Skip to main content
Log in

Weaning Business Ethics from Strategic Economism: The Development Ethics Perspective

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

For more than three decades, business ethics has suggested and evaluated strategies for multinationals to address abject deprivations and weak regulatory institutions in developing countries. Critical appraisals, internal and external, have observed these concerns being severely constrained by the overwhelming prioritization of economic values, i.e., economism. Recent contributions to business ethics stress a re-imagination of the field wherein economic goals are downgraded and more attention given to redistribution of wealth and well-being of the weaker individuals and groups. Development ethics, a lesser known field of normative enquiry, already offers nuanced justifications against economism which business ethicists can use in their current attempts to wean the field from old habits.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although, the idea that business must contribute to society is much older (De Bakker et al. 2005; Garriga and Melé 2004; Husted and Allen 2000), I have taken the launch of the Journal of Business Ethics (JBE) in 1982 as the starting point, for a specialist journal represents the emergence of a self-conscious field. The review of contributions focusing on developing countries that follows in later sections is largely limited to contributions to the JBE and Business Ethics Quarterly (BEQ); these journals have been suggested earlier as acceptable indicators of current trends in business ethics scholarship (Talukdar 2011; Collins 2000).

  2. Retrieved from: http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/economism. Accessed on April 11 2011.

  3. Of course, the majority of these contributions can be considered to be voices of Americans shocked by the role of their corporations in destroying lives and futures of their countrymen, in some cases by adopting attitudes they themselves may have espoused. See Marens (2010) for an historical overview of the influences of American political economy on the generation of ideas within business ethics. But the overall stress on securing the well-being of societies from insidious corporate misconduct is applicable in almost any context in the world.

  4. Though these philosophers do not identify themselves explicitly as development ethicists, since they position themselves as aiming to reorient social ethics as such, normative analysis of development without references to their work are rare (Drydyk 2011). Further, being a new and interdisciplinary field of attention, development ethicists do not necessarily associate themselves solely with development ethics. See the website of International Development Ethics Association (IDEA) and contributions to its partner Journal of Global Ethics.

  5. Gasper (2010b) observes that though “well-being” is used when we speak in terms of individuals and “quality of life” when we speak of societies, their meanings overlap. The former terms comes from psychology while the latter from sociology and social policy. Though the fine-grained differences in human well beings and qualities of life offered in development ethics is significant for business ethics, considering the introductory purpose this paper is intended to serve, these variations are not separately tackled.

  6. As Gasper (2008) and Crocker (2006) observe, Goulet had anticipated the capabilities approach before Sen, Haq or Nussbaum. It is evident in his observation—“authentic development aims toward the realization of human capabilities in all spheres” (Goulet 1971, quoted in Gasper 2008, p. 454).

  7. The impact of John Rawls’s Theory of Justice is deeply felt in most contemporary ethical theorizing that links moral philosophy to the social sciences (Coleman 1974), and development ethics is no exception. Central contributors to development ethics, including Sen and Nussbaum, have developed their theories against the backdrop of Rawlsian notions of a just society and individual capacities, extending its application to unique contexts in developing countries characterized by extreme diversity, resource scarcity, and historic forms of oppressions (Sen 2009; Nussbaum 2006a, b, 2011a, b). Rawlsian political philosophy is also pivotal in discussions among philosophers of the role of global institutions regulating distribution of wealth from rich to developing nations, since most of the flow is in the other direction (see, Pogge 2003).

  8. It is impossible to do justice to Sen’s and Nussbaum’s widely discussed and complex contributions to development ethics in this short space; for extended treatments, refer to Gasper (2004), (1997), Gasper (2013); Alkire (2002), and Crocker (1992).

  9. Summarizing Galtung (1979), the idea of basic needs was proposed as an alternative to the New International Economic Order (NIEO) intended to correct international trade imbalances considered to be skewed in favor of the advanced nations as a result of colonialism. The politicians and the elite in developing countries were, and still are, champions of the NIEO as they stood to benefit from increased trade and production in their countries. The basic needs approach (BNA) emanated in intellectual circles concerned with the lack of equitable distribution of the benefits of development within these newly independent countries; these scholars argued that basic needs of the poor be met as a condition for access to the lucrative global trade system. The elite in the developing countries often vociferously objected to these demands and interpreted these demands as surreptitious plots by advanced nations to maintain the advantages they could, in previous centuries, maintain by force (Galtung 1979).

  10. Later works on basic needs have, in turn, drawn from Sen’s insights. For instance, Doyal and Gough use Sen’s insights to distinguish between universal needs and “culturally-sensitive satisfiers” to indicate the level of satisfaction basic needs: “Basic needs, then, are always universal but their satisfiers are often relative”(Doyal and Gough 1991, p. 155).

  11. ‘Direct violence is an event; structural violence is a process with ups and downs; cultural violence is an invariant, a permanence remaining essentially the same for long periods, given the slow transformations of basic culture” (Galtung 1990, p. 293). Galtung uses the metaphor of earthquakes as direct violence, movement of tectonic plates as structural violence, and the fault lines as cultural features.

  12. Margolis and Walsh (2003) draw extensively on Nussbaum’s (1986) position on the incommensurability of values to build their approach to balance economic and social goals. Their acknowledgement of the tragedy of the human condition is compatible with the fundamental tenets of development ethics.

  13. Rights are a “major set of tools in the political struggles to claim fulfillment of needs” (Gasper 2005, p. 231). There are differences in the use of the terms—rights are used in legal and humanitarian worlds and needs for policy making and planning purposes (Gasper 2005). The differences in usage obscure the shared structure of both needs and rights language as concerning an intermediate requirement to attain an acceptable level of human existence. However, “rights” are understood as justified claims of individuals while “needs” are criteria used to allocate resources. (ibid).

  14. Their ethics of conducting deliberations involves an early identification of stakeholders, prior distribution of project information, facilitation of negotiations, and management of resettlement when required, good governance, and avoiding corruption (Penz, et al. 2011). Any change to the existing a living pattern of a community can be justified only if the supporters of a change can prove that (1) the new development is authentic development, (2) the development improves an existing barrier to well-being, (3) alternatives have been considered, and (4) fair deliberations were held to arrive at the decision. These are conditions more stringent and steps more explicit than what is currently available in business ethics (Byrne 2012; Kemp et al. 2011; Gilbert and Behnam 2008).

  15. It is quite surprising that business ethicists continued developing theories on the basis of a premise that academic opinion in global sociology and political economy on globalization had already concluded was a myth; rather the overwhelming evidence pointed to a reoriented but centrally relevant state (Hay 2005; Djelic and Quack 2003; Sassen 2000; Hirst 1997; Dicken 1994).

  16. Drawing interesting parallels between the past decades of business ethics scholarship and seventeenth century Britain, Marens (2007) argues that a majority of business ethicists who prefer the language of contracts tend to adopt Lockean versions of social contracts due to the match with the elitist purpose (protection of private property) Locke intended to serve. Adoption of a broader Rawlsian version, explicitly focusing on redistribution of wealth (the difference principle) also risks repelling the consumers (and/or funders) of business schools (Marens 2007). There are, of course, business ethicists like Hsieh (2009) who adopt Rawlsian versions of social contract. Development ethics, as noted earlier, believe even Rawlsian contracts require supplementing (cf. Sen 2009; Nussbaum 2004, Pogge 2003).

  17. The clients, many of whom were workers living in shanty towns were, according to market principles, assumed to be capable of making decisions on what is good for them. It was only after some poor workers started gambling away their monthly income and adversely affected the lives of family members, including children and elderly, the government stepped into pressure corporations to responsible to adapt and publicize the risks (Gasper 2004).

References

  • Aharoni, Y. (2013). The road to relevance. In: T.M. Devinney, T. Pedersen, & L. Tihanyi (Eds.), Philosophy of Science and Meta-Knowledge in International Business and Management (Advances in International Management, Volume 26) (pp.127–169) Bingley: Emerald Group Publishing Limited.

  • Alkire, S. (2002). Dimensions of human development. World Development, 30(2), 181–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alkire, S. (2003). A Conceptual Framework for Human Security, CRISE Working Paper 2, Queen Elizabeth House, University of Oxford.

  • Amba-Rao, S. C. (1993). Multinational corporate social responsibility, ethics, interactions, third world governments: An agenda for the 19990s. Journal of Business Ethics, 12(7), 553–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Argandona, A. (1998). The stakeholder theory and the common good. Journal of Business Ethics, 7(9–10), 1093–1102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. (2010). Transnational corporations and the duty to respect basic human rights. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(3), 371–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. G., & Bowie, N. E. (2003). Sweatshops and respect for persons. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 221–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. G., Audi, R., & Zwolinski, M. (2010). Recent work in ethical theory and its implications for business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 559–581.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, S. B. (2010). Governing the global corporation: A critical perspective. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(2), 264–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bardy, R., Drew, S., & Kennedy, T. F. (2012). Foreign investment and ethics: How to contribute to social responsibility by doing business in less-developed countries. Journal of Business Ethics, 106(3), 267–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barley, S. R. (2007). Corporations, democracy, and the public good. Journal of Management Inquiry, 16(3), 201–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, P. (1974). Pyramids of sacrifice: Political ethics and social change. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (1998). Does business ethics rest on a mistake? Business Ethics Quarterly, 9(4), 583–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boatright, J. R. (2000). Globalization and the ethics of business. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BBC News. (2012). South Africa’s Lonmin Marikana Mine Clashes Killed 34. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/world-africa-19292909, Accessed Oct 31 2012.

  • Business Ethics Quarterly (BEQ). (2010). Anniversary reflections. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 711–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, E. (2012). Appropriating resources: Land claims, law, and illicit business. Journal of Business Ethics, 106(4), 453–466.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, J., & Ojha, K. (2007). A deliberative ethic for development: A Nepalese journey from Bourdieu through Kant to Dewey and Habermas. International Journal of Social Economics, 34(1/2), 66–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, J. S. (1974). Inequality, sociology, and moral philosophy. The American Journal of Sociology, 80(3), 739–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, D. (2000). The quest to improve the human condition: The First 1,500 articles published in the Journal of Business Ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 26(1), 1–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Commission on Human Security. (2003). Human Security Now. New York: United Nations Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotula, L. (2012). The international political economy of the global land rush: A critical appraisal of trends, scale, geography and drivers. The Journal of Peasant Studies, 39(3–4), 649–680.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cragg, C. (2012). Ethics, enlightened self-interest, and the corporate responsibility to respect human rights: A critical look at the justificatory foundations of the UN framework. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(1), 9–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cragg, C., Arnold, D., & Muchlinski, P. (2012). Human rights and business. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(1), 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crocker, D. A. (1991). Towards development ethics. World Development, 19(5), 457–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crocker, D. A. (1992). Functioning and capability; The foundations of Sen’s and Nussbaum’s development ethic. Political Theory, 20(4), 584–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crocker, D.A. (2006). Foreword, in Goulet’s Development Ethics at Work: Explorations19602002. London: Routledge.

  • Crocker, D. A. (2008). Ethics of global development: Agency, capability and deliberative democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Bakker, F. G. A., Groenewegen, P., & Den Hond, F. (2005). A bibliometric analysis of 30 years of research and theory on corporate social responsibility and corporate social performance. Business & Society, 44(3), 283–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De George, R. (2010). BEQ at twenty. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 722–723.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deneulin, S. (2011a). Development and the limits of Amartya Sen’s The Idea of Justice. Third World Quarterly, 32(4), 787–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deneulin, S. (2011b). Recovering Nussbaum’s Aristotelian Roots. Revista Cultura Económica, 81/82, 31–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dicken, P. (1994). Global-local tensions: Firms and states in the global space-economy. Economic Geography, 70(2), 101–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Djelic, M. L., & Quack, S. (2003). Theoretical building blocks for a research agenda linking globalization and institutions. In Djelic & Quack (Eds.), Globalization and institutions: Redefining the rules of the economic game. Northampton: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. (1985). Multinational decision-making: Reconciling international norms. Journal of Business Ethics, 4(4), 357–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. (2010). The values realignment in modern industrial society. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 728–729.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T., & Dunfee, T. W. (1994). Toward a unified conception of business ethics: Integrative social contracts theory. Academy of Management Review, 19(2), 252–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dower, N. (2008). The nature and scope of development ethics. Journal of Global Ethics, 4(3), 183–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doyal, L., & Gough, I. (1991). A theory of human need. Basingstoke: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drydyk, J. (2011). Development ethics. In D. Chatterjee (Ed.), Encyclopedia of global justice. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duska, R. (2010). BEQ’s twentieth anniversary: The evolution of business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 729–730.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferraro, F., Pfeffer, J., & Sutton, R. I. (2005). Economics language and assumptions: How theories can become self-fulfilling. Academy of Management Review, 30(1), 8–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fort, T. L. (2010). Business ethics quarterly reflections. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 736–738.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. E. (2000). Business ethics at the millennium. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10(1), 169–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, J. L., & Wokutch, R. E. (2005). Child workers, globalization and international business ethics: A case study in Brazil’s export-oriented shoe industry. Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(4), 615–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frynas, J. G. (2010). Corporate social responsibility and societal governance: Lessons from transparency in the oil and gas sector. Journal of Business Ethics, 93(2), 163–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galtung, J. (1979). The new international economic order and the basic needs approach. Alternatives: Global, Local, Political, 4, 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galtung, J. (1990). Cultural violence. Journal of Peace Research, 27(3), 291–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galtung, J. (2004). Imagining global democracy. Development and Change, 31(5), 1073–1079.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garriga, E., & Melé, D. (2004). Corporate social responsibility theories: Mapping the territory. Journal of Business Ethics, 53(1–2), 51–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (1996). Culture and development ethics: Needs, women’s rights, and Western theories. Development and Change, 27(4), 627–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (1997). Sen’s capability approach and Nussbaum’s capabilities ethic. Journal of International Development, 9(2), 281–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2004). The ethics of development. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2005). Securing humanity: situating ‘Human Security’ as concept and discourse. Journal of Human Development, 6(2), 221–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2007). Human rights, human needs, human development, human security: Relationships between four international ‘human’ discourses, Institute of Social Studies, Working Paper no. 445.

  • Gasper, D. (2008). Denis Goulet and the project of development ethics; choices in methodology, focus and organization. Journal of Human Development, 9(3), 453–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2010a). The idea of human security. In K. O’Brien, A. L. St Clair, & B. Kristoffersen (Eds.), Climate change, ethics and human security (pp. 23–46). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2010b). Understanding the diversity of conceptions of well-being and quality-of-life. Journal of Socio-Economics, 39(3), 351–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2012a). Development ethics—Why? What? How? A Formulation of the Field. Journal of Global Ethics, 8(1), 117–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2012b). Climate change—The need for a human rights agenda within a framework of shared human security. Social Research: An International Quarterly of the Social Sciences, 79(3), 983–1014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D. (2013). Logos, pathos and ethos in Martha Nussbaum’s capabilities approach to human development. In Flavio Comim & Martha Nussbaum (Eds.), Capabilities, gender, equality: Toward fundamental entitlements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D., & Truong, T. (2005). Deepening development ethics: From economism to human development to human security. European Journal of Development Research, 17(3), 372–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D., & Truong, T. (2010). Development ethics through the lenses of caring, gender, and human security. In S. Esquith & F. Gifford (Eds.), Capabilities, power and institutions: Towards a more critical development ethics. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasper, D., & van Staveren, I. (2003). Development as freedom—and as what else? Feminist Economics, 9(2–3), 137–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghosh, J. (2012). Demonizing Dissent, Frontline 29(23), Nov 17–30. http://www.frontlineonnet.com/fl2923/stories/20121130292304300.htm. Accessed Feb 4 2013.

  • Gilbert, D. U., & Behnam, M. (2008). Advancing integrative social contracts theory: A Habermasian perspective. Journal of Business Ethics, 89(2), 215–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D. U., & Rasche, A. (2007). Discourse ethics and social accountability—The ethics of SA 8000. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(2), 187–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glassman, J. (2011). The geo-political economy of global production networks. Geography Compass, 5(4), 154–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1968). Development for what. Comparative Political Studies, 1, 295–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1971). The cruel choice. New York: Athenaeum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1977). The Uncertain Promise. Values and Conflicts in Technology Transfer. New York: New Horizons Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1981a). In defense of cultural rights: Technology, tradition and conflicting models of rationality. Human Rights Quarterly, 3(4), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1981b). An international support system for meeting basic needs. The Review of Politics, 43(1), 22–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1983). Obstacles to world development: An ethical reflection. World Development, 11(7), 609–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1988). Tasks and methods in development ethics, Kellogg Institute. Cross Currents, 38(2), 146–163. Working Paper No. 106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1992). International ethics and human rights. Alternatives: Global, Local, Political, 17(2), 231–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (1997). Development ethics: A new discipline. International Journal of Social Economics, 24(11), 1160–1171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (2002). What is a just economy in a globalized world. International Journal of Social Economics, 29(1), 10–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goulet, D. (2006). Development ethics at work; explorations 1960–2002. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, R. (2009). The ethical rational of business for the poor—Integrating the concepts, bottom of the pyramid, sustainable development, and corporate citizenship. Journal of Business Ethics, 84(3), 313–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, L. P., Shaw, B., & Stevenson, R. (2003). Exploring the ethics and economics of global labor standards: A challenge to integrative social contract theory. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 193–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hay, C. (2005). Globalisation’s impact on states. In J. Ravenhill (Ed.), Global political economy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heath, J., Moriarty, J., & Norman, W. (2010). Business ethics and (or as) political philosophy. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(3), 427–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heugens, P. P. M. A. R., & Scherer, A. (2010). When organization theory met business ethics: Toward further symbioses. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 643–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heugens, P. P. M. A. R., Kaptein, M., & Van Oosterhout, J. (2006). Foundations and applications of contractualist business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 68(3), 211–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. (1997). The global economy—Myths and realities. International Affairs, 73(3), 409–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoksbergen, R. (1986). Approaches to evaluation of development interventions: The importance of world and life views. World Development, 14(2), 283–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, N. (2009). Does global business have a responsibility to promote just institutions? Business Ethics Quarterly, 19(2), 251–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husted, B. W., & Allen, D. B. (2000). Is it ethical to use ethics as strategy? Journal of Business Ethics, 27(1/2), 21–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeppesen, S., & Lund-Thomsen, P. (2010). Special issue on new perspectives on business, development, and society research. Journal of Business Ethics, 93(2), 139–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolly, R., & Basu Ray, D. (2007). Human security—National perspectives and global agendas. Journal of International Development, 19(4), 457–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, T. M. (2010). The future of business ethics research: Reflections on the twentieth anniversary of business ethics quarterly. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 746–747.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karnani, A. (2007). The mirage of marketing to the bottom of the pyramid: How the private sector can help alleviate poverty. California Management Review, 49(4), 90–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karnani, A. (2009). Romaticising the poor harms the poor. Journal of International Development, 21(1), 76–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemp, D., Owen, J. R., Gotzmann, N., & Bond, C. J. (2011). Just relations and company community conflict in mining. Journal of Business Ethics, 101(1), 93–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khan, F. R., Munir, K. A., & Willmott, H. (2007). A dark side of institutional entrepreneurship: Soccer balls, child labour and postcolonial impoverishment. Organization Studies, 28(7), 1055–1077.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khan, F. R., Westwood, R. I., & Boje, D. M. (2010). I Feel Like a Foreign Agent: NGOs and corporate social responsibility interventions into Third World child labour. Human Relations, 63(9), 1138–1417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kobrin, S. J. (2009). Private political authority and public responsibility: Transnational politics, transnational firms, and human rights. Business Ethics Quarterly, 19(3), 349–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D. (2008). Political contestation in global production networks. Academy of Management Review, 33(4), 943–963.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liotta, P. H., & Owen, T. (2006). Why human security? The Whitehead Journal of Diplomacy and International Relations, 7(1), 37–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maitland, I. (2004). The great non-debate over international sweatshops. In T. L. Beauchamp & N. E. Bowie (Eds.), Ethical Theory and Business (6th ed) (pp. 593–605). Englewood Cliffs: Pretence Hall.

  • Manning, S., F. Boons, O. von Hagen, J. Reinecke. (2011). National contexts matter: The co-evolution of sustainability standards in global value chains. Ecological Economics, http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.bbr.2011.03.031. Accessed, 10 Mar 2012.

  • Marens, R. (2007). Returning to rawls: Social contracting, social justice, and transcending the limitations of locke. Journal of Business Ethics, 75(1), 63–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marens, R. (2010). Speaking platitudes to power: observing American business ethics in an age of declining hegemony. Journal of Business Ethics, 94(2), 239–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. D., & Walsh, J. P. (2003). Misery loves companies: Rethinking social initiatives by business. Administrative Science Quarterly, 48(2), 655–689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, D., Argandona, A., & Sanchez-Runde, C. (2011). Facing the crisis: Towards a new humanistic synthesis for business. Journal of Business Ethics, 99(1), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mintzberg, H. (1990). The design school: Reconsidering the basic premises of strategic management. Strategic Management Journal, 11(3), 171–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moon, J., Crane, A., & Matten, D. (2005). Can corporations be citizens? Corporate citizenship as a metaphor for business participation in society. Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(3), 427–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naor, J. (1982). A new approach to multinational social responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics, 1(3), 219–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, P. (2008). CSR and the limits of capital. Development and Change, 39(6), 1063–1078.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1986). The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1992). Human functioning and social justice: In defense of Aristotelian essentialism. Political Theory, 20(2), 202–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2004). Beyond the social contract: Capabilities and global justice. Oxford Development Studies, 32(1), 3–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2006a). Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2006b). Reply: In defense of global political liberalism. Development and Change, 37(6), 1227–1334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2011a). Creating capabilities: The human development approach. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2011b). Perfectionist liberalism and political liberalism. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39(1), 3–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M., & Sen, A. K. (Eds.). (1993). The Quality of Life. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (1986). Faces of hunger. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pahle, S. (2010). The rise and demise of the ‘Social Clause’ proposal in the 1990s: Implications of a discourse theoretical reading. Labor History, 51(3), 389–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penz, P., Drydyk, J., & Bose, P. (2011). Displacement by development—Ethics, rights and responsibilities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Petras, J. (2008). Global ruling class: Billionaires and how they “Make It”. Journal of Contemporary Asia, 38(2), 319–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. (2011). The individual and the social: A comparative study of quality of life, social quality and human development approaches. International Journal of Social Quality, 1(1), 71–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, T. (2003). World poverty and human rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Powell, T. C. (2001). Competitive advantage: Logical and philosophical considerations. Strategic Management Journal, 22(9), 875–888.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Powell, T. C. (2002). The philosophy of strategy. Strategic Management Journal, 23(9), 873–880.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prahalad, C. K., & Hammond, A. (2002). Serving the world’s poor profitably. Harvard Business Review, 80(9), 48–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, C. B. (1991). Multinational corporate social policy process for ethical responsibility in Sub-Saharan Africa. Journal of Business Ethics, 10(7), 527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Qizilbash, M. (1996). Ethical development. World Development, 24(7), 1209–1221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Qizilbash, M. (1998). The concept of well-BEING. Economics and Philosophy, 14, 51–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rajak, D. (2010). HIV/AIDS is Our Business’: The moral economy of treatment in a transnational mining company. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 16(3), 551–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Randeria, S. (2003). Glocalization of law: Environmental justice, World Bank, NGOs and the Cunning State in India. Current Sociology, 51(3/4), 305–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sassen, S. (2000). The need to distinguish denationalized and postnational. Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies, 7(2), 575–584.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sassen, S. (2010). A savage sorting of winners and losers: Contemporary versions of primitive accumulation. Globalizations, 7(1–2), 23–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A., & Palazzo, G. (2011). The new political role of business in a globalized world: A review of a new perspective on CSR and its implications for the firm, governance, and democracy. Journal of Management Studies, 48(4), 899–931.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A. G., Palazzo, G., & Matten, D. (2009). Introduction to the special issue: Globalization as a challenge for business responsibilities. Business Ethics Quarterly, 19(3), 327–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwenke, C. (2009). Reclaiming values in international development. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1987). On Ethics and economics. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Sen, A. K. (1999a). Commodities and capabilities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Sen, A. K. (1999b). Development as freedom. New York: Knopf Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (2009). The idea of justice. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sisón, A. J. G., & Fontrodona, J. (2012). The common good of the firm in the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition. Business Ethics Quarterly, 31(2), 211–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • St. Clair, L. A. (2006). Global poverty: Development ethics meets global justice. Globalizations, 3(2), 139–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, F. (1989). Basic needs strategies, human rights, and the right to development. World Development, 11, 347–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streeten, P. (1980). Basic needs and human rights. World Development, 8, 107–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streeten, P., et al. (1981). First things first. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Streeten, P. (1984). Basic needs: Some unsettled questions. World Development, 12, 973–978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talukdar, D. (2011). Patterns of research productivity in the business ethics literature: Insights from analyses of bibliometric distributions. Journal of Business Ethics, 98(1), 137–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teltumbde, A. (2012). The ‘Maoists’ of Manesar. Economic and Political Weekly, 34, 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Truong, T. (2009). Feminist Knowledge and Human Security: Bridging Rifts through the Epistemology of Care, Institute of Social Studies, Working Paper No. 481.

  • United Nations (UN). (2007). Business and Human Rights: Mapping International Standards of Responsibility and Accountability for Corporate Acts. UN Doc A/HRC/4/035.

  • United Nations (UN). (2008). Protect, Respect and Remedy: A Framework for Business and Human Rights. UN Doc A/HRC/8/5.

  • United Nations Development Programme (UNDP). (1994). Human Development Report. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Utting, P., & Zammit, A. (2009). United Nations-business partnerships: Good intentions and contradictory agendas. Journal of Business Ethics, 90(1), 39–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Oosterhout, J. (2010). The role of corporations in shaping the global rules of the game: In search of new foundations. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(2), 253–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, E. (1998). The Bankruptcy crisis. Indiana Law Journal, 73(4), 1079–1101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. H. (2000). Exporting mental models: Global capitalism in the 21st century. Business Ethics Quarterly, 10(1), 353–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. H. (2010). Principles and practices for corporate responsibility. Business Ethics Quarterly, 20(4), 695–701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werhane, P. H., Kelley, S. P., Hartman, L., & Moberg, D. J. (2010). Alleviating poverty through profitable partnerships: Globalization, markets, and economic well-being. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, F. (2010). The duty to protect: Corporate complicity, political responsibility, and human rights advocacy. Journal of Business Ethics, 96(1), 33–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, F. (2012). Silence as complicity: Elements of a corporate duty to speak out against the violation of human rights. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(1), 37–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wicks, A., Freeman, R. E., Werhane, P. H., & Martin, K. E. (2010). Business ethics: A managerial perspective. New Jersey: Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worden, S. (2009). A genealogy of business ethics: A Nietzschean Perspective. Journal of Business Ethics, 84(3), 427–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wry, T. E. (2009). Does business and society scholarship matter to society? Pursuing a normative agenda with critical realism and neoinsitutional theory. Journal of Business Ethics, 89(2), 151–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Prabhir Vishnu Poruthiyil.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Poruthiyil, P.V. Weaning Business Ethics from Strategic Economism: The Development Ethics Perspective. J Bus Ethics 116, 735–749 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-1818-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-1818-8

Keywords

Navigation