Skip to main content
Log in

Local Selective Realism: Shifting from Classical to Quantum Electrodynamics

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article elaborates local selective realism in view of the shifting from classical to quantum electrodynamics. After some introductory remarks, we critically address what we call global selective realism, hence setting forth the background for outlining local selective realism. When examining the transition from classical to quantum electrodynamics, we evaluate both continuities and discontinuities in observational features, mathematical structures, and ontological presuppositions. Our argument leads us to criticise the narrow understanding of limiting-case strategies, and to reject the claim that we need a fully coherent theoretical framework to account for the transition from one theory to its successor in the case of electrodynamics. We close with a few remarks on the scope of local selective realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Among others, Saatsi (2017) observes that selective versions of scientific realism dominate the debate. Saatsi develops his own exemplar realism, which takes realism to be an attitude that should be applied locally by specifying the exemplar in each case. Below, differences between local selective realism and other forms of selective realism will become clear.

  2. We greatly thank one of the referees for helping us to make this point clear throughout the article.

  3. We thank one of the referees for directing our attention to this passage from Maxwell.

  4. Note that beyond the variables of the set of equations above, the mathematics in the Fresnel–Maxwell case involves various theoretical assumptions: (a) the minimal mechanical assumption that the velocity of the displacement of molecules of ether is proportional to the amplitude of the light wave; (b) the principle of conservation of energy during the propagation of light in the two media; and (c) the geometrical analysis of the configuration of the light-rays in the interface of two media (Psillos 1999).

  5. Although neither Planck’s work on black-body radiation nor Einstein’s on the photoelectric effect amount to complete theories of electromagnetism, they certainly provided new theoretical elements that played a crucial part in the transition from CED to QED. Such elements could also be targets of the PMI against a smooth transition from CED to QED. Taking these elements into consideration helps us point out traces of continuities or discontinuities in a piecemeal fashion in the present case.

  6. The following lines summarise ideas taken from Weinberg (2005). Similar approaches appear in Greiner (2000), Sect. 15.5, pp. 364–366, Frisch (2005), p. 16 and Rohrlich (1988).

  7. Any term with higher derivatives or higher order in \(F_{\mu \nu }\) can be included in the matter action \(I_M\).

  8. It is not possible to re-obtain the whole of classical mechanics from quantum mechanics by taking the limit of \(\hbar \) to zero. The latter claim is true for only a—limited—number of results. More to the point, as quantum field theory is a perturbation theory where calculations are performed by means of expansion in powers of the fine structure constant (which is inversely proportional to \(\hbar \)), the limit \(\hbar \) to zero cannot be performed in quantum field theory. We thank one of the referees for bringing our attention to this point.

  9. Note that the previous discussion overlaps with the larger debate concerning theory reduction. The limiting-case strategy belongs to a case of “domain preserving reduction” (Nickles 1973). Yet, this is not the only form of theory reduction, as other cases of theory reduction would involve the explanation of one theory by another (or domain combined reduction, following (Nickles 1973) once more). The case at hand is a complex one of “domain combined reduction” that includes “domain preserving reduction” as well. It is not our intention to dive into the theory reduction debate. But the point we want to make is that a narrow understanding of the limiting-case strategy overlooks complexities associated with exactly these considerations. As Nickles points out: “I am not advancing the simplistic view that all or even most historical reductions fit neatly into one or the other of the schemata. For one thing, many of the reductions will be partial; for another, [domain combined] reduction is rarely strictly derivational” (Nickles 1973, p. 186). We thank one of the referees for suggesting Nickles’ work in view of our argument.

References

  • Arons, A., & Peppard, M. (1965). Einstein’s proposal of the photon concept-a translation of the annalen der physik paper of 1905. American Journal of Physics, 33(5), 367–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asay, J. (2019). Going local: A defense of methodological localism about scientific realism. Synthese, 196, 587–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darrigol, O. (2012). A history of optics from Greek antiquity to the nineteenth century. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyson, F. J. (2007). Why is Maxwell’s theory so hard to understand? In The second European conference on antennas and propagation, 2007. EuCAP 2007 (pp. 1–6). IET.

  • French, S. (2014). The structure of the world: Metaphysics and representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (2005). Inconsistency, asymmetry, and non-locality: A philosophical investigation of classical electrodynamics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greiner, W. (2000). Relativistic quantum mechanics. Wave equations. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haag, R. (2012). Local quantum physics: Fields, particles, algebras. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, L. (2017). Global versus local arguments for realism. In J. Saatsi (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of scientific realism. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurrett, D., & Collier, J. G. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University. (press on demand).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2002). Introduction to the philosophy of physics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyre, H. (2004). Holism and structuralism in u (1) gauge theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 35(4), 643–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1995). Taking naturalism seriously. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 134, 383–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, J. C. (1873). A treatise on electricity and magnetism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2000). Unifying scientific theories: Physical concepts and mathematical structures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1973). Two concepts of intertheoretic reduction. The Journal of Philosophy, 70(7), 181–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Rahilly, A. (1965). Electromagnetic theory: A critical examination of fundamentals (Vol. 2). Dover Publications: Constable.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2011). Mathematical structural realism. Scientific Structuralism, 67–79.

  • Psillos, S. (1995). Is structural realism the best of both worlds? Dialectica, 49(1), 15–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohrlich, F. (1988). Pluralistic ontology and theory reduction in the physical sciences. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39(3), 295–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rohrlich, F., & Hardin, L. (1983). Established theories. Philosophy of Science, 50(4), 603–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romero-Maltrana, D., Benitez, F., & Soto, C. (2018). A proposal for a coherent ontology of fundamental entities. Foundations of Science, 23, 705–717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2017). Replacing recipe realism. Synthese, 194(9), 3233–3244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tipler, P. (1976). Physics. New York: Worth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valente, M. B. (2011). The relation between classical and quantum electrodynamics. THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 26(1), 51–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (2005). The quantum theory of fields: Foundations (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43(1–2), 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Diego Romero-Maltrana.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

On behalf of all authors, the corresponding author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article is a partial result of research carried out within the framework of governmental funded Grants FONDECYT de Iniciación No. 11160324, “The Physico-Mathematical Structure of Scientific Laws: On the Roles of Mathematics, Models, Measurements and Metaphysics in the Construction of Laws in Physics”, responsible investigator: Dr. Cristian Soto; and FONDECYT Regular No. 1150661, “Masa, emergencia y realismo estructural”, responsible investigator, Dr. Diego Romero-Maltrana. We thank their financial support. Likewise, we are deeply grateful to two referees for Foundations of Science. They helped us work through the details of our own views, providing invaluable feedback on ways to improve our argument.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Soto, C., Romero-Maltrana, D. Local Selective Realism: Shifting from Classical to Quantum Electrodynamics. Found Sci 25, 955–970 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09663-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09663-3

Keywords

Navigation