Skip to main content

Rational-Choice Models of Political Behavior vs. Functionalist and Conformist Theories

  • Chapter
Essays on Ethics, Social Behavior, and Scientific Explanation

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library ((TDLU,volume 12))

  • 269 Accesses

Abstract

After a virtual neglect for several decades, in the last twenty years renewed interest has been shown in a general theory of social behavior. Most of this theoretical work has depended on two main postulates. One is the functionalist (sometimes called structural-functional) approach to the explanation of social institutions, based on the assumption that the social institutions of a given society can best be understood in terms of their social functions, that is, in terms of the contributions they make to the maintenance of social systems as a whole. For lack of an established technical term, we shall call the other postulate the conformist approach to the explanation of individual behavior, it is based on the assumption that uniformities of individual behavior in a given society can best be understood in terms of certain commonly accepted social values, which most members of the society tend to internalize during their socialization process.

World Politics, 21 (1969), 513–538. The author wishes to express his gratitude to the National Science Foundation, which has supported this research by grant GS-722, administered through the University of California Center for Research in Management Science. This paper was presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association in Chicago, September, 1967. The author wishes to express his thanks for the comments received.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (Glencoe, Ill. 1949);

    Google Scholar 

  2. Talcott Parsons, The Social System (Glencoe, Ill. 1951);

    Google Scholar 

  3. Talcott Parsons, Essays in Sociological Theory (Glencoe, Ill. 1954);

    Google Scholar 

  4. Talcott Parsons, Structure and Process in Modern Societies (Glencoe, Ill. 1961).

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Gabriel Almond, ‘Comparative Political Systems’, Journal of Politics, XVIII, (Aug. 1956), 391–409;

    Google Scholar 

  6. Marion J. Levy Jr., The Structure of Society (Princeton 1952);

    Google Scholar 

  7. R. K. Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure (New York 1957);

    Google Scholar 

  8. William C. Mitchell, The American Polity (New York 1962) and

    Google Scholar 

  9. William C. Mitchell, Sociological Analysis and Politics (Englewood Cliffs, N.J. 1967);

    Google Scholar 

  10. A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, Structure and Function in Primitive Society (Glencoe, Ill. 1952), etc.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See, e.g., James S. Coleman, ‘Comment on ‘On the Concept of Influence,’’ The Public Opinion Quarterly, XXVII (Spring 1963), 63–92;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Ralf Dahrendorf, ‘Out of Utopia: Toward a Reorientation of Sociological Analysis’, American Journal of Sociology, LXIV (September 1958), 115–27;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society (Stanford 1959);

    Google Scholar 

  14. Alvin Gouldner, ‘Some Observations on Systematic Theory, 1945–55’, in Hans L. Zetterberg, ed., Sociology in the United States (Paris, 1956);

    Google Scholar 

  15. Alvin Gouldner, ‘Reciprocity and Autonomy in Functional Theory’, in Llewellyn Gross, ed., Symposium on Sociological Theory (New York 1959);

    Google Scholar 

  16. John C. Harsanyi, ‘Explanation and Comparative Dynamics in Social Science’, Behavioral Science, V (April 1960), 136–45,

    Google Scholar 

  17. John C. Harsanyi, ‘A Bargaining Model for Social Status in Informal Groups and Formal Organizations’, Behavioral Science XI (September 1966), 357–69,

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. John C. Harsanyi, ‘Individualistic versus Functionalistic Explanations in the Light of Game Theory’, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave, eds., Problems in the Philosophy of Science (Amsterdam 1967);

    Google Scholar 

  19. Carl G. Hempel, ‘The Logic of Functional Analysis’, in Llewellyn Gross, ed., Symposium on Sociological Theory (New York 1959);

    Google Scholar 

  20. George C. Homans, ‘Contemporary Theory in Sociology’, in Robert E. L. Faris, ed., Handbook of Modern Sociology (Chicago 1964);

    Google Scholar 

  21. David Lockwood, ‘Some Remarks on ‘The Social System’,’ British Journal of Sociology VII (June 1956), 134–46;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. John Rex, Key Problems of Sociological Theory (London 1961).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Dahrendorf, 127, has argued that we cannot use the same theoretical model to analyze social conflicts and to analyze social consensus or cooperation. In actual fact, as modern game theory has shown in analyzing games with mixed interests (where the players’ interests are similar in some respects and are dissimilar in other respects), the same theoretical model can handle both conflict and cooperation without any difficulty.

    Google Scholar 

  25. The von Neumann-Morgenstern approach to game theory does not yield determinate predictions for two-person non-zero-sum games and for n-person games, the two game classes most important for social science applications. John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton 1944). But later work has overcome this difficulty.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See, e.g. John C. Harsanyi, ‘Bargaining and Conflict Situations in the Light of a New Approach to Game Theory’, American Economic Review, LV (May 1965), 447–57 and

    Google Scholar 

  27. See, e.g. John C. Harsanyi, ‘A General Theory of Rational Behavior in Game Situations’, Econometrica, XXXIV (July 1966), 613–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. See e.g., Herbert A. Simon, Administrative Behavior (New York 1957),

    Google Scholar 

  29. See e.g., Herbert A. Simon, Models of Man (New York 1957),

    Google Scholar 

  30. See e.g., Herbert A. Simon, ‘The Executive as Decision Maker’, in H. A. Simon, The Shape of Automation (New York 1965),

    Google Scholar 

  31. See e.g., Herbert A. Simon, ‘Political Research: The Decision-Making Framework’, in David Eas-ton, ed., Varieties of Political Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J. 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  32. In fairness to traditional ‘interest theories’, before the emergence of modern game theory the analytical tools needed for answering some of these questions were simply not available.

    Google Scholar 

  33. For example, Duncan Black, The Theory of Committees and Elections (Cambridge 1958);

    Google Scholar 

  34. James M. Buchanan and Gordon Tullock, The Calculus of Consent (Ann Arbor 1962);

    Google Scholar 

  35. James S. Coleman, ‘Collective Decisions’, Sociological Inquiry, XXXIV (Spring 1964), 166–81;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. John C. Harsanyi, ‘Measurement of Social Power, Opportunity Costs, and the Theory of Two-Person Bargaining Games’, Behavioral Science, VII (January 1962), 67–80,

    Google Scholar 

  37. John C. Harsanyi, ‘Measurement of Social Power in n-Person Reciprocal Power Situations’, Behavioral Science, VII (January 1962), 81–91,

    Google Scholar 

  38. John C. Harsanyi, ‘Models for the Analysis of the Balance of Power in Society’, in the Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science (Stanford 1962), 442–62;

    Google Scholar 

  39. Morton Kaplan, System and Process in International Politics (New York 1957);

    Google Scholar 

  40. Mancur Olson Jr., The Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge, Mass. 1965);

    Google Scholar 

  41. William H. Riker, The Theory of Political Coalitions (New Haven, Conn. 1962), etc. See also

    Google Scholar 

  42. Robert A. Dahl, A Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago 1956);

    Google Scholar 

  43. George C. Homans, Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms (New York 1961); and

    Google Scholar 

  44. J. W. Thibaut and H.H. Kelley, The Social Psychology of Groups (New York 1959). The last three books make no explicit use of formal rational-choice models, but most of their analysis could be easily restated in these terms.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Modern economic theory (often called neoclassical economic theory in contrast to the classical theory) has considerably relaxed this assumption. Though economic self-interest is still regarded as the dominant motive of economic behavior, it is no longer assumed to be the only important motive.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  47. If the number of adjustable parameters of a given theory is as large as (or is even larger than) the number of independent observations available to us, then the fact that the theory is consistent with these observations does not provide a real confirmation for it, because such a theory can always be made consistent with our observations if we choose appropriate numerical values for its parameters. Even if the number of adjustable parameters of the theory is smaller than the number of independent observations, but is only just a little smaller, we cannot ascribe much significance to an agreement between our observations and the theory, because this agreement can easily be a matter of chance. Only if the number of adjustable parameters is much smaller than the number of our observations does an agreement between these observations and our theory represent a true confirmation for the latter, and only in this case can we say that our theory provides an explanation for the observed facts.

    Google Scholar 

  48. See John C. Harsanyi, ‘Cardinal Utility in Welfare Economics and in the Theory of Risk-Taking’, Journal of Political Economy, LXI (October 1953), 434–35;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. See John C. Harsanyi, ‘Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility’, Journal of Political Economy, LXIII (August 1955), 309–21;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. See John C. Harsanyi, ‘Ethics in Terms of Hypothetical Imperatives’, Mind, XLVII (July 1958), 305–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. See Harsanyi, ‘A Bargaining Model for Social Status’.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Harsanyi, ‘Explanation and Comparative Dynamics’, 136–37.

    Google Scholar 

  53. I owe this point to Nelson Polsby.

    Google Scholar 

  54. By explaining the ‘existence’ of an institution I mean explaining its emergence at some point of time and its survival ever since.

    Google Scholar 

  55. See Section VIII; cf. also Harsanyi, ‘Explanation and Comparative Dynamics’.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1980 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Harsanyi, J.C. (1980). Rational-Choice Models of Political Behavior vs. Functionalist and Conformist Theories. In: Essays on Ethics, Social Behavior, and Scientific Explanation. Theory and Decision Library, vol 12. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9327-9_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9327-9_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-1186-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-9327-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics