions.

  3. 3.

    From their axiomatic perspective of maintaining such unity in order to make sense of human beings in general, the twentieth and beyond centuries’ practices in psychology of “measuring” gender differences would have made no sense. In their selection of meta-codes, this way the investigators four centuries ago were ahead of our contemporary psychology in their direction of where the knowledge construction should proceed. Of course they had no solutions to the question of how human beings operate.

References

  • Aakvaag, G. (2019). Fragmented and critical? Reflections on the institutional infrastructure and intellectual ambitions of Norwegian sociology. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asquith, P. (2000). Negotiating science: Internationalization and Japanese primatology. In S. C. Strum & L. M. Fedigan (Eds.), Primate encounters (pp. 165–183). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bachelard, G. (2002). The formation of the scientific mind. Manchester, UK: Clinaman Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Branco, A. U., & Valsiner, J. (1997). Changing methodologies: A co-constructivist study of goal orientations in social interactions. Psychology and Developing Societies, 9(1), 35–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brinkmann, S. (2019). Normativity in psychology and the social sciences: Questions of universality. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carré, D. (2019). Social sciences, what for? On the manifold directions of social research. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen-Morris, R. (2009). From emblems to diagrams: Kepler’s new pictorial language of scientific representation. Renaissance Quarterly, 62(1), 134–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devereux, G. (1967). From anxiety to method in the behavioral sciences. The Hague, The Netherlands: Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (1991). From tools to theories: A heuristic discovery in cognitive psychology. Psychological Review, 98, 254–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karpenko, V. (2016). A path to the Rudolphine world. In I. Purs & V. Karpenko (Eds.), Alchemy and Rudolf II: Exploring the secrets of nature in Central Europe in the 16th and 17th centuries (pp. 19–46). Prague: Artifactum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lind, J.-T. (2019). How do economists think? In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindstad, T. G., Stänicke, E., & Valsiner, J. (Eds.). (2019). Respect for reasoning: Jan Smedslund’s legacy in psychology. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lundh, L.-G. (2019). The crisis in psychological science, and the need for a person-oriented approach. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, M. (1618). Alalanta fugiens hoc est, Emblemata Nova de secretis naturae ae chymica. Oppenheim, Germany: Hieronimii Galleri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malnes, R. (2019). Explanation: Guidance for social scientists. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ohnuki-Tierney, E. (1989). The monkey as mirror: Symbolic transformations in Japanese history and ritual. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reber, R., & Bullot, N. (2019). Conditional objectivism: A strategy for connecting the social sciences and practical decision-making. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salvatore, S., & Valsiner, J. (2010). Between the general and the unique: Overcoming the nomothetic versus idiographic opposition. Theory & Psychology, 20(6), 817–833.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinha, D., & Tripathi, R. C. (1994). Individualism in a collectivist culture: A case of coexistence of opposites. In U. Kim, H. Triandis, C. Kagitcibasi, S.-C. Choi, & G. Yoon (Eds.), Individualism and collectivism (pp. 123–136). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1995). Psychologic: Common sense and the pseudoempirical. In J. A. Smith, R. Harre, & L. van Langenhove (Eds.), Rethinking psychology (pp. 196–206). London, UK: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smedslund, J. (1997). The structure of psychological common sense. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strand, R. (2019). Vitenskapsteori – what, why and how? In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (2009). Integrating psychology within the globalizing world: A requiem to the post-modernist experiment with Wissenschaft. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 43(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (2018). Needed in psychology: Theoretical precision. Europe’s Journal of Psychology, 14(1), 1–6. https://doi.org/10.5964/ejop.v14i1.602

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (2019a). Social sciences between knowledge and ideologies: Need for philosophy. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (2019b). From causality to catalysis in the social sciences. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J., Lutsenko, A., & Antoniouk, A. (Eds.). (2018). Sustainable futures for higher education: The making of knowledge makers. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watzl, S. (2019). Culture or biology? If this sounds interesting, you might be confused. In J. Valsiner (Ed.), Social philosophy of science for the social sciences. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. London, UK: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yurevich, A. V (2009) Cognitive frames in psychology: Demarcations and ruptures. IPBS: Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science 43, 89–103

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Valsiner, J. (2019). General Conclusion: What Can Social Science Practitioners Learn from Philosophies of Science?. In: Valsiner, J. (eds) Social Philosophy of Science for the Social Sciences. Theory and History in the Human and Social Sciences. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-33099-6_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics