Skip to main content
Log in

Walter Benjamin and the Re-Imageination of International Law

  • Published:
Law and Critique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Drawing on the work of Walter Benjamin, Harold Bloom, and Theodor Adorno this article proposes the re-imageination of international law as a ‘pure means’ of representation rather than a means of exercising control over the world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Koskenniemi (2005, p. 59) on “ascending” and “descending” styles of legal argument.

  2. Benjamin (2004a, p. 239): ‘the law’s interest in a monopoly of violence vis-à-vis individuals is explained not by the intention of preserving legal ends but, rather, by the intention of preserving the law itself’.

  3. See International Law Commission (2006b, p. 14, para. 14): ‘although there are “problems”, they are neither altogether new nor of such nature that they could not be dealt with through techniques international lawyers have used to deal with the normative conflicts that have arisen in the past’.

  4. Ibid (p. 17, para. 20).

  5. See Benjamin (2002, p. 462, N2a,3): ‘image is dialectics at a standstill. For while the relation of the present to the past is a purely temporal, continuous one, the relation of what-has-been to the now is dialectical: is not progression but image, suddenly emergent. – Only dialectical images are genuine images (that is, not archaic); and the place where one encounters them is language. Awakening’; see also Parfitt (2014, p. 297) on ‘a revolutionary re-imagining of the discipline’ as a means of overcoming international law’s Eurocentrism. My use of ‘re-imageination’, as opposed to ‘re-imagination’, conveys the distinctly Benjamin character of the approach advocated.

  6. See Benjamin (1998, p. 27): ‘It is characteristic of philosophical writing that it must continually confront the question of representation’.

  7. Bloom (1997, p. xix): ‘great writing is always at work strongly (or weakly) misreading previous writing’; Bloom (1997, p. 5): ‘Poetic history … is held to be indistinguishable from poetic influence, since strong poets make that history by misreading one another, so as to clear imaginative space for themselves’.

  8. Marks (2006, p. 346): ‘Bloom coined the phrase “anxiety of influence” to refer to the shock felt by poets when they recognize the influence of their precursors in their work, and their despair at ever being able to come up with anything original. At the same time, it refers to the things they do to overcome this sense of belatedness in relation to the tradition to which they belong’.

  9. See the opening Fry quotation; see also Adorno (2007, p. 281): ‘the role, the heteronomy prescribed by autonomy, is the latest objective form of an unhappy consciousness’.

  10. Adorno (2007, p. 309): ‘In law the formal principle of equivalence becomes the norm; everyone is treated alike … For the sake of an unbroken systematic, the legal norms cut short what is not covered … The total legal realm is one of definitions. Its systematic forbids the admission of anything that eludes their closed circle … These bounds, ideological in themselves, turn into real violence as they are sanctioned by law as the socially controlling authority’.

  11. See Benjamin (1998, p. 119) on ‘the onlooker’: ‘He learns how, on the stage, a space which belongs to an inner world of feeling and bears no relationship to the cosmos, situations are compellingly presented to him.’

  12. See Benjamin quotation in n. 5 above.

  13. Benjamin (2004a, p. 247): ‘Since, however, every conceivable solution to human problems, not to speak of deliverance from the confines of all the world-historical conditions of existence obtaining hitherto, remains impossible if violence is totally excluded in principle, the question necessarily arises as to what kinds of violence exist other than all those envisaged by legal theory.’ On means-ends thinking and law’s violence see Benjamin (2004a, p. 236), and the discussion below at nn. 46–49.

  14. See Jenkins (2005, p. 252) on ‘a self-effacing mode of practice’; see also Jenkins (2012, p. 178) on the notion of ‘a law that forces nothing on those who receive it’ and, on Jenkins (2012), see my article (Nicholson 2014).

  15. See Benjamin (2005a, pp. 771–772): ‘[T]he conventional distinction between author and public… begins … to disappear … the reader is at all times ready to become a writer—that is, a describer, or even a prescriber’; Knox (2011, p. 46): ‘in a sense, we are all lawyers’; Feyerabend (2010, xxvii): ‘non-experts often know more than experts and should therefore be consulted, and … prophets of truth (including those who use arguments) more often than not are carried along by a vision that clashes with the very events the vision is supposed to be exploring’; Charlesworth (2002, p. 391): ‘An international law of everyday life would require a methodology to consider the perspectives of non-elite groups’; Anghie (2004, p. 318): ‘I continue to hope … that international law can be transformed into a means by which the marginalized may be empowered. In short, that law can play its ideal role in limiting and resisting power.’

  16. Parfitt (2014, p. 304): ‘[the] contextualist approach [advocated by Anne Orford] … is … in danger of throwing the baby out with the bathwater and, in particular, of abandoning its commitment to emancipatory change’. At pp. 305-6 Parfitt concludes that there is no such abandonment in Orford’s work.

  17. Parfitt (2014, pp. 304-5) reads Benjamin, through Tomlins (2012), in a way that indicates continuity between Benjamin’s thought and Orford’s conceptualisation of international law as ‘the art of making meaning move across time’ (Orford, 2013, p. 172).

  18. See Parfitt (2014, p. 297) for a similar point: ‘if “doctrine” can be understood as the space in which international history is transformed, or “imaged”, into international legal history … then it would seem that doctrine is where the process of revolutionary re-imagination and re-ordering must begin.’

  19. See Benjamin quotation in n 5 above; on historical materialist method see Benjamin (1999, p. 254): ‘A historical materialist cannot do without the notion of a present which is not a transition, but in which time stands still and has come to a stop. For this notion defines the present in which he himself is writing history … The historical materialist … remains in control of his powers, man enough to blast open the continuum of history.’ The anachronistic, gendered language of this passage is to be regretted. I read it as an affirmation of the capacity of individual, materialistic-idealistic practice to disturb established, historical patterns. On the tension between idealism and materialism in Benjamin see Buck-Morss (1991, pp. 173–177), who treats Benjamin as a critic of idealism and allegory as an idealistic form of practice, and Pensky (1993, pp. 148-150) who, contra Buck-Morss, treats Benjamin as a cautious advocate of a materialistic-idealism and Benjamin’s work on allegory as the expression of that idealism. On the basis outlined in the latter sections of this article, I prefer Pensky’s view and read Benjamin as a theorist and advocate of allegory as a mode of practice which is the expression, per Pensky (1993, p. 150), of ‘a fragile, productive critical subjectivity’.

  20. See Sontag (1983, p. 104): ‘What is important now is to recover our senses. We must learn to see more, to hear more, to feel more.’

  21. Benjamin (1999, p. 249): ‘A Klee painting named ‘Angelus Novus’ shows an angel looking as though he is about to move away from something he is fixedly contemplating. His eyes are open, his mouth is open, his wings are spread. This is how one pictures the angel of history. His face is turned towards the past. Where we perceive a chain of events, he sees one single catastrophe which keeps piling wreckage upon wreckage and hurls it in front of his feet. The angel would like to stay, awaken the dead, and make whole what has been smashed. But a storm is blowing from Paradise; it has got caught in his wings with such violence that the angel can no longer close them. This storm irresistibly propels him into the future to which his back is turned, while the pile of debris before him grows skyward. This storm is what we call progress’; Benjamin (2002, p. 473, N9a, 1): ‘The concept of progress must be grounded in the idea of catastrophe. That things are “status quo” is the catastrophe.’

  22. See Adorno quotation in n. 10 above.

  23. See Orford (2004, p. 444): ‘one of the traditional strategies by which international lawyers respond to [a] … pervading crisis of authority [is] … through an attempt to reassert control or mastery’.

  24. See Horkheimer (2004, p. 52): ‘the positivists reiterate that science proceeds by observation and describe circumstantially how it functions… they will say that it is not their concern to justify or prove the principle of verification—that they merely want to talk scientific [or legal] sense … [but] in refusing to verify their own principle—that no statement is meaningful unless verified—they are guilty of petitio principii, begging the question.’

  25. See also Koller (2012, pp. 99–105) on international law’s ‘journey’ along a ‘line of progress’, and Johns et al. (2011, p. 2) on ‘stringing events together into evolutionary narratives’ and international law’s ‘collective disciplinary past'.

  26. See text to n. 4 above.

  27. See, in particular, Judge Greenwood (ICJ 2010c, para. 29): ‘Courts and tribunals are necessarily required to focus for most of the time upon the events of the past … the Court has concluded that Uruguay’s conduct to date has violated its substantive obligations and that the declaration of a procedural breach is the only remedy which it is appropriate for the Court to grant.’

  28. I am grateful to Professor Martti Koskenniemi for his suggestion that I consider these ICSID claims. See Waibel (2007) for background.

  29. See Charlesworth (2002, p. 391): ‘Through regarding “crises” as its bread and butter and the engine of progressive development of international law, international law becomes simply a source of justification for the status quo.’

  30. See French and Rajamani (2013, p. 460): ‘how often, and how far, does climate change legal literature truly ever question the underlying purpose of the climate change regime; to posit any form of heresy as to its long-term normative sustainability?… most work rarely questions the purpose and value of the overarching regime itself’, and see p. 461: ‘The present diplomatic negotiations … are a process that we feel compelled, as both commentators and participants, to believe to be heading somewhere.’

  31. See Adorno quotation in n. 10 above.

  32. On ‘reflection’ see Adorno (2007, p. 12): ‘Philosophical reflection makes sure of the nonconceptual in the concept’; and see Adorno (2007, p. 365): ‘If negative dialectics calls for the self-reflection of thinking, the tangible implication is that if thinking is to be true—if it is to be true today, in any case—it must also be a thinking against itself.’

  33. See Marks (2006, p. 347): ‘when we treat international law as a redemptive force that could save the world if only it were properly respected and enforced, we obscure the possibility that international legal norms may themselves have contributed to creating or sustaining the ills from which we are now to be saved’.

  34. On anthropocentrism in international environmental law see Gillespie (2010, p. 118) and Natarajan and Khoday (2014); on international human rights law and the natural environment see Francioni (2010).

  35. See n 15.

  36. On the Benjaminian practice of legal history see Tomlins (2012). Tomlins, in my view, misreads Benjamin in claiming that a central concept in Benjamin’s thought - the ‘dialectical image’—whilst ‘[sensitive] to the fragmentary nature of what is apprehended … [holds] the possibility of completing the comprehension of truth content by critique, by theory, render[ing] it an antidote to indeterminacy and complexity’—Tomlins (2012, p. 57)—overlooking the importance of the ‘idea’, as a frame situated in practice and remade through practice and failing to appreciate the nature of the dialectical image, not as an ‘antidote to indeterminacy and complexity’, but, via an allegorical method, as the most truthful, real account of reality.

  37. Adorno (2005a, p. 265): ‘The primacy of the object must be respected by praxis’; Benjamin (1998, p. 30): ‘Again and again the statement that the object of knowledge is not identical with the truth will prove itself to be one of the profoundest intentions of philosophy in its original form, the Platonic theory of ideas’; Benjamin (1998, p. 28): ‘Inasmuch as it is determined by [the] concept of system, philosophy is in danger of accommodating itself to a syncretism which weaves a spider’s web between separate kinds of knowledge in an attempt to ensnare the truth as if it were something which came flying in from outside.’

  38. See Benjamin (1998, pp. 162–165), rejecting a symbolic concept of language and its attempt to contain reality in favour of allegory—and on that rejection see Finkelde (2009, p. 60); Benjamin (2005b, p. 718): ‘The symbol is definable as a sign by means of which no similarity can appear’; see also Benjamin (1998, p. 27): ‘It is characteristic of philosophical writing that it must continually confront the question of representation … The more clearly mathematics demonstrate that the total elimination of the problem of representation … is the sign of genuine knowledge, the more conclusively does it reveal its renunciation of that area of truth towards which language is directed.’

  39. See Benjamin (2004b, p. 74) on ‘imperfect’ language; Adorno (2004, p. 184): ‘The comportment of artworks reflects the violence and domination of empirical reality by more than analogy. The closure of artworks, as the unity of their multiplicity, directly transfers the nature-dominating comportment to something remote from its reality.’

  40. See Adorno (2005b, p. 50): ‘The whole is the false’; see also Adorno and Horkheimer (2011, p. 71): ‘[t]rue thought is thought that has no wish to insist on being in the right’.

  41. See Marks (2007, p. 208): ‘there can be no expectation that [international law] … will one day be placed beyond ideology or made ideology-proof … The work of critique is never done.’

  42. Benjamin (2004a, p. 247): ‘every conceivable solution to human problems, not to speak of deliverance from the confines of all the world-historical conditions of existence obtaining hitherto, remains impossible if violence is totally excluded in principle’.

  43. Benjamin (1998, pp. 28–29): ‘Just as mosaics preserve their majesty despite their fragmentation into capricious particles, so philosophical contemplation is not lacking in momentum … The value of fragments of thought is all the greater the less direct their relationship to the underlying idea, and the brilliance of the representation depends as much on this value as the brilliance of the mosaic does on the quality of the glass paste’.

  44. Adorno (2004, p. 187): ‘Form is … conceived as something superimposed, subjectively dictated, whereas it is substantial only when it does no violence to what is formed and emerges from it.’

  45. See Benjamin (2004a, p. 239): ‘the law’s interest in a monopoly of violence vis-à-vis individuals is explained not by the intention of preserving legal ends but, rather, by the intention of preserving the law itself’.

  46. Ibid (p. 236): ‘The task of a critique of violence can be summarized as that of expounding its relation to law and justice … it is clear that the most elementary relationship within any legal system is that of ends to means’; see also Honneth (2009), p. 98).

  47. Ibid (p. 248): ‘at [the] very moment of lawmaking, it specifically establishes as law not an end unalloyed by violence but one necessarily and intimately bound to it, under the title of power. Lawmaking is powermaking, assumption of power, and to that extent an immediate manifestation of violence.’

  48. Ibid: ‘lawmaking pursues as its end, with violence as the means, what is to be established as law’.

  49. See also ibid (p. 239): ‘violence, when not in the hands of the law, threatens it not by the ends that it may pursue but by its mere existence outside the law’.

  50. Ginzberg (1911, pp. 299–300): ‘Not until after the Resurrection will their punishment cease, for even in spite of their grave sin they were not given over to eternal damnation’; Benjamin (2004a, p. 250): ‘it is justifiable to call this [divine] violence … annihilating; but it is so only relatively, with regard to goods, right, life, and suchlike, never absolutely, with regard to the soul of the living’.

  51. Benjamin (2004a, p. 251): ‘The proposition that existence stands higher than a just existence is false and ignominious, if existence is to mean nothing other than mere life’; See Butler (2006, p. 216): ‘positive law vanquishes life and its necessary transience, both its suffering and its happiness’.

  52. On ‘the now’ see Benjamin quotation in n 5 above.

  53. See Benjamin (1998, p. 28) quote in n 37 above.

  54. Adorno (2004, p. 188): ‘There is absolutely no reducing the concept of form to mathematical relations … Such relations … play a role as technical procedures, yet they are not form itself but rather its vehicle’.

  55. Ibid (p. 189): ‘Form secularizes the theological model of the world as an image made in God’s likeness, though not as an act of creation but as the objectivation of the human comportment that imitates creation; not creatio ex nihilo but creation out of the created.’

  56. Rang (1994, p. 231): ‘The agonists come running from the door of damnation on the left. They run in unison—through the medium of chaos’.

  57. Ibid: ‘The Athenian-Syracusian theater is an agon (cf. the word agonist)’.

  58. On (mis-)reading see text to n 12 above.

  59. Benjamin (1998, p. 27): ‘It is characteristic of philosophical writing that it must continually confront the question of representation.’

  60. On ‘toolbox’ see text to n 4 above.

  61. On Bloom and “misprision” see text to n 12 above.

  62. On ‘the now’ see quotation in n 5 above.

  63. See text at around n 50 above.

References

  • Abbott, Matthew. 2008. The creature before the law: Notes on Walter Benjamin’s Critique of Violence. Colloquy 16: 80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2004 (1970). Aesthetic theory, eds. Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedemann. Trans. R Hullot-Kentor. London: Continuum.

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2005a (1951). Marginalia to theory and praxis. In Critical models: Interventions and catchwords, 259. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Adorno, Theodor. 2005b (1951). Minima moralia: Reflections on damaged life. Trans. E.F.N. Jephcott. London: Verso.

  • Adorno, Theodor W. 2007 (1966). Negative dialectics. London: Continuum.

  • Adorno, Theodor, and Max Horkheimer. 2011. Towards a new manifesto. Trans. Rodney Livingstone. London: Verso.

  • Anderson, Perry. 1979 (1976). Considerations on Western Marxism. London: Verso.

  • Anghie, Antony. 2004. Imperialism, sovereignty, and the making of international law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Andrew. 2011. Morality, law and the place of critique: Walter Benjamin’s The meaning of time in the moral world. Critical Horizons 12(3): 281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, Walter. 1978 (1955). Theologico-political fragment. In Reflections, ed. Peter Demetz. Trans. Edmund Jephcott, 312. New York: Schocken.

  • Benjamin, Walter. 1998 (1963). The origin of German tragic drama. Trans. John Osborne. London: Verso.

  • Benjamin, Walter. 1999 (1955). Theses on the philosophy of history. In Walter Benjamin, Illuminations, ed. Hannah Arendt. Trans. Harry Zorn, 245. London: Pimlico.

  • Benjamin, Walter. 2002. The Arcades project. Trans. Howard Eiland and Kevin McLaughlin. Cambridge Mass: The Belknap Press, Harvard University Press.

  • Benjamin, Walter. 2004a (1921). Critique of violence. In Walter Benjamin: Selected writings: Volume 1 19131926, eds. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings, 236. Cambridge Mass: The Belknap Press, Harvard University Press.

  • Benjamin, Walter. 2004b. On language as such and on the language of man. In Walter Benjamin: Selected writings: Volume 1 19131926, eds. Marcus Bullock and Michael W. Jennings, 62. Cambridge Mass: The Belknap Press, Harvard University Press.

  • Benjamin, Walter. 2005a. The author as producer. In Walter Benjamin: Selected writings: Volume 2 19271934, eds. Michael W. Jennings, Howard Eiland, and Gary Smith, 768. Cambridge Mass: The Belknap Press, Harvard University Press.

  • Benjamin, Walter. 2005b. Antitheses concerning word and name. In Walter Benjamin: Selected writings: Volume 2 19271934, eds. Michael W. Jennings, Howard Eiland, and Gary Smith, 717. Cambridge Mass: The Belknap Press, Harvard University Press.

  • Birnie, Patricia, Alan Boyle, and Catherine Redgwell. 2009. International law and the environment, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, Harold. 1997. The anxiety of influence: A theory of poetry, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, Harold. 2011. The anatomy of influence: Literature as a way of life. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottomore, Tom. 2002 (1984). The Frankfurt School and its critics. London: Routledge.

  • Bowring, Bill. 2011. What is radical in ‘Radical international law’? Finnish Yearbook of International Law 22: 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, Alan. 2012. Human rights and the environment: Where next? European Journal of International Law 23: 613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, Kevin. 2004. Human rights, religion and democracy: The Refah Party Case. Essex Human Rights Review. 1(1):1. http://projects.essex.ac.uk/ehrr/Vol1No1.html. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • Buck-Morss, Susan. 1979. The origin of negative dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno, Walter Benjamin, and the Frankfurt Institute. New York: The Free Press.

  • Buck-Morss, Susan. 1991. The dialectics of seeing: Walter Benjamin and the Arcades Project. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke-White, William. 2008. The Argentine financial crisis: State liability under BITs and the legitimacy of the ICSID system. Asian Journal of WTO and International Health Law and Policy 3: 199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2006. Critique, coercion, and sacred Life in Benjamin’s ‘Critique of Violence’. In Political theologies: Public religions in a post-secular world, eds. Hent de Vries and Lawrence E. Sullivan, 201. New York: Fordham University Press.

  • Charlesworth, Hilary. 2002. International law: A discipline of crisis. Modern Law Review 65: 377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cockburn, Patrick. 2013. Is it the end of Sykes-Picot? London Review of Books 35(11): 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cullis-Suzuki, Sarika, and Daniel Pauly. 2010. Failing the high seas: A global evaluation of regional fisheries management organizations. Marine Policy 34: 1036.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • d’Aspremont, Jean. 2011. Formalism and the sources of international law: A theory of the ascertainment of legal rules. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Wilde, Marc. 2006. Violence in the state of exception: Reflections on theologico-political motifs in Benjamin and Schmitt. In Political theologies: Public religions in a post-secular world, ed. Hent de Vries, and Lawrence E. Sullivan, 188. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1992. Force of law: The ‘mystical foundation of authority’. In Deconstruction and the possibility of justice, eds. Drucilla Cornell, Michael Rosenfeld and David Gray Carlson. Trans. Mary Quaintance, 3. London: Routledge.

  • Dunoff, Jeffrey L., and Joel P. Trachtman (eds.). 2009. Ruling the world? Constitutionalism, international law and global governance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, Paul. 2010 (1975). Against method, 4th edn. London:Verso.

  • Finkelde, Dominik. 2009. The presence of the Baroque: Benjamin’s Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels in contemporary contexts. In A companion to the works of Walter Benjamin, ed. Rolf J. Goebel, 46. London: Camden House.

  • Francioni, Francesco. 2010. International human rights in an environmental horizon. European Journal of International Law 21: 41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, Duncan, and Lavanya Rajamani. 2013. Climate change and international environmental law: Musings on a journey to somewhere. Journal of Environmental Law 25(3): 437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fry, Naomi. 2013. Like China girls. London Review of Books 35(14): 19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie, Alexander. 2010. An introduction to ethical considerations in international environmental law. In Research handbook on international environmental law, ed. Malgosia Fitzmaurice, David M. Ong, and Panos Merkouris, 117. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginzberg, Louis. 1911. The legends of the Jews, Volume III: Bible times and characters from the exodus to the death of Moses. Trans. Paul Radin. Philadelphia: Jewish Publication Society of America.

  • Hanssen, Beatrice. 1995. Philosophy at its origin: Walter Benjamin’s prologue to the Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels. Modern Language Notes 110: 809.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanssen, Beatrice. 1997. On the politics of pure means: Benjamin, Arendt, Foucault. In Violence, identity, and self-determination, ed. Hent de Vries, and Samuel Weber, 236. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgins, Rosalyn. 1978. Conceptual thinking about the individual in international law. New York Law School Law Review 24: 11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 2009. Saving the sacred with a philosophy of history: On Benjamin’s ‘Critique of violence’. In Pathologies of reason: On the legacy of critical theory. Trans. James Ingram, 88. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Horkheimer, Max. 2004 (1947). Eclipse of reason. London: Continuum.

  • Jenkins, Joseph. 2005. Heavy law/light law: Walter Benjamin, Friedrich Nietzsche, Robert Bork, Duncan Kennedy. Law and Literature 17: 249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, Joseph S. 2012. Inheritance law and political theology in Shakespeare and Milton: Election and grace as constitutional in early modern literature and beyond. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johns, Fleur, Richard Joyce, and Sundhya Pahuja (eds.). 2011. Events: The force of international law. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, David. 1987. International Legal Structures. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, David. 1999–2000. When renewal repeats: Thinking against the box. New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 32:335.

  • Kennedy, David. 2006–2007. One, two, three, many legal orders: Legal pluralism and the cosmopolitan dream. New York University Review of Law and Social Change 31:641.

  • Klabbers, Jan, Anne Peters, and Geir Ulfstein. 2009. The constitutionalization of international law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Knox, Robert. 2009. Marxism, international law, and political strategy. Leiden Journal of International Law 22: 413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knox, Robert. 2011. What is to be done (with critical legal theory)? Finnish Yearbook of International Law 22: 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolakowski, Leszek. 1978. Main current in Marxism: The breakdown, trans. P.S. Falla. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koller, David. 2012. … and New York and The Hague and Tokyo and Geneva and Nuremberg and …: The geographies of international law. European Journal of International Law 23: 97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koskenniemi, Martti. 2001. The gentle civilizer of nations: The rise and fall of international law 1870–1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koskenniemi, Martti. 2005 (1989). From apology to utopia: The structure of international legal argumentReissue with new epilogue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Koskenniemi, Martti. 2010. What is international law for? In International law, ed. Malcolm D. Evans, 3rd edn, 32. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kotiaho, Paavo. 2012. A return to Koskenniemi, or the disconcerting co-optation of rupture. German Law Journal 13: 483.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasswell, Harold D., and Myres S. McDougal. 1992. Jurisprudence for a free society: Studies in law, science and policy. New Haven: New Haven Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mack, Michael. 2000. Law and charity: Walter Benjamin, Leo Strauss, Georg Simmel, Franz Baermann Steiner. Law Text Culture 5: 97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1991. One-dimensional man, 2nd ed. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marks, Susan. 2000. The riddle of all constitutions: International law, democracy, and the critique of ideology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marks, Susan. 2006. State-centrism, international law, and the anxieties of influence. Leiden Journal of International Law 19: 339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marks, Susan. 2007. International judicial activism and the commodity-form theory of international law. European Journal of International Law 18: 199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marks, Susan. 2009. False contingency. Current Legal Problems 62: 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miéville, China. 2005. Between equal rights: A Marxist theory of international law. London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Benjamin. 2007. Undoing legal violence: Walter Benjamin’s and Giorgio Agamben’s aesthetics of pure means. Law and Society 34(1): 46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Natarajan, Usha, and Kishan Khoday. 2014. Locating nature: Making and unmaking international law. Leiden Journal of International Law 27: 573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, Matthew. 2014. Fragmented method: Walter Benjamin, law, and representation in Joseph S. Jenkins’ Inheritance law and political theology in Shakespeare and Milton. Law and Literature 26(3): 389.

  • Oppenheim, Lassa. 1908. The science of international law: Its tasks and method. American Journal of International Law 2: 313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orford, Anne. 2004. The destiny of international law. Leiden Journal of International Law 17: 441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orford, Anne. 2013. On international legal method. London Review of International Law 1: 166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfitt, Rose. 2014. The Spectre of Sources. European Journal of International Law 25: 297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Payne, Cymie R. 2011. Pulp mills on the River Uruguay. American Journal of International Law 105: 94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pensky, Max. 1993. Melancholy dialectics: Walter Benjamin and the play of mourning. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rang, Florens Christian. 1994 (1924). Agon and theater. In The correspondence of Walter Benjamin 19101940, eds. Gershom Scholem and Theodor W. Adorno. Trans. Manfred R. Jacobson and Evelyn M. Jacobson, 231. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Reisman, W. Michael. 1981. International lawmaking: A process of communication. In Proceedings of the annual meeting (American Society of International Law), Vol. 75, p. 101.

  • Schachter, Oscar. 1985. McDougal’s jurisprudence: Utility, influence, controversy—Remarks by Oscar Schachter. In Proceedings of the annual meeting (American Society of International Law) Vol. 79, p. 266.

  • Sontag, Susan. 1983. Against interpretation. In A Susan Sontag reader: Introduction by Elizabeth Hardwick, 95. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Holy Bible, King James Version. 1769. http://www.kingjamesbibleonline.org. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • Tomlins, Christopher. 2012. After critical legal history: Scope, scale, structure. Annual Review of Law and Social Science 8: 31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waibel, Michael. 2007. Two worlds of necessity in ICSID arbitration: CMS and LG&E. Leiden Journal of International Law 20: 637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, Slavoj. 2007. Divine violence and liberated territories: Soft Targets talks with Slavoj Žižek. http://www.softtargetsjournal.com/web/zizek.php. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • Žižek, Slavoj. 2009. Violence: Six sideways reflections. London: Profile.

    Google Scholar 

Cases and International Legal Materials

  • CBD. 1995. Convention on biological diversity conference of the parties decision II/10 (the ‘Jakarta Mandate’). http://www.cbd.int/decision/cop/default.shtml?id=7083. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • ECHR. 1995. Lopez Ostra v Spain. European Human Rights Reports 20: 277.

    Google Scholar 

  • ECHR. 2001. Refah Partisi (Welfare Party) and Others v Turkey. European Human Rights Reports 35: 56.

    Google Scholar 

  • ECHR. 2003. Refah Partisi (Welfare Party) and Others v Turkey. European Human Rights Reports 37: 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • ECHR. 2005. Kyrtatos v Greece. European Human Rights Reports 40: 390.

    Google Scholar 

  • ICJ. 2010a. Pulp Mills on the River Uruguay (Argentina v. Uruguay). Judgment of 20 April 2010. http://www.icj-cij.org/docket/index.php?p1=3&p2=3&case=135&code=au&p3=4. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • ICJ. 2010b. Pulp Mills on the River Uruguay (Argentina v. Uruguay). Joint dissenting opinion Judges Al-Khasawneh and Simma. http://www.icj-cij.org/docket/index.php?p1=3&p2=3&case=135&code=au&p3=4. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • ICJ. 2010c. Pulp Mills on the River Uruguay (Argentina v. Uruguay). Separate opinion of Judge Greenwood. http://www.icj-cij.org/docket/index.php?p1=3&p2=3&case=135&code=au&p3=4. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • ICSID. 2005. CMS Gas Transmission Company v The Argentine Republic. International Legal Materials 44: 1205.

    Google Scholar 

  • ICSID. 2007a. LG&E Energy Corp., G&E Capital Corp., LG&E International Inc. v Argentine Republic. International Legal Materials 46: 40.

  • ICSID. 2007b. CMS Gas Transmission Company v Argentine Republic, Decision of the Ad Hoc Committee on the Application for Annulment of the Argentine Republic. International Legal Materials 46: 1136.

    Google Scholar 

  • International Law Commission (ILC). 2006a. Conclusions of the work of the Study Group on the Fragmentation of International Law: Difficulties arising from the Diversification and Expansion of International Law. http://legal.un.org/ilc/texts/1_9.shtml. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • International Law Commission (ILC). 2006b. Fragmentation of International Law: Difficulties Arising from the Diversification and Expansion of International Law—Report of the Study Group of the International Law Commission Finalized by Martti Koskenniemi. http://legal.un.org/ilc/texts/1_9.shtml (see under ‘Analytical study’). Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

  • UN. 1945. Charter of the United Nations. Documents of the United Nations Conference on International Organization 15: 335.

    Google Scholar 

  • UN. 1992. United Nations framework convention on climate change. United Nations Treaty Series 1771: 107.

    Google Scholar 

  • UN. 1997. Kyoto Protocol to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change. United Nations Treaty Series 2303: 162.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNCLOS. 1982. United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea. United Nations Treaty Series 1833: 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNCLOS. 1995. United Nations Agreement Relating to the Conservation and Management of Straddling Fish Stocks and Migratory Fish Stocks. International Legal Materials. 34: 1542.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNEP. 1972. Stockholm Declaration (‘Declaration of the United Nations Conference on the Human Environment’). http://www.unep.org/Documents.Multilingual/Default.asp?documentid=97&articleid=1503. Accessed 1 Oct 2015.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Ralph Wilde and Catherine Redgwell for their support as doctoral supervisors, to Susan Marks, Peter Goodrich, Hazel Biggs, and Aoife O’Donoghue, and to the anonymous reviewers of earlier drafts for their thoughtful comments. Thanks to Martti Koskenniemi and Phillipe Sands (examiners of the doctoral thesis on which this article is based), to David Kennedy, Sundhya Pahuja, Shaun McVeigh, Gleider Hernandez, Yoriko Otomo, Stephen Humphreys, and Anne Orford, and to the participants and organisers of conferences, workshops and seminars in which versions or aspects of this paper were presented. Some aspects of the argument presented here are sketched in my article ‘Fragmented Method: Walter Benjamin, Law, and Representation in Joseph S. Jenkins’ Inheritance Law and Political Theology in Shakespeare and Milton’ (2014) Law and Literature 26(3): 389. I am grateful to UCL’s Graduate School for financial support of much of this research undertaken during doctoral study. Any inadequacies or errors are my fault.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew Nicholson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nicholson, M. Walter Benjamin and the Re-Imageination of International Law. Law Critique 27, 103–129 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-015-9170-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-015-9170-z

Keywords

Navigation