Skip to main content

The Rationality of Morality

  • Chapter
Morality in Evolution
  • 75 Accesses

Abstract

The rigorous employment of his empirical method led Bergson to the discovery that there are two distinct and irreducible moralities in the life of man — the closed or static, and the open or dynamic These two are not merely different aspects of a single morality since there is a difference of kind between them and not merely one of degree. Bergson traced each of the two moralities to a separate cause: the closed morality to social pressure, the open morality to aspiration. He found the first to be rooted in instinct and habit, and the second in the experience of moral heroes and mystics. Human beings behave as they do morally (I) because nature, acting through society, constrains them to do so, and (2) because certain heroic souls have had visions of a spiritual destiny for man and have inspired them with these visions. Social pressure and aspiration — these are the facts that must be taken into account in any inquiry into the nature and evolution of morality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. The Two Sources, p. 55 (O. 1029).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., p. 14 (O. 992). In criticizing the moral philosophies of the past Bergson ignores the significant differences existing between them with respect to the role played by intellect. He seems to lump together and reject all moral theories from the Greek period on since all of them represent in his opinion an excessive intellectualism. See ibid., pp. 13–14. 56–57, 80–87 (O. 992–93. 1029–30, 1050–57).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., p. 15 (O. 994).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., D. 15 (O. 994).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid., D. 16 (O. 994–95): “We find in primitive races many prohibitions and prescriptions explicable at most by vague associations of ideas, by superstition, by automatism. Nor are they without their use, since the obedience of everyone to laws, even absurd ones, assures greater cohesion to the community. But in that case the usefulness of the rule accrues, by a kind of reverse action, solely from the fact of our submission to it. Prescriptions or prohibitions which are intrinsically useful are those that are explicitly designed for the preservation or well-being of society.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., p. 16 (O. 994–95).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., pp. 17–18 (O. 995). Bergson draws attention to the fact that his use of the term “categorical imperative” bears little resemblance to that of Kant who defined the categorical imperative as a command of reason necessarily obligating the will, and obligation as the necessity of a free action when viewed in relation to the categorical imperative of reason. See Immanuel Kant, General Introduction to the Metaphysics of Morals, IV, “General Preliminary Conceptions Defined and Explained,” (Great Books of the Western World, ed. Robert M. Hutchins and Mortimer J. Adler, published by Encyclopaedia Brittannica, Inc., Chicago, 1952 ). vol. 42, pp. 390–94; also Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals, section III, “How is a categorical imperative possible?” Ibid., pp. 282–83; and Critique of Practical Reason, Part I, Book I, Chapter I, ibid., pp. 297–98.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid.. p. i8 (O. 996).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., pp. 49–60 (O. 1032–33).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., pp. 83–84 (O. 1053–54). See also p. iii (O. 1077–78).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., p. 84 (O. 1054).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., D. 85 (O. 2054 ).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., D. 85 (O. 2054 ).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., D. 151 (O. 1112 ).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid.. D. 85 (O. 2055 ).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid.. p. 151 (O. 1112).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., p. 112 (O. 1078).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 154 (O. i ii5).

    Google Scholar 

  19. See ibid., pp. 109–97 (O. 1076–1152) for an extended discussion of the various myths and their purposes.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., pp. III-112 (O. 2078).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., p. 121 (O. 2086).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., D. 194 (O. 1150 ).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., pp. 31–32 (O. ioo8).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 35 (O. I o t t).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid.; “In the first case the emotion is the consequence of an idea, or of a mental picture; the `feeling’ is indeed the result of an intellectual state which owes nothing to it, which is self-sufficient, and which, if it does experience a certain reaction from the feeling, loses more than it gains.”

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid p. 35 (O. 1012).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., p. 39 (O. 1015).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., p. 39 (O. 1015).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., p. 40 (O. 1016).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 40 (O. (o16).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., 013. 40–41 (O. 1016).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., pp. 52–55 (O. ioz5–28). It was not Socrates, the founder of moral science, who was the moral hero, but Socrates bouleversant les âmes par sa vie et par sa mort.’ See Henri Gouhier, Bergson et le Christ des Évangiles, p. 337.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., p. 55 (O. 3029).

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., pp. 52–54 (O. 3026–27).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gallagher, I.J. (1970). The Rationality of Morality. In: Morality in Evolution. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7573-7_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7573-7_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-017-0034-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7573-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics