Skip to main content
Log in

Does Scientific Progress Consist in Increasing Knowledge or Understanding?

  • Discussion
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Bird (2007) argues that scientific progress consists in increasing knowledge. Dellsén (2016a) objects that increasing knowledge is neither necessary nor sufficient for scientific progress, and argues that scientific progress rather consists in increasing understanding. Dellsén also contends that unlike Bird’s view, his view can account for the scientific practices of using idealizations and of choosing simple theories over complex ones. I argue that Dellsén’s criticisms against Bird’s view fail, and that increasing understanding cannot account for scientific progress, if acceptance, as opposed to belief, is required for scientific understanding.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. ‘Noetic’ comes from the Greek ‘nous’ which means understanding (Dellsén 2016a, b: 72, footnote 2).

  2. See Rowbottom (2010), Niiniluoto (2015), and Saatsi (2016) for other criticisms against the epistemic approach.

  3. Bird conjectures, a referee points out, that “the relevant developments that promote knowledge will themselves be knowledge” (2007, 84). In my view, however, Bird seems to mean gathering observational knowledge by ‘the relevant developments.’ In any event, the epistemic approach requires only the mean-end thesis.

  4. Should they believe that Newtonian mechanics is true? Dellsén would say no, but I (2015: 226–228; 2016: 77–78; 2017: 59–60) argue that problems arise when we explain something in terms of a scientific theory without believing that it is (approximately) true. This paper, however, assumes for the sake of argument that Dellsén is right, i.e., that it is legitimate merely to accept a scientific theory and then use it to explain phenomena.

  5. Approximate knowledge concerns an approximately true proposition. Suppose, for example, that I know that Alice is 170.1 cm. Then, I approximately know that she is 170 cm.

References

  • Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs, 41(1), 64–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. J. (1992). An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellsén, F. (2016a). Scientific progress: Knowledge vs. understanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 72–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dellsén, F. (2016b). Understanding without Justification or Belief. Ratio. doi:10.1111/rati.12134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1905/1956). Investigations on the theory of the Brownian movement (A. D. Cowper, Trans.). New York: Dover.

  • Grimm, S. (2006). Is understanding a species of knowledge? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 515–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2014). Understanding as knowledge of causes. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue epistemology naturalized: Bridges between virtue epistemology and philosophy of science. Synthese Library (Vol. 366, pp. 329–345). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Kitcher, P. (2002). Scientific knowledge. In P. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 385–408). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1962/1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1980). Is science progressive?. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2014). Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 46, 73–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2015). Optimistic realism about scientific progress. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0974-z.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2015). Accepting our best scientific theories. Filosofija. Sociologija, 26(3), 218–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2016). Scientific realism and antirealism in science education. Coactivity: Philosophy Communication, 24(1), 72–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Park, S. (2017). Defense of epistemic reciprocalism. Filosofija Sociologija, 28(1), 56–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowbottom, D. (2010). What scientific progress is not: Against Bird’s epistemic view. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 24(3), 241–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2016). What is theoretical progress of science? Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1118-9.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper improved a lot thanks to the insightful comments from anonymous referees and Prof. Beisbart.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Seungbae Park.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Park, S. Does Scientific Progress Consist in Increasing Knowledge or Understanding?. J Gen Philos Sci 48, 569–579 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9363-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-017-9363-2

Keywords

Navigation