Skip to main content

Informal Logic and the Concept of Argument

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1618 Accesses

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 30))

Abstract

Informal logic studies the identification, analysis, evaluation, criticism and construction of arguments. An argument is a set of one or more interlinked premiss-illative-conclusion sequences. Premisses are assertives, not necessarily asserted by anyone. Conclusions can be assertives, directives, declaratives, commissives or expressives. Each can be expressed either in language or by visual images or physically. Two arguments can be linked either by having a conclusion of one as a premiss of the other or by having one as a premiss of the other. A box-arrow system for diagramming arguments thus conceived is illustrated with reference to three expressed arguments; the diagrams show that the diagramming system can handle conditional proof, argument about an arbitrary instance as a proof of a universal generalization, argument by cases, and reductio ad absurdum. A final section lists issues in informal logic and gives some indication of the range of positions taken on these issues.

Bibliographical note: This chapter was first published with the same title in Philosophy of Logic, ed. Dale Jacquette, volume 5 of Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, ed. Dov M. Gabbay, Paul Thagard and John Woods (Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2007), 101–129. © 2007 Elsevier B. V. Republished with permission of Elsevier. I am deeply grateful for comments on an earlier version of this chapter to Lilian Bermejo-Luque , J. Anthony Blair , Inga B. Dolinina , Frans H. van Eemeren , Robert H. Ennis , Bart Garssen , Dale Hample , Ralph H. Johnson , Mike Metcalfe , Leah E. Polcar, Harvey Siegel and John Woods . They saved me from some embarrassing errors, and made useful suggestions. The responsibility for errors that remain is mine. Nor would they all agree with everything asserted in this chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Correction in the present republication: The word ‘single’ replaces ‘simple’.

  2. 2.

    Change in this chapter: For ease of understanding, in the diagram I have replaced the word ‘suppose’ with ‘thenS’ at the beginning of conclusions drawn directly from suppositions. The word ‘then’ signals their status as a conclusion. The superscripted ‘S’ signals their inheritance of a suppositional status from a premiss.

  3. 3.

    Added in the present republication: One might wonder how this conclusion follows, and might be inclined to strengthen the supposition so as to make the inference more plausible, but that is interpretation rather than the faithful analysis illustrated here.

  4. 4.

    Change in the present republication: For ease of understanding, in the diagram I have replaced the word ‘suppose’ with ‘thenS’ at the beginning of conclusions drawn directly from suppositions. The word ‘then’ signals their status as a conclusion. The superscripted ‘S’ signals their inheritance of a suppositional status from a premiss.

  5. 5.

    Added in the present republication: The reader might wonder how such a piece of suppositional reasoning can be an argument and how it can be a premiss. It counts as an argument because Anselm (in this translation*) explicitly uses the illative ‘then’ to indicate that he is drawing a conclusion from what he has just supposed. It counts as a premiss because anything put forward in support of a conclusion is a premiss and Anselm puts this piece of suppositional reasoning forward in support of a conclusion. The western logical tradition has not counted suppositional reasoning used to support a further claim as a premiss, but only tradition counts against doing so. In chapter 32, where I revise the definition of argument developed in the present chapter, I no longer call suppositional reasoning used to support a claim a premiss, but instead speak of it as adduced in support of the claim. The new terminology bows to the traditional reluctance to allow that an argument can be a premiss, but the basic idea is still the same.

    *The translation is in this respect unfaithful. A more faithful translation would read: “For if indeed it exists in the understanding alone, it can be conceived to exist also in reality.” (Latin: Si enim vel in solo intellectu est, potest cogitari esse et in re.) Thus the embedded suppositional reasoning turns out to be an artifact of the translation rather than part of the structure of what Anselm wrote. There are real-life examples of suppositional reasoning used to support a conditional claim, such as some rather technical arguments in mathematics.

References

  • Anselm, Saint. 1903. Proslogium; Monologium: An appendix in behalf of the fool by Gaunilo; and Cur deus homo, translated from the Latin by Sidney Norton Deane, B.A. with an introduction, bibliography, and reprints of the opinions of leading philosophers and writers on the ontological argument. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1984. The complete works of Aristotle, 2 vols., the revised Oxford translation edited by Jonathan Barnes. Bollingen Series LXXI: 2. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beardsley, Monroe C. 1950. Practical logic. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J. Anthony. 2004. Argument and its uses. Informal Logic 24: 137–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J. Anthony, and Ralph H. Johnson. 1987. The current state of informal logic. Informal Logic 9: 147–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano, Bernard. 1985–1989. Wissenschaftslehre, ed. Jan Berg, vols. 11-13 of his Schriften. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann. First published in 1837.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diogenes Laertius. 1925. Lives of eminent philosophers, with an English translation by R. D. Hicks. 2 vols. Loeb Classical Library numbers 184 and 185. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. First published ca. 210–240 CE.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, Frans H., and Rob Grootendorst. 1984. Speech acts in argumentative discussions: A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Dordrecht-Holland/ Cinnaminson-USA: Foris Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, Frans H., and Rob Grootendorst. 1992. Argumentation, communication and fallacies: A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, Frans H., and Rob Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehninger, Douglas, and Wayne Brockriede. 1963. Decision by debate. New York: Dodd, Mead.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ennis, Robert H. 1982. Identifying implicit assumptions. Synthese 51: 61–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Euclid. 1969–1973. Elementa, vols. 1-4, ed. E. S. Stamatis (post J.L. Heiberg), 2nd edition. Leipzig: Teubner. First published ca. 300 BCE. Accessed via the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Richard. 1994. Good arguments. In Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge, ed. Frederick F Schmitt, 159–188. Lanham, MD, Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro, Maurice A. 1980. Galileo and the art of reasoning: Rhetorical foundations of logic and scientific method. Boston: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, James B. 1991. Dialectics and the macrostructure of arguments: A theory of argument structure. Berlin: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelder, Tim J. van. 2004. Reason!Able. Available at http://timvangelder.com/software . Visited 2016 01 21.

  • George, Rolf. 1983. Bolzano’s consequence, relevance, and enthymemes. Journal of Philosophical Logic 12: 299–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Michael A. 1997. Coalescent argumentation. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin I. 1999. Knowledge in a social world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, Trudy. 1987. Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Studies of Argumentation in Pragmatics and Discourse Analysis, 5. Dordrecht: Mouton de Gruyter/Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, Trudy. 2005. A practical study of argument, 6th edition. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. Previous editions published 1985, 1988, 1992, 1997, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grennan, Wayne. 1997. Informal logic: Issues and approaches. Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, Leo. 1996. Logic, art and argument. Informal Logic 18: 116–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, Charles L. 1970. Fallacies. New York: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, Hans V., and Robert C. Pinto. 1995. Fallacies: Classical and contemporary readings. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hastings, Arthur C. 1962. A reformulation of the modes of reasoning in argumentation, Ph.D. dissertation, Northwestern University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, Jaakko. 1987. The fallacy of fallacies. Argumentation 1: 211–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, David. 2002. The practice of argumentative discussion. Argumentation 16: 287–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Ralph H. 2000. Manifest rationality: A pragmatic theory of argument. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Ralph H. 2002. Manifest rationality reconsidered: reply to my fellow symposiasts. Argumentation 16: 311–331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Ralph H., and J. Anthony Blair. 1993. Logical self-defense, 3rd edition. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson. First edition published 1977, 2nd edition 1983, 1st U.S. edition 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Ralph H., and J. Anthony Blair. 2000. Informal logic: an overview. Informal Logic 20: 93–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kienpointner, Manfred. 1992. Alltagslogik: Struktur und Funktion von Argumentationsmustern. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzbog.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kneale, William C., and Martha Kneale. 1962. The development of logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krabbe, Erik C.W. 1992. So what? Profiles for relevance criticism in persuasion dialogues. Argumentation 6: 271–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krabbe, Erik C.W. 1999. Profiles of dialogue. In JFAK: Essays Dedicated to Johan van Benthem on the Occasion of his 50th Birthday, III, ed. Jelle Gerbrandy, Maarten Marx. Maarten de Rijke, and Yde Venema, 25–36. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, Chaim, and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1958. La nouvelle rhétorique. Traité de l’argumentation. Bruxelles: Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, Chaim, and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1969. The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation, trans. John Wilkinson and Purcell Weaver. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, Robert C. 2001a. Argument, inference and dialectic: Collected papers on informal logic with an introduction by Hans V. Hansen. Dordrecht/ Boston/ London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, Robert C. 2001b. Generalizing the notion of argument. In Pinto 2001a, pp. 10–20. First published in Proceedings of the Second International Conference on Argumentation, vol. 1A, ed. Frans H. van Eemeren, Rob Grootendorst, J. Anthony Blair and Charles Willard, 137-146. Amsterdam: SICSAT, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, Robert C. 2001c. The relation of argument to inference. In Pinto 2001a, pp. 32–45. First published in Perspectives and approaches: Proceedings of the Third International Conference on Argumentation, vol. 1, ed. Frans H. van Eemeren, Rob Grootendorst, J. Anthony Blair, and Charles Willard, 271-286. Amsterdam: SICSAT, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantin, Christian. 2003. Argumentation studies in France: a new legitimacy. In Anyone Who Has a View: Theoretical Contributions to the Study of Argument, ed. Frans H. van Eemeren, J. Anthony Blair, Charles A. Willard, and A. Francisca Snoeck Henkemans, 173–187. Dordrecht/ Boston/ London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1997. Complete works, edited, with introduction and notes, by John Cooper, associate editor, D. S. Hutchinson. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, Chris, and Glenn Rowe. 2005. Araucaria Version 3.1. Available at http://araucaria.en.malavida.com/. Visited 2016 01 21.

  • Rolf, Bertil, and Charlotte Magnusson. 2002. Athena Standard 2.7. http://www.bertilrolf.com/index/Argument_Software.html; accessed 2016 08 12.

  • Searle, John R. 1979. Expression and meaning: Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sextus Empiricus. 1935. Against the logicians, trans. R. G. Bury. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. First published ca. 180–200 CE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, Harvey, and John Biro. 1997. Epistemic normativity, argumentation, and fallacies. Argumentation 11: 277–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. Francisca. 1992. Analyzing complex argumentation. PhD dissertation, University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Stephen N. 1977. Practical reasoning in natural language, 1st edition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, Stephen Edelston. 1958. The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vorobej, Mark. 1994. The TRUE test of linkage. Informal Logic 16: 147–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vorobej, Mark. 1995. Hybrid arguments. Informal Logic 17: 289–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas N. 1990. What is reasoning? What is an argument? Journal of Philosophy 87: 399–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas N. 1996a. Argument structure: A pragmatic theory. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas N. 1996b. Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas N. 1998. Ad hominem arguments. Tuscaloosa and London: University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Douglas N., and Erik C. W. Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in dialogue: Basic concepts of interpersonal reasoning. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, Carl. 1971. Challenge and response: Justification in ethics. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenzel, Joseph W. 1980. Three perspectives on argument: Rhetoric, dialectic, logic. In Perspectives on argumentation: Essays in honor of Wayne Brockriede, ed. Robert Trapp and Janice Schuetz, 9–26. Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whately, Richard. 1848. Elements of logic, 9th edition. London: Longmans. First edition published 1826.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, John, and Douglas N. Walton. 1989. Fallacies: Selected papers 1972–1982. Dordrecht, Holland and Providence, RI: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Hitchcock .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hitchcock, D. (2017). Informal Logic and the Concept of Argument. In: On Reasoning and Argument. Argumentation Library, vol 30. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53562-3_29

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics