Skip to main content
Log in

Using Natural-Kind Essentialism to Defend Dispositionalism

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

An Erratum to this article was published on 26 September 2013

Abstract

Marc Lange and Ann Whittle have independently developed an important challenge to dispositionalism, arguing that dispositions are reducible to primitive subjunctive facts. I argue in reply that by pairing dispositionalism with a certain version of natural-kind essentialism, their objection can be overcome. Moreover, such a marriage carries further advantages for the dispositionalist. My aim is therefore two-fold: to defend dispositionalism, and to give the dispositionalist some new motivation to adopt natural-kind essentialism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For recent presentations of categoricalism consult for instance Armstrong (2010) and Psillos (2006).

  2. For his own expositions consult for instance his (2004, 2009a, b, forthcoming).

  3. For detailed discussion see Mumford (1998, Chap. 3 and 4).

  4. See Handfield (2005).

  5. Laid out in detail in his previously cited works.

  6. “In this paper, it [nominalism] is taken to be the conjunction of two theses. The first is the standard claim that everything that exists is particular, so there are no entities that exist in more than one place at the same time. The second asserts that there are no basic property instances or tropes.” (2009, p. 244).

  7. And though it is a challenge for all dispositionalists, it may be especially troubling to pan-dispositionalists, as their entire ontology of properties would collapse.

  8. See especially his (2006, 2007b).

  9. See for instance Lange (2009b, pp. 37–42).

  10. “The laws of nature will explain why-necessarily-there are no members of chemical and microphysical kinds that lack certain properties, why of necessity certain properties cluster together in a partially or fully precise manner.” (2007, p. 211) This does not sit comfortably with Bird’s larger dispositionalist ontology.

  11. Among the other advocates of this view are assorted Thomists and other neo-Scholastics who, unfortunately, tend not to engage much with the analytic literature on essentialism. Besides Oderberg, members of these schools who have made such an engagement include Beards (2008), Freddoso (1986), Klima (2002), Kronen (1991), and O’Callaghan (2008).

  12. Or point-like, depending on where one stands on the question of whether fundamental particles are literally indivisible.

  13. For early formulations, see Dretske (1977), Tooley (1977), and Armstrong (1983).

  14. See my “Natural-Kind Essentialism and the Operator Theory of Instantiation” (manuscript). This issue is also a chief focus of Oderberg (2011).

  15. So it does not arise for pan-dispositionalists like Bird (2007, 2009) and Bostock (2008). Or at least, it does not arise in the same form. They are in fact faced with an even more vexing problem, namely how to reduce all categorical properties to dispositional properties. It is also worth noting that given their rejection of basic categorical properties, my reply to Lange and Whittle’s reductionism will not work for pan-dispositionalists.

  16. Only on certain versions though; Oderberg’s (2007) hylomorphism could be classed (roughly) as a kind of substratum/attribute theory, and yet that theory’s substratum, prime matter, cannot play this unifying role (for reasons that would take too long to go into here). This is yet another reason for positing natural-kind essences—or substantial forms, on his preferred terminology—within that system.

  17. Reference could also be made to external laws of nature that govern the co-instantiation of properties. But since most dispositionalists want to say that the laws of nature are grounded in dispositions, this would not be an option for them.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (2010). Sketch for a systematic metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beards, A. (2008). Method in metaphysics: Lonergan and the future of analytic philosophy. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2009). Structural properties revisited. In T. Handfield (Ed.), Dispositions and causes (pp. 215–241). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bostock, S. (2008). A defence of pan-dispositionalism. Metaphysica, 9, 139–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). Inessential Aristotle: Powers without essences. In R. Groff (Ed.), Revitalizing causality: Realism about causality in philosophy and social science (pp. 152–162). London: Routledge.

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44, 248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. (2004). Real natures and familiar objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. (2007). Realism and the problem of Infimae Species. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 111–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Handfield, T. (2005). Lange on essentialism, counterfactuals, and explanation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 83, 81–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klima, G. (2002). Contemporary ‘Essentialism’ vs. Aristotelian Essentialism. In J. Haldane (ed.), Mind, metaphysics, and value in the thomistic and analytic traditions. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press

  • Kronen, J. (1991). Essentialism old and new: Suarez and Brody. Modern Schoolman, 58, 123–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2004). A note on scientific essentialism, laws of nature, and counterfactual conditionals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 227–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009a). Why do the laws explain why? In T. Handfield (Ed.), Dispositions and causes (pp. 286–321). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Lange, M. (2009b). Laws and lawmakers: Science, metaphysics, and the laws of nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2011). It takes more than all kinds to make a world. In J. Campbell, M. O'Rourke & M. Slater (Eds.), Carving nature at its joints: Natural kinds in metaphysics and science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Loux, M. (2002). Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald, C. (2005). Varieties of things: Foundations of contemporary metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, (1998). Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, (2004). Laws in nature. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, (2006). The ungrounded argument. Synthese, 149, 471–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford. (2007a). Powers, dispositions, properties or a causal realist manifesto. In R. Groff (Ed.), Revitalizing causality: Realism about causality in philosophy and social science (pp. 139–151). London: Routledge.

  • Mumford. (2007b). Filling in space. In M Kistler & B. Gnassounou (Eds.), Dispositions and causal powers (pp. 67–80). Aldershot: Ashgate.

  • O’Callaghan, J. (2008). The plurality of forms: Now and then. Review of Metaphysics, 62, 3–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. (2007). Real essentialism. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. (2011). Essence and properties. Erkenntnis, 75, 85–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2006). What do powers do when they are not manifested? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72, 137–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1980). Causality and properties. In: P. Van Inwagen (Ed.), Time and cause (pp. 109–135). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Shoemaker, S. (1998). Causal and metaphysical necessity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 79, 59–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 667–698.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whittle, A. (2009). Causal nominalism. In: T. Handfield (Ed.), Dispositions and causes (pp. 242–285). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Withheld for blind review.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Travis Dumsday.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dumsday, T. Using Natural-Kind Essentialism to Defend Dispositionalism. Erkenn 78, 869–880 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-012-9361-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-012-9361-z

Keywords

Navigation