Skip to main content

Contingency as Eigen-value of Politics [Reflexivity as second-order Observation]

  • Chapter
Law and Reflexive Politics

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 35))

  • 167 Accesses

Abstract

In Luhmann’s discussion of the political system, democracy, as foil for the guiding distinction, allowed for the system’s self-observation. The scope of political variability was thereby delimited, the scope of what could change arrested in that depiction. This means more than that the system sanctions a certain order of affairs. What is at stake here is meaning, the possibility that something registers as politically meaningful. For Luhmann, the ‘government/opposition’ distinction opens up the contingency space in politics in the sense of delimiting what can be done politically in terms of operations. In terms of observation it allows not simply an understanding of how things are but also a glimpse of how things could be different (the opposition could come to power). It is in that limiting way that the conceptual space of political possibility is semanticised.

A picture kept us captive. And we could not get outside of it, for it lay in our language and language seemed to repeat it to us inexorably. (Wittgenstein)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See Luhmann, 1991a, 225-6. Systems, that is, perceive each other all the time without automatically becoming second-order observers. They only become that when what one system-say law-thematises another’s-say the economy-way of observing, say people as profit maximizers. It is obvious in this context why theory is the second-order observer par excellence.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Luhmann, 1986e, 23

    Google Scholar 

  3. Luhmann, 1990a 139

    Google Scholar 

  4. uhmann, 1990a, 168

    Google Scholar 

  5. ‘If a system is able to discover new “inviolate levels” that serve to deparadoxise its identity, semantic systems deemed necessary may become contingent.’ (1990a 138-139)

    Google Scholar 

  6. (1986e 25)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Luhmann ascribes the contingency of the social world to his discussion of functional differentiation. Functionally induced reductions of social complexity compete as contingency. Luhmann says: ‘die Universalität der Kontingenz an die Spezifikation der Funktionsysteme gebunden ist.’ And ‘In diesem Sinne ist das Beobachten zweuter Ordnung mit seiner Semantik, seinen Eigenwerten der Kontingenz, methodologisch gesprochen, eine Intervenierende Variable, die erklärt, dass die Gesellschaft in eine an Funktionen orientierer Differenzierungsform übergehen kann.’ (1992a, 114, 119)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Luhmann defines as contingent that which is neither impossible nor necessary 1984, 152. For the problems of defining the term through two negations, see 1992a pp96ff.

    Google Scholar 

  9. In a previous paper (1991) I had attempted to establish a connection between first and second-observation, such as would allow the political system (first-order) to “learn from political theory. How was political theory to ‘resonate’ at the level of the political system? I hesitate to follow this as a possible-or at least not incompatible with systems-theory-route. On the one hand I think, now, that this connection between levels of observation flies in the face of too much of systems theory. There cannot be an adequate feedback, recursive or not, between levels of observation. On the other hand, Luhmann recently seems to re-affirm the possibility, by treating theory not as a different system, but at the level of system’s programming. “The entire system [can] operate at the level of second order observation, and only secondarily is observation of the first order activated once again …” And “[I]n the case of self-observation of the second order [the observing system] can be the system itself.” (1991a, 220, 225). I will leave the question open because given the contingency of guiding distinctions around which worlds of political action build up, a notion of reflexive politics need not seek its internal leverage from such a connection between levels of observation.

    Google Scholar 

  10. In systems theory, contingency is tied to second-order observation. ‘Alles wird kontingent, wenn das, was beobachtet wird, da von abhängt, wer beobachtet wird.’ (1992a, 100)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Luhmann takes the concept from Gunther (See Luhmann, 1986a, sections V, VII and n13). To take a simple example. The use of one system code operates as a rejection value for all other codes. Once a true/false code is opted for, given the incompatibility of encodements, the criteriality of all other codes is precluded. In the above sense, rejection values are congruent with the differentiation of autopoietic systems. Problems begin to arise when the rejection value is introduced not as the privileging of one system coding over another but internally within one and the same system, “adapting it to being three-valued, and giving it the possibility of throwing out its own code” (1986a, p24). Luhmann undertakes a complex analysis of this possibility with regard to the legal system and concludes that rejection values would require a degree of differentiation of levels that is unrealistic in the legal systems of the present day.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Luhmann, 1986a, 187

    Google Scholar 

  13. ibid., 189

    Google Scholar 

  14. Luhmann himself does not connect his discussion of political theory with the rejection value.

    Google Scholar 

  15. This, his earlier position in (1986e) is tempered in his more recent analysis of protest movements in (1991a). Here he says: “The form of protest remains a form that presupposes the other side that is to react to the protest. The collapse of this difference entails the collapse of the protest.” (1991a, 126) To the extent only that this difference refers to “the very institutions from which [the protest] is taking exception” (ibid), the difference again becomes an opposition to the political system itself. In my eyes Luhmann remains ambiguous on this point.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Luhmann, 1988a, 139

    Google Scholar 

  17. Smitt, 1976

    Google Scholar 

  18. Luhmann maintains that with the transition from stratification to functional differentiation, the critique of arbitrariness and despotism was made redundant.

    Google Scholar 

  19. “There is a plurality of subjects of resistance, each the product of highly differentiated social processes and exemplifying its own discrete and peculiar rationality. Their opacity and incommensurability is such that there is no privileged position from which their reactions can be predicted and channeled, least of all the institutions of parliamentary democracy. Subterranean political groupings engage in a form of guerrilla warfare against the state … they become visible only infrequently and unexpectedly, and their relationship to the state is one of ‘reciprocal incitation and struggle; less of a face to face confrontation which paralyses both sides than a permanent provocation.’ [Foucault]” (Barron, 1990, 122-123)

    Google Scholar 

  20. “The Nation-State has been replaced from above by a tightly interdependent system of transnational relationships and subdivided from below into a multiplicity of partial governments, defined both by their own systems of representation and decision-making and by an ensemble of interwoven organisations which combine inextricably the public and the private.” (Melucci, 1988, 257)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Jean-Louis Moynot, confederal secretary of the CGT and member of the communist party, urged in his writings that the party neither ignore nor take over the new social protest but try to push them beyond corporatist formulations. Similar appeals not to stifle the political dynamism of class and autogestionnaire action, were heard by the radical labour lawyers in Germany in the thirties (Frankel) and Otto-Kahn Freund in Britain.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Glasman’s excellent (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Luhmann, 1990a, 101

    Google Scholar 

  24. Offe (1985)

    Google Scholar 

  25. ibid., 69

    Google Scholar 

  26. ibid., 70

    Google Scholar 

  27. Barron, 1990, 122

    Google Scholar 

  28. Luhmann, 1990a, 33

    Google Scholar 

  29. Deleuze and Guattari 1988, 353

    Google Scholar 

  30. Luhmann, 1971, 21-22

    Google Scholar 

  31. For a defence of reflexivity as rationalization see Eder, who alludes to Habermas. Eder writes: “Reduced to its procedural form, the ultimate ground of the rationality of modernity is that we can choose our symbolic orders, that we are not stuck with any one type of rationality, and that we can at any time abandon what we have ceased to accept rationally. (1993, 34)

    Google Scholar 

  32. The allusion is to Luhmann’s Kontingenz als Eigenwert der modernen Gesellschaft (In 1992a)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Luhmann, 1990a, 105

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Christodoulidis, E.A. (1998). Contingency as Eigen-value of Politics [Reflexivity as second-order Observation]. In: Law and Reflexive Politics. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 35. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3967-0_19

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3967-0_19

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0283-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3967-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics