Skip to main content
Log in

Identifying and individuating cognitive systems: a task-based distributed cognition alternative to agent-based extended cognition

  • Research Report
  • Published:
Cognitive Processing Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article argues for a task-based approach to identifying and individuating cognitive systems. The agent-based extended cognition approach faces a problem of cognitive bloat and has difficulty accommodating both sub-individual cognitive systems (“scaling down”) and some supra-individual cognitive systems (“scaling up”). The standard distributed cognition approach can accommodate a wider variety of supra-individual systems but likewise has difficulties with sub-individual systems and faces the problem of cognitive bloat. We develop a task-based variant of distributed cognition designed to scale up and down smoothly while providing a principled means of avoiding cognitive bloat. The advantages of the task-based approach are illustrated by means of two parallel case studies: re-representation in the human visual system and in a biomedical engineering laboratory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Clark and Chalmers argue that both cognition and mind are extended; the Otto case was originally used to argue that mind, in particular, is extended, but it can be used for either purpose. Our focus here is on the hypothesis of extended cognition; hence we will not be concerned with the claim that Otto’s beliefs are located in his notebook but rather with the claim that Otto and his notebook constitute a single cognitive system. See Huebner (2014) for a defense of distributed mentality. Our focus is also distinct from that of theorists who have argued for extended consciousness (Manzotti 2011; Honderich 2014), and we take no stand on the question of extended or distributed consciousness. A fuller treatment would, however, eventually have to deal with this question, especially in view of recent debates on cognitive phenomenology, many participants in which have argued that cognition has a distinctive conscious character (see, e.g., Strawson 2011; Smithies 2013.)

  2. But see Sprevak (2009) for an attempt to use the relationship between functionalism and the extended cognition hypothesis to ground a reductio of the latter.

  3. For an overview of the transition from first-wave to second-wave extended cognition theorizing, see Kirchhoff (2012).

  4. In fact, it is unclear to what extent it is compatible with the spirit of first-wave extended cognition to impose criteria in addition to functional isomorphism; in retrospect, the “trust-and-glue” conditions to some extent look like an ad hoc attempt to prevent cognitive bloat (Palermos 2011).

  5. Similarly, artificial intelligence researchers will sometimes perform “ablation experiments” on their complicated programs. These are analogous to lesioning experiments in animals in that they remove a part of the program and observe the resulting behavior, allowing the researcher to draw conclusions regarding the functions of specific parts of the program.

  6. We say “virtually” because there are exceptions, e.g., Tallis (2004). While most theorists agree that cognition is a matter of information processing, there is controversy over the nature of information itself. In a recent review, for example, Crnkovic and Hofkirchner (2011) list several senses of information endorsed by scholars. Our conception of information is meant to be very inclusive, neutral among the kinds of information listed.

  7. This raises the question of how cognitive tasks are to be individuated; see “Identifying cognitive systems” section below.

  8. This implies that cognition necessarily involves representations. While this view is compatible with most approaches to cognition, it is rejected by radical brands of antirepresentationalism (Beer 1990; Brooks 1999; Gelder 1995; Chemero 2009). Many dynamical systems theorists, for example, reject talk of representations. While this approach has found applications in certain domains in fields such as robotics, dynamical systems theorists have difficulty providing a general account of cognition that does not appeal to representations, since cognition includes, in addition to processes that might be explained in terms of interaction between the cognizer and its environment, processes that refer to entities beyond the cognizer’s environment (Clark 1998a). Consider, e.g., the difficulty of providing an account of mental time travel [i.e., remembering the past and imagining the future (Michaelian 2016; Michaelian et al. 2016)] without appealing to representations of past and future events.

  9. One might ask what additional explanatory power is gained by positing the existence of sub- and supra-individual cognitive systems; we return to this question in “Summing up” section.

  10. While we have chosen these cases because they involve analogous cognitive tasks performed at different scales, this should not be taken to suggest that we endorse the functionalist reasoning behind first-wave extended cognition.

  11. We use the term “proposition” here in the sense that it has in the knowledge representation literature: propositions are sentence-like representations, as opposed to, for example, images. We do not use it in the logical sense, in that, for example, propositions do not necessarily obey the law of excluded middle.

  12. Though re-interpretation is the major functional reason offered for mental imagery, empirical support for peoples’ ability to do it at all has been spotty. See Chambers and Reisberg (1985) and Slezak (1992) for some failed attempts, and Finks et al. (1989) for a response.

  13. Nersessian was the first to suggest that scientific laboratories were distributed cognitive systems. See Giere (2002) for a useful description of this approach.

  14. Aliases are used to protect the anonymity of respondents and their laboratories.

  15. After the results are collected, statistics are run on the data. Since software is used to run these analyses, it too is done by a DCS consisting of, at the very least, a person and a computer program.

  16. The architecture CLARION (Sun 2005) supports the modeling of multi-person cognition, though not (or at least not explicitly) of cognitive artifacts.

  17. Swarm intelligence (Panigrahi et al. 2011) provides one illustration of the insights that can be obtained when we are prepared to view processes unfolding at different scales—including the scale of multi-organism systems—as engaged in cognition.

References

  • Adams F, Aizawa K (2001) The bounds of cognition. Philos Psychol 14(1):43–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams F, Aizawa K (2008) The bounds of cognition. Wiley-Blackwell, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer RD (1990) Intelligence as adaptive behavior. Academic Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks RA (1999) Cambrian intelligence: the early history of the new AI. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers D, Reisberg D (1985) Can mental images be ambiguous? J Exp Psychol Hum Percept Perform 11(3):317–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero A (2009) Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1998a) Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke A (1998b) Author’s response. Metascience 7(1):95–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2001) Reasons, robots and the extended mind. Mind Lang 16(2):121–145

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2007) Curing cognitive hiccups: a defense of the extended mind. J Philos 104(4):163–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2008) Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Chalmers D (1998) The extended mind. Analysis 58(1):7–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clowes RW (2013) The cognitive integration of e-memory. Rev Philos Psychol 4(1):107–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniel PM, Whitteridge D (1961) The representation of the visual field on the cerebral cortex in monkeys. J Physiol 159(2):203–221

    Article  CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Dodig-Crnkovic G, Hofkirchner W (2011) Floridi’s “open problems in philosophy of information”, ten years later. Information 2(2):327–359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donald M (1993) Origins of the modern mind: three stages in the evolution of culture and cognition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dror IE, Harnad S (eds) (2008) Cognition distributed: how cognitive technology extends our minds. John Benjamins Publishing, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Farah MJ, Peronnet F, Gonon MA, Giard MH (1988) Electrophysiological evidence for a shared representational medium for visual images and visual percepts. J Exp Psychol Gen 117(3):248

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Finks RA, Pinker S, Farah MJ (1989) Reinterpreting visual patterns in mental imagery. Cogn Sci 13(1):51–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2002) Scientific cognition as distributed cognition. In: Carruthers P, Stich S, Siegal M (eds) Cognitive bases of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2011) Distributed cognition as human centered although not human bound: reply to Vaesen. Soc Epistemol 25(4):393–399

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere RN (2012) Scientific cognition: human centered but not human bound. Philos Explor 15(2):199–206

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heersmink R (2012) Mind and artifact: a multidimensional matrix for exploring cognition-artifact relations. In: Proceedings of AISB/IACAP world congress 2012

  • Heersmink R (2015) Dimensions of integration in embedded and extended cognitive systems. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 14(3):577–598

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Höldobler B, Wilson EO (1990) The Ants. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Honderich T (2014) Actual consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huebner B (2014) Macrocognition: a theory of distributed minds and collective intentionality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (1995a) Cognition in the wild. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (1995b) How a cockpit remembers its speeds. Cogn Sci 19(3):265–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (2011) Enculturating the supersized mind. Philos Stud 152(3):437–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (2014) The cultural ecosystem of human cognition. Philos Psychol 27(1):34–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff MD (2012) Extended cognition and fixed properties: steps to a third-wave version of extended cognition. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 11(2):287–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn SM (1996) Image and brain: the resolution of the imagery debate. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn SM, Thompson WL (2003) When is early visual cortex activated during visual mental imagery? Psychol Bull 129(5):723

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lave J (1988) Cognition in practice: mind, mathematics and culture in everyday life. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Manzotti R (2011) The spread mind: is consciousness situated? Teorema 30(2):55–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr D (1982) Vision: a computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian K (2012) Is external memory memory? Biological memory and extended mind. Conscious Cogn 21(3):1154–1165

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian K (2014) JFGI: from distributed cognition to distributed reliabilism. Philos Issues 24(1):314–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian K (2016) Mental time travel: episodic memory and our knowledge of the personal past. MIT Press, Cambridge

  • Michaelian K, Sutton J (2013) Distributed cognition and memory research: history and current directions. Rev Philos Psychol 4(1):1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian K, Klein SB, Szpunar KK (eds) (2016) Seeing the future: theoretical perspectives on future-oriented mental time travel. Oxford University Press

  • Nersessian NJ, Kurz-Milcke E, Newstetter WC, Davies J (2003) Research laboratories as evolving distributed cognitive systems. In: Markman A, Barsalou L (eds) Proceedings of the 25th annual conference of the cognitive science society. Erlbaum, pp 857–862

  • Nersessian NJ, Kurz-Milcke E, Davies J (2005) Ubiquitous computing in science and engineering labs: a case study of a biomedical engineering lab. In: Kouzelis G, Pournari M, Stoeppler M, Tselfes V (eds) Knowledge in the new technologies. Peter Lang, Bern, pp 167–195

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermos SO (2011) Belief-forming processes, extended. Rev Philos Psychol 2(4):741–765

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palermos SO (2014) Loops, constitution, and cognitive extension. Cogn Syst Res 27:25–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Panigrahi BK, Shi Y, Lim M-H (2011) Handbook of swarm intelligence. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Poirier P, Chicoisne G (2006) A framework for thinking about distributed cognition. Pragmat Cogn 14(2):215–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn ZW (2002) Mental imagery: in search of a theory. Behav Brain Sci 25:157–182 4

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands M (2009) Extended cognition and the mark of the cognitive. Philos Psychol 22(1):1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert RD (2004) Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. J Philos 101(8):389–428

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert RD (2013) Memory, natural kinds, and cognitive extension; or, Martians dont remember, and cognitive science is not about cognition. Rev Philos Psychol 4(1):25–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L (2011) Embodied cognition. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Slezak P (1992) When can visual images be re-interpreted. In: Proceedings of 14th annual conference of the cognitive science society, pp 124–129

  • Smithies D (2013) The nature of cognitive phenomenology. Philos Compass 8(8):744–754

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak M (2009) Extended cognition and functionalism. J Philos 106(9):503–527

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson G (2011) Cognitive phenomenology: real life. In: Bayne T, Montague M (eds) Cognitive phenomenology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 285–325

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sun R (2005) The CLARION cognitive architecture: extending cognitive modeling to social simulation. In: Sun R (ed) Cognition and multi-agent interaction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton J (2006) Distributed cognition: domains and dimensions. Pragmat Cogn 14(2):235–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton J (2010) Exograms and interdisciplinarity: history, the extended mind, and the civilizing process. In: Menary R (ed) The extended mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 189–225

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tallis R (2004) Why the mind is not a computer: a pocket lexicon of neuromythology. Imprint Academic, Exeter

    Google Scholar 

  • Theiner G (forthcoming) Group-sized distributed cognitive systems. In: Routledge handbook of collective intentionality. Routledge

  • Van Gelder T (1995) What might cognition be, if not computation? J Philos 92(7):345–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Rooij I (2008) The tractable cognition thesis. Cogn Sci 32(6):939–984

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Andrew Brook, Anthony J. Francis, Jeanette Bicknell, Eros Corazza, Wendy Newstetter, Elke Kurz-Milcke, Etienne Pelaprat, and especially Nancy J. Nersessian. The ethnographic research discussed in “Re-representation in a biomedical engineering laboratory” section was part of a project in which the first author was involved; the project was supported by a National Science Foundation ROLE Grant (REC0106773) to Nancy J. Nersessian (PI) and Wendy Newstetter (co-PI).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jim Davies.

Additional information

Handling editor: John K. Tsotsos, York University, Toronto.

Reviewers: Iris van Rooij, Radboud University Nijmegen, Igor Aleksander, Imperial College, London.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Davies, J., Michaelian, K. Identifying and individuating cognitive systems: a task-based distributed cognition alternative to agent-based extended cognition. Cogn Process 17, 307–319 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-016-0759-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-016-0759-4

Keywords

Navigation