Skip to main content

The Challenge of Experimental Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Thought Experiments
  • 391 Accesses

Abstract

We have briefly mentioned some criticisms of TEs, and tried to defend TEs from them. In this chapter we focus on a recent critical movement, the so called “experimental philosophy”, X-phi for short that has been in the center of discussion of TEs in the last two decades.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See a fine overview in Mortensen and Nagel (2016:53–71).

  2. 2.

    For a recent overview see the section “Philosophy of Science” in Sytsma and Buckwalter (eds.) (2016).

  3. 3.

    For a useful overview of huge literature on the topic see Buckwalter (2016) (eds.).

  4. 4.

    For a relatively recent list of problems by Alexander et al. (2010).

  5. 5.

    The pioneering works are Weinberg et al. (2001), Nichols et al. (2003a, b), Machery et al. (2004).

  6. 6.

    The main early sources are Haidt (2001), Nichols (2004), Nichols and Knobe (2007), Prinz 2007 (recently summarized in Stich and Tobia (2018:374)).

  7. 7.

    For more see Cova (2016) and Björnsson and Pereboom (2016).

  8. 8.

    For recent short summary see Stich and Tobia (2018:374).

  9. 9.

    A different study by the same authors (Nichols et al. 2003a, b) reported that the number of philosophy courses subjects had taken was a factor in influencing their responses. Subjects who had taken a number of philosophy courses were more susceptible to skeptical arguments than those who had taken fewer.

  10. 10.

    See for instance recent surveys in Greene (2016) and Justin W. Martin and Fiery Cushman The Adaptive Logic of Moral Luck (2016).

  11. 11.

    Some of the more recent comments by X-philosophers are less dramatic. For instance, Stephen Stich and Kevin Tobia recently offered a more modest proposal:

    The skepticism about the use of intuitions as evidence (…) should be directed primarily at intuitions that have been shown to be susceptible to irrelevant influences, and at other intuitions that are the product of psychological mechanisms that are likely to be vulnerable in similar ways. And which are these? The answer is that at this point we do not know, and we are not going to find out without a great deal more sophisticated work in psychology and neuroscience. On our view, this sort of research should be viewed as quite central to experimental philosophy. So the take-home message from this chapter is not that intuitions should not be used as evidence in philosophy. Rather, it is that experimental philosophy, broadly construed, has a crucial role to play in assessing and improving philosophical methodology (2018:379).

  12. 12.

    Here is his complete Argument from dogmatism:

    1. 1.

      Most of the philosophical cases examined by experimental philosophers elicit disagreement.

    2. 2.

      This disagreement takes place among epistemic peers.

    3. 3.

      If most of the philosophical cases examined by experimental philosophers elicit disagreement among peers, then most philosophical cases would plausibly elicit disagreement among peers.

    4. 4.

      If epistemic peers are likely to disagree about a philosophical case, they ought to suspend judgment about it.

    5. 5.

      Hence, except for those philosophical cases known not to elicit disagreement among peers, philosophers ought to suspend judgment about the situations described by philosophical cases (2017:128).

  13. 13.

    Here is his Argument from parochialism:

    1. 1.

      When people respond differently to the philosophical cases examined by experimental philosophers, it is because they refer to different (epistemic, moral, etc.) properties.

    2. 2.

      If people refer to different (epistemic, moral, etc.) properties when they respond differently to the philosophical cases examined by experimental philosophers, they would plausibly do so in response to most philosophical cases.

    3. 3.

      Philosophers are not justified in believing that theorizing about the (epistemic, moral, etc.) properties they refer to will allow them to achieve their philosophical goals.

    4. 4.

      You ought not to decide to φ in order to ψ if you believe you are not justified to believe that φ-ing is likely to bring about ψ.

    5. 5.

      Hence, philosophers ought to focus on determining whether theorizing about the (epistemic, moral, etc.) properties they refer to or about the (epistemic, moral, etc.) properties others refer to will allow them to reach their philosophical goals, stopping for the time being their theorizing about the (epistemic, moral, etc.) properties they refer to.

    6. 6.

      Hence, for the time being, philosophers should not appeal to the method of cases (2017:140).

  14. 14.

    And one more:

    […] philosophical education (…) is supposed to improve far more mundane skills, such as careful attention to details in the description of the scenario and their potential relevance to the questions at issue (Ibid.).

  15. 15.

    For instance, Jackson notes the following:

    Physicists aren’t being chauvinists when they tell us which ways of categorizing systems of particles are important. They are doing their job. Part of our job—the job of philosophers—is to assess which concepts in, for example, epistemology are theoretically important, to delineate the connections between various concepts, and to identify the questions worth asking. 2011.480.

    Here it is worth recalling the history of probabilistic reasoning. Early folk concepts were progressively refined. (…) Polls are relevant to the elucidation of one or another folk concept relating to our uses of terms like ‘expect’ and ‘believe likely’. They are not relevant to the assessment of the edifice of probabilistic reasoning that informs current statistics. This is why the ‘they are wrong’ response is the correct one to those who commit the gambler’s fallacy. We can think of philosophical work in epistemology as aiming to build on some of the same folk materials, with the aim of producing a finished theory (a theory which of course will incorporate probabilistic ways of thinking). Polls won’t be relevant to assessing the final product (Ibid).

  16. 16.

    To quote a recent title of the book by Inmaculada de Melo-Martín and Kristen Intemann published in 2018 by Oxford University Press.

  17. 17.

    For more recent development see Sosa (2017).

  18. 18.

    For another kind of pragmatic considerations see Sytsma and Livengood (2011). See also Adams and Steadman (2004) and Driver (2008).

  19. 19.

    The issue of understanding is now being made prominent in several lines of discussions, that go beyond the discussion in experimental philosophy, where theorists often use procedures from the methodology of psychology in order to control variables that might influence subject’s understanding of the question.

    For logical intuitions the famous issue is subjects’ understanding of everyday words for logical constants, most famously “if…then”; is it conditional and biconditional and if the first, what kind of conditional (see chapters Four and Five of Stenning and Lambalgen (2008).

    Concerning arithmetical intuitions there has been a recent intriguing debate about a Brazilian Indian tribe whose members were described as being unable to place objects from even two small bunches in one–one correlation: the researcher took it as a very significant result since the tribe also seems to lack numerals/number words. Others accused him of simply having misunderstood his subjects. See Everett and Madora (2012) For linguistic intuitions a famous, not to say notorious issue is whether illiterate subjects indeed have grammatical intuitions at all see Schütze (1986).

  20. 20.

    See Baz (2012). Baz in his paper also has interesting things to say about the ways semantic/pragmatic distinction is relevant in the Gettier context.

  21. 21.

    An earlier attempt to compare X-phi and theories of bounded rationality is to be found in Buon et al. (2013) “A non-mentalistic cause-based heuristic in human social evaluations”, Cognition 126 149–155.

    I have profited a lot from discussion with one of the authors, Pierre, and I thank him for this!

  22. 22.

    This is, of course, just a beginning. There has been much work done on compatibilism and incompatibilism as represented by folk intuition; we cannot go into it here. See, for instance Nahmias et al. (2005, 2006), and Chan et al. (2016).

  23. 23.

    In short, in light of suggesting that the ideal moral enquirer consider all reasonable arguments, the method of reflective equilibrium fails to Adjudicate the central controversies within moral methodology. Rather, it in effect absorbs all such controversies, as inputs. This undercuts any claim that the method provides an informative answer to pressing methodological questions in ethics. Note that this is true even holding as fixed Rawls’ project of moral theory; how we should proceed if and when we attempt to move from moral theory to actually defending answers to ethical questions is even less clear 2015:661.

  24. 24.

    See also Rédei (2003).

References

  • Adams F, Steadman A (2004) Intentional action in ordinary language: core concept, pragmatic understanding? Analysis 64(282):173–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander J (2016) Thought experiments, mental modeling, and experimental philosophy. In: Nado J (ed) Advances in experimental philosophy and philosophical methodology. Bloomsbury Academic, London, pp 53–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander J, Mallon R, Weinberg JM (2010) Accentuate the Negative. In: Knobe J, Nichols S (Eds) Experimental philosophy: Volume 2. Oxford University Press, New York (2014), first published in Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1(2):297–314 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson D (2003) Experiments and thought experiments in natural science. In: Galavotti MC (ed) Observation and experiment in the natural and social sciences. Springer Verlag, Switzerland, pp 209–225

    Google Scholar 

  • Baz A (2012) Must philosophers rely on intuitions? J Philos 109(4):316–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Björnsson G, Pereboom D (2006) Traditional and experimental approaches to free will and moral responsibility. In: Sytsma J, Buckwalter W (eds) A companion to experimental philosophy. Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp 142–171

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter W (2016) Experimental philosophy, Oxford Bibliographies Online. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Buon M, Jacob P, Loissel E, Dupoux E (2013) A non-mentalistic cause-based heuristic in human social evaluations. Cognition 126:149–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chan H-Y, Deutsch M, Nichols S (2016) Free will and experimental philosophy. In: Sytsma J, Buckwalter W (eds) A Companion to Experimental Philosophy, Blackwell, pp 158–172

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1985) Reduction, qualia and the direct introspection of brain states. J Philos 82(January):8–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Cova F (2016) The folk concept of intentional action: empirical approaches. In: Sytsma J, Buckwalter W (eds) A companion to experimental philosophy, Blackwell, pp 121–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Cullen S (2010) Survey-Driven Romanticism. Rev Philos Psychol 1(2):275–296

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver J (2008) Attributions of causation and moral responsibility. In: Sinnott-Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology. vol 2. The cognitive science of morality: intuition and diversity. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 423–440

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett C, Madora K (2012) Quantity recognition among speakers of an Anumeric language. Cognit Sci 36(1):130

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene JD (2016) Solving the trolley problem. In: Sytsma J, Buckwalter W (eds), pp 175–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108:814–834

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1982) Epiphenomenal qualia. Philos Quart 32:127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (2011) ‘On Gettier Holdouts’. Mind Lang 26(4):468–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2011) Thinking, fast and slow. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen A (2007) The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philos Explor 10(2):95–118. Reprinted In: Knobe J, Nichols S (eds), Experimental Philosophy, vol 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2014

    Google Scholar 

  • Klampfer F (2017) The false promise of thought-experimentation in moral and political philosophy. In: Borstner B, Gartner S (eds), pp 328–348

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig K (2018) Thought experiments and experimental philosophy. In: Stuart MT, Fehige Y, Brown JR (eds) The routledge companion to thought experiments. Routledge, pp 385–403

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery E (2014) What is the significance of the demographic variation in semantic intuitions? In: Machery E, O’Neill E (eds) Current controversies in experimental philosophy. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery E (2017) Philosophy within its proper bounds. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery E, Mallon R, Nichols S, Stich S (2004) Semantics cross-cultural style. Cognition 92(3):B1–B12

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery E, Stich S, Rose D, Chatterjee A, Karasawa K, Struchiner N, Sirker S, Usui N, Hashimoto T (2016) Gettier across cultures. Noûs 50(4)

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin JW, Cushman W (2016) The adaptive logic of moral luck. In: Sytsma J, Buckwalter W (eds), pp 190–201

    Google Scholar 

  • McPherson T (2015) The methodological irrelevance of reflective equilibrium. In Daly Ch (ed) The palgrave handbook of philosophical methods. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier H, Sperber D (2017) The enigma of reason. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mortensen K, Nagel J (2016) Armchair‐friendly experimental philosophy. In: Sytsma J, Buckwalter W (eds) A companion to experimental philosophy. Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp 53–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias E, Morris S, Nadelhoffer T, Turner J (2005) Surveying freedom: folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility. Philos Psychol 18(5):561–584

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias E, Morris S, Nadelhoffer T, Turner J (2006) “Is incompatibilism intuitive? Res 73(1):28–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian N (2007) Thought experiments as mental modeling. Croatian J Philos 7:125–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Knobe J (2007) Moral responsibility and determinism: the cognitive science of folk intuitions. Nous 41(4):663–685

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Stich S, Weinberg J (2003a) Metaskepticism: meditations in ethno-epistemology. In: Luper S (ed) The skeptics: contemporary debates. Ashgate, Burlington, pp 227–247

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Stich S, Weinberg JM (2003b) Meta-skepticism: meditations in ethno-epistemology. In: Luper S (ed) The skeptics: contemporary essays. Ashgate, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols S, Stich S, Weinberg JM (2012) Meta-skepticism, meditations in ethno-epistemology. In Stephen stich collected papers, Volume 2: Knowledge, rationality, and morality, 1978–2010, first published In Luper S (ed) The Skeptics. Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot, England 2003, pp 227–247

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacock KA (2018) Happiest thoughts great thought experiments of modern physics. In Stuart M, Fehige Y, Brown JR (eds) Routledge companion to thought experiments. Routledge, London, 211–241

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2007) Can moral obligations be empirically discovered?. In: Wettstein H (ed) Midwest studies in philosophy 31

    Google Scholar 

  • Rédei M (2003) Thinking about thought experiments in physics comment on Experiments and thought experiments in natural science. In: Galavotti MC (ed) Observation and experiment in the natural and social sciences. Springer Verlag, Switzerland, pp 237–241

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnall S, Haidt J, Clore GL, Jordan AH (2008) Disgust as embodied moral judgment. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 34(8):1096–1109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schütze CT (1986) The empirical base for linguistics, grammatical judgments and linguistic methodology. The University of Chicago Presss, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen RA (2014) Novice thought experiments. In: Booth AR, Rowbottom DP (eds) Intuitions. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 135–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E (2007) “Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Intuition.” In: Knobe J, Nichols S (eds) Experimental philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E (2009) A defense of the use of intuitions in philosophy. In: Bishop M, Murphy D (eds) Stich and his critics. edited by, Blackwell Publishers, pp 101–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenning K, Lambalgen Mv (2008) Human reasoning and cognitive science, a bradford book. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich S, Tobia K (2018) Intuition and its critics. In: Stuart M, Fehige Y, Brown J (eds) Routledge handbook of thought experiments. Routledge, London, pp 369–383

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich S, Mizumoto M, McCready E (2018) Introduction. In: Stich S, Mizumoto M, McCready E (eds) Epistemology for the rest of the world. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma J, Livengood J (2011) New perspective concerning experiments on semantic intuitions. Australas J Philos 89(2):315–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swain S, Alexander J, Weinberg JM (2008) The instability of philosophical intuitions: running hot and cold on truetemp. Philos Phenomenol Res 76(1 January):138–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabo GT (2010) Intuition, imagination, and philosophical methodology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg JM (2007) How to change intuitions empirically without risking skepticism. Midwest Stud Philos 31 (1):318–343

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg JM, Nichols Sh, Stich S (2001) Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philos Top 29:429–460

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka A (2018) I know a human universal. In: Stich S, Mizumoto M, McCready E (eds) Epistemology for the rest of the world. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 216–246

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2007a) Philosophical knowledge and knowledge of counterfactuals. Grazer Philosophische Studien 74:89–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2007b) The philosophy of philosophy. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2011) ‘Philosophical expertise and the burden of proof’. Metaphilosophy 42(3):215–229

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nenad Miscevic .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Miscevic, N. (2022). The Challenge of Experimental Philosophy. In: Thought Experiments. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-81082-5_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics