Skip to main content
Log in

Choice is Not True or False: The Domain of Rhetorical Argumentation

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Leading contemporary argumentation theories such as those of Ralph Johnson, van Eemeren and Houtlosser, and Tindale, in their attempt to address rhetoric, tend to define rhetorical argumentation with reference to (a) the rhetorical arguer’s goal (to persuade effectively), and (b) the means he employs to do so. However, a central strand in the rhetorical tradition itself, led by Aristotle, and arguably the dominant view, sees rhetorical argumentation as defined with reference to the domain of issues discussed. On that view, the domain of rhetorical argumentation is centered on choice of action in the civic sphere, and the distinctive nature of issues in this domain is considered crucial. Hence, argumentation theories such as those discussed, insofar as they do not see rhetoric as defined by its distinctive domain, apply an understanding of rhetoric that is historically inadequate. It is further suggested that theories adopting this understanding of rhetoric risk ignoring important distinctive features of argumentation about action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Undoubtedly, van Eemeren and Houtlosser would deny that there is such a dilemma. Indeed, some of their formulations of how debaters could be rhetorical and dialectical at the same time are such that rhetoricians ought to give them their wholehearted endorsement, for example when they speak of “maintaining certain standards of reasonableness and expecting others to comply with the same critical standards”, after which they go on to say that this commitment need not prevent debaters from “attempting to resolve the difference of opinion in their own favour” (2001, p. 151). This sounds like the position often articulated by the late Wayne Booth, and I agree with it completely. However, obeying standards of reasonableness is not the same as being committed to resolving the difference of opinion. It may be true that if debaters in politics and other spheres did obey such standards, they would reach consensus more often; but even with the severest standards upheld they often would not. Why? Some of the authentic debate examples that van Eemeren and Houtlosser have analyzed are actually about the kind of issues where consensus may never ensue, no matter how much reasonable discussion the discussants would have engaged in; this is also the kind of issue where rhetorical argumentation typically occurs. For instance, in the British debate about fox-hunting clearly no resolution of the difference occurs. Yet in most of the strategic manoeuvres on the two sides that van Eemeren and Houtlosser have discussed there is no unreasonableness, no “derailment” of strategic manoeuvring; but there is no consensus either. The pragma-dialectical theory, based on the ideal of the critical discussion and aiming at a resolution of the difference, predicts that if the rules are obeyed, consensus will occur. So why doesn’t it? My answer is that legislation on fox-hunting is a typical example of an issue belonging to the rhetorical domain of issues—those ultimately concerned with choice of action, not truth.

  2. This division of labour was first suggested by Wenzel (1990).

  3. Jeffrey Walker seems to make a strong case against such a claim. He sees rhetoric as rooted in the poetic/epideictic kind of discourse performed by “singers”, aiodoi, according to Hesiod (c. 700 B·C.); the “pragmatic discourse” of later age is, to Walker, a “’secondary’ projection of that rhetoric into the particular forums and dispute occasions of civic life” (2000, p. 10). I have no need to contradict Walker’s genealogy; as I noted initially, rhetoric is a wider concept than rhetorical argumentation. Yet it remains true that most ancient theorists of rhetorical argumentation from Aristotle onwards see it as rooted in civic issues. And in fact, there is a reason why poetic and epideictic features of the discourse of the aiodoi may be “projected” into the domain of civic debate. As will be discussed below, such debate is about choosing action, not about the truth of propositions. In debate about choice of action, two opposite standpoints may both be legitimate and reasonable; it is not the case that one is “true” while the other is “false”. Hence neither debater may be compelled by dialectical argument to retract his standpoint and agree with the other. Instead, debaters must seek to win the free adherence of their opponents and audience by including, among other arguments and appeals, features known poetic and epideictic discourse.

  4. This follows Kennedy's translation (1991). The translation in the complete English edition of Aristotle's works, by J.H. Freese (Aristotle 1926), consistently uses "deliberate", as does Kennedy some of the time; it is a word which, like the Greek bouleuein, is tied more closely than "debate" to discussions of what we will.

  5. Long notes that Aristotle uses the middle voice of bouleuein throughout the Ethics, giving the word the self-reflexive meaning “to take council with oneself”, and thereby underlining the importance of this self-reflexivity to his concept of phronêsis (2002, p. 52).

  6. This example will probably raise objections to the effect that, as Alan Gross (1990), Jeanne Fahnestock (2003) and others have shown, argumentation in the natural sciences is full of rhetoric. However, while features of rhetorical argumentation may, unavoidably, show up even in domains like science, there remains a difference of principle between arguments over truth and arguments over action. To be sure, a scientist may have been influenced in part by the rhetoric of, e.g., Einstein’s writing, to opt for atomic theory in the sense that he chooses to believe in the existence of atoms and to propagate this belief in his teaching, etc.; but he may not decide to bring about the existence of atoms, any more than he may decide to bring about anything else in the fundamental constitution of nature. He may, however, as any other human being, decide to bring about any number of changes or events in his own life, e.g., to marry, to quit smoking, to eat a hamburger, to kill himself; or he may decide to help bring about events and changes in the social world he inhabits, e.g., by voting for a given presidential candidate. Similarly, he may argue for the truth of atomic theory, but not for atoms coming into existence; conversely, he may argue for the election of the candidate of his choice, but that argument is not an argument for the "truth" of that choice. Of course, an argument for someone's election may be (and usually is) supported by assertions whose truth the arguer argues for, e.g., that the candidate is well qualified, that his policies are wise, etc. But what we argue for in deliberation, such a the election of a given candidate, is not a proposition that may have a truth value; by contrast, what we argue for in science is precisely a proposition that may have a truth value, even though the philosophy of science tells us that we will never be able conclusively to determine that truth value.

  7. To Locke, in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, rhetoric is a “powerful instrument of error and deceit” (1959 [1690], II, p. 146; Book III, X, p. 34); to Kant, in Kritik der Urteilskraft, it is “gar keiner Achtung würdig” (1914 [1790], p. 404; Sect. 53, footnote).

  8. The notion of reasonable disagreement and its inevitability on political, ethical and other practical issues there is a large body of thinking by contemporary philosophers that argumentation theory might do well to address; see, e.g., Rawls (1989, 1993), Larmore (1996); Kock (2007).

References

  • Anon. 1964. Ad C. Herennium: De ratione dicendi (Rhetorica ad Herennium), with an English translation by Harry Caplan (Loeb Classical Library, 403). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. 1957. Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1926. The works of Aristotle translated into English under the Editorship of W. D. Ross, Vol. xxii. The Art of Rhetoric (trans: Freese, J.H.) (Loeb Classical Library, 193). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Austin, J.L. 1953. How to talk-some simple ways. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 53: 227–246.

  • Bitzer, L.F. 1968. The rhetorical situation. Philosophy and Rhetoric 1: 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, H. 1783/2004. Lectures on rhetoric and belles lettres, ed. Linda Ferreira-Buckley and S. Michael Halloran. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Boethius, Anicius Manlius Severinus. 1978. Boethius’s De topicis differentiis. Translated, with notes and essays on the text, by Eleonore Stump. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Campbell, G. 1776/1969. The philosophy of rhetoric by George Campbell, ed. Lloyd F. Bitzer, Foreword by David Potter. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Cicero, M.T. 1967. De Oratore; De fato; Paradoxa stoicorum; De partitione oratoria (trans: Sutton, E.W. and Rackham, H.). (Loeb Classical Library, 368). London: Heinemann.

  • Cicero, M.T. 1968. De inventione; De optimo genere oratorum; Topica. With an English translation by H.M. Hubell (Loeb Classical Library, 386). London: Heinemann.

  • Cox, V. 2003. Rhetoric and humanism in Quattrocento Venice. Renaissance Quarterly 56: 652–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dilts, M.R., and G.A. Kennedy. 1997. Two greek rhetorical treatises from the roman empire: Introduction, text and translation of the arts of rhetoric attributed to anonymous Seguerianus and to Apsines of Gadara. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fahnestock, J. 2003. Rhetorical figures in science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumaroli, M. 1983. Rhetoric, politics, and society: From Italian Ciceronianism to French Classicism. In Renaissance eloquence, ed. J.J. Murphy, 253–273. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garver, E. 2000. Comments on “Rhetorical analysis within a pragma-dialectical framework: The case of R.J. Reynolds”. Argumentation 14: 307–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, A.G. 1990. The rhetoric of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, A.G., and A.E. Walzer (eds.). 2000. Rereading Aristotle’s rhetoric. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halm, K. 1863. Rhetores Latini minores: Ex codicibus maximam partem primum adhibitis emendabat Carolus Halm. Teubner: Lipsiae [Leipzig].

  • Hauser, G.A. 1999. Aristotle on epideictic: The formation of public morality. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 29: 5–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, G.A. 2002. Introduction to rhetorical theory, 2nd ed. Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, M. 1995. Hermogenes on issues: Strategies of argument in later Greek rhetoric. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, M. 2004. Menander: A rhetor in context. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R.H. 1996. The need for a dialectical tier in arguments. In Proceedings of the international conference on formal and applied practical reasoning, ed. Dov M. Gabbay and Hans Jürgen Ohlbach, 349–360.

  • Johnson, R.H. 2000. Manifest rationality: A pragmatic theory of argument. Mahwah, N.J: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R.H. 2002. Manifest rationality reconsidered: Reply to my fellow symposiasts. Argumentation 16: 311–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1914 [1790]. Kritik der Urteilskraft. In Werke, Vol. V., ed. Ernst Cassirer and Hermann Cohen. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer.

  • Kennedy, G.A. 1991. Aristotle on rhetoric: A theory of civic discourse. Newly translated with introduction, notes, and appendixes by George A. Kennedy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, G.A. 1994. A new history of classical rhetoric. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, G.A. 1999. Classical rhetoric and its Christian and secular tradition from ancient to modern times, 2nd Revised edition. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.

  • Kock, C. 2007. Norms of legitimate dissensus. Informal Logic 27: 179–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larmore, C. 1996. The morals of modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. 1959 [1690]. An essay concerning human understanding. Collated and annotated, with prolegomena, biographical, critical, and historical by Alexander Campbell Fraser, Vol. I–II. New York: Dover.

  • Long, C.P. 2002. The ontological reappropriation of phronēsis. Continental Philosophy Review 35: 35–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1969 [1863]. ‘Utilitarianism’. In The collected works of John Stuart Mill, general editor John M. Robson, Vol. X. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

  • Miller, J.M., M.H. Prosser, and T.W. Benson. 1973. Readings in medieval rhetoric. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C. 1970. The new rhetoric: A theory of practical reasoning. The great ideas today, 272–312. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1969. The new rhetoric. A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press (Original edition: 1958, La nouvelle rhétorique. Traité de l’argumentation. Paris: Presses universitaires de France).

  • Rawls, J. 1989. The domain of the political and overlapping consensus. New York University Law Review 64: 233–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Remer, G. 1999. Political oratory and conversation: Cicero versus deliberative democracy. Political Theory 27: 39–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1993. Pluralism: Against the demand for consensus. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, J.E. 1960. Book three of Brunetto Latini’s Tresor: An English translation and assessment of its contribution to rhetorical theory. Diss. Stanford: Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Donald A., ed. and trans. 2001. Quintilian. The Orator’s education, II.xvi.9–10. Cambridge: Harvard UP.

  • Searle, J.R. 1979a. What is an intentional state? Mind 88: 74–92. New Series.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1979b. Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1983. Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tindale, C. 1999. Acts of arguing: A rhetorical model of argument. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tindale, C. 2004. Rhetorical argumentation: Principles of theory and practice. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 1999. Strategic manoeuvring in argumentative discourse. Discourse Studies 1: 479–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2000. Rhetorical analysis within a pragma-dialectical framework: The case of R. J. Reynolds. Argumentation 14: 293–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2001. Managing disagreement: Rhetorical analysis within a dialectical framework. Argumentation and Advocacy 37: 150–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2002. Strategic manoeuvring: Maintaining a delicate balance. In The warp and woof of argumentation analysis (Argumentation Library 6), ed. F.H. van Eemeren and P. Houtlosser, 131–160. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisers.

  • Vico, G. 1996. The art of rhetoric (Institutiones Oratoriae, 1711–1741). From the definitive latin text and notes, Italian commentary and introduction by Giuliano Crifò (trans and ed.: Pinton, Giorgio A. and Shippee, Arthur W.). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

  • Walker, J. 2000. Rhetoric and poetics in antiquity. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenzel, J.W. 1990. Three perspectives on argument: Rhetoric, dialectic, logic. In Perspectives on argumentation: Essays in the honor of Wayne Brockriede, ed. R. Trapp, and J. Schuetz, 9–26. Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. 1994. The art of rhetoric (1560). Edited with Notes and Commentary by Peter E. Medine. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Kock.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kock, C. Choice is Not True or False: The Domain of Rhetorical Argumentation. Argumentation 23, 61–80 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-008-9115-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-008-9115-x

Keywords

Navigation