Skip to main content
Log in

Narrative, meaning, interpretation: an enactivist approach

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

After establishing its roots in basic forms of sensorimotor coupling between an organism and its environment, the new wave in cognitive science known as “enactivism” has turned to higher-level cognition, in an attempt to prove that even socioculturally mediated meaning-making processes can be accounted for in enactivist terms. My article tries to bolster this case by focusing on how the production and interpretation of stories can shape the value landscape of those who engage with them. First, it builds on the idea that narrative plays a key role in expressing the values held by a society, in order to argue that the interpretation of stories cannot be understood in abstraction from the background of storytelling in which we are always already involved. Second, it presents interpretation as an example of what Di Paolo et al. (2010) have called in their recent enactivist manifesto a “joint process of sensemaking”: just like in face-to-face interaction, the recipient of the story collaborates with the authorial point of view, generating meaning. Third, it traces the meaning brought into the world by interpretation to the activation and, potentially, the restructuring of the background of the recipients of the story.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am referring here to the claim—advanced by Dennett (1991, 1992) himself, and more recently by philosophers of mind like Schechtman (1996, 2007) and Velleman (2006)—that our personal identity and “self” are constituted, in a strong sense, by the narratives we tell about ourselves. Exploring in full this debated problem would take me too far from my present concerns (for discussion, see Strawson, 2004).

  2. The terms “big stories” and “small stories” have been first used by Bamberg (2004a).

  3. Within literary narratology, this view has been advanced by Herman (2003) and Walsh (2007).

  4. Richard Menary has made a similar claim about writing: “the act of writing is itself a process of thinking” (Menary, 2007, p. 622).

  5. For a recent update to Searle’s theory, see Hutto (forthcoming b)

  6. See, for example, Michelle Scalise Sugiyama on the survival function of narratives: “Narrative may function as a virtual reality, enabling humans to acquire knowledge useful to the pursuit of fitness without undertaking the risks and costs of first-hand experience” (Sugiyama, 2001, pp. 223–224).

  7. For a wide-ranging review of this discussion, see Krausz (2002).

  8. The reference is to Lamarque’s (2008) institutional theory of literature.

  9. Di Paolo, Rohde, and De Jaegher recognize this possibility at one point (Di Paolo et al., 2010, p. 72).

  10. Fludernik (1996) has built her “natural” narratology around this term, which she—however—uses in a different sense.

  11. On our engagement with fictional characters, see at least Neill (1996), Currie (1997), and Coplan (2004). I have offered an enactivist account of recipients’ interaction with the experiences of characters in Caracciolo (2012).

  12. Such a transformation of our landscape of significance bears a close resemblance to what Paul Ricoeur called “mimesis 3,” or the refiguration of our experience brought about by stories: “a work, in acting on the reader, affects that reader. This being affected has the noteworthy quality of combining in an experience of a particular type activity and passivity” he wrote in Time and Narrative (Ricoeur, 1988, p. 167).

  13. Along similar lines, Gibson (2007, pp. 106–107) traces a connection between the cognitive value of literary works and this kind of “recognition.”

References

  • Abbott, H. P. (2008). The Cambridge introduction to narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M. (1981). The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays. In M. Holquist (Ed.). Austin: University of Texas Press.

  • Bamberg, M. (2004a). Talk, small stories, and adolescent identities. Human Development, 47, 366–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bamberg, M. (2004b). Narrative discourse and identities. In J. C. Meister, T. Kind, & W. Schernus (Eds.), Narratology beyond literary criticism (pp. 213–237). Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bamberg, M. (2004c). Considering counter narratives. In M. Bamberg & M. Andrews (Eds.), Considering counter-narratives: narrative, resisting, making sense (pp. 351–371). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bamberg, M. (2007a). Stories: big or small. Why do we care? In M. Bamberg (Ed.), Narrative: state of the art (pp. 165–174). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bamberg, M. (2007b). Introductory remarks. In M. Bamberg (Ed.), Narrative: state of the art (pp. 1–5). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bamberg, M. (Ed.). (2007c). Selves and identities in narrative and discourse. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bamberg, M., & Andrews, M. (Eds.). (2004). Considering counter-narratives: narrative, resisting, making sense. Philadelphia: John Benjamins

  • Baroni, R. (2009). Tellability. In P. Hühn, J. Pier, W. Schmid, & J. Schönert (Eds.), Handbook of narratology. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booth, W. C. (1983). The rhetoric of fiction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caracciolo, M. (2012). Fictional consciousnesses: a reader’s manual. Style, 46.

  • Colombetti, G. (2010). Enaction, sense-making, and emotion. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 145–164). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coplan, A. (2004). Empathic engagement with narrative fictions. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 62(2), 141–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corngold, S. (1973). The commentator’s despair: the interpretation of Kafka’s Metamorphosis. Port Washington: Kennikat Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (1997). The paradox of caring: fiction and the philosophy of mind. In M. Hjort & S. Laver (Eds.), Emotion and the arts (pp. 63–77). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (2010). Narratives and narrators: a philosophy of stories. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1992). The self as a center of narrative gravity. In F. S. Kessel, P. M. Cole, & D. L. Johnson (Eds.), Self and consciousness: multiple perspectives (pp. 103–115). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1979). The role of the reader: explorations in the semiotics of texts. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder, J. (2006). Ways of being close to characters. Film Studies, 8, 68–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (2007). The really hard problem: meaning in a material world. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fludernik, M. (1996). Towards a “natural” narratology. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fludernik, M. (2003). Natural narratology and cognitive parameters. In D. Herman (Ed.), Narrative theory and the cognitive sciences (pp. 243–267). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, M. (1993). Rewriting the self: history, memory, narrative. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, M. (2007). Life “On holiday?”: in defense of big stories. Narrative: state of the art (pp. 155–163). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: theory, simulation, or interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 5–7, 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. New York: Basic Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind: an introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgakopoulou, A. (1997). Narrative performances: a study of modern Greek storytelling. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. (2007). Fiction and the weave of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herman, D. (2003). Stories as a tool for thinking. Narrative theory and the cognitive sciences (pp. 163–192). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herman, D. (2008). Narrative theory and the intentional stance. Partial Answers, 6(2), 233–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herman, D. (2009). Basic elements of narrative. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2007). The narrative practice hypothesis: origins and applications of folk psychology. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and understanding persons (pp. 43–68). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives: the sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (forthcoming a). Elementary mind minding, enactivist-style. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint attention: New developments in philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (forthcoming b). Exposing the background: deep and local. In Z. Radman (Ed.), Knowing without thinking: the background in philosophy of mind. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iser, W. (1978). The act of reading: a theory of aesthetic response. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, T. E. (2003). “Literary interpretation” and cognitive literary studies. Poetics Today, 24(2), 191–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2007). Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jahn, M. (1997). Frames, preferences, and the reading of third person narratives. Poetics Today, 18(4), 441–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, H. (1972). Theory of fiction. (J. E. Miller, Ed.). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

  • John, E. (2005). Art and knowledge. In B. Gaut & D. Lopes (Eds.), The Routledge companion to aesthetics (pp. 417–430). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krausz, M. (2002). Is there a single right interpretation? University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Labov, W. (1972). Language in the inner city: studies in the Black English vernacular. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Labov, W., & Waletzky, J. (1967). Narrative analysis: oral versions of personal experience. In J. Helm (Ed.), Essays on the verbal and visual arts (pp. 12–44). Seattle: University of Washington Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarque, P. (2002). Appreciation and literary interpretation. In M. Krausz (Ed.), Is there a single right interpretation? (pp. 285–306). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamarque, P. (2008). The philosophy of literature. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, J.-F. (1984). The postmodern condition: a report on knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mar, R. A., & Oatley, K. (2008). The function of fiction is the abstraction and simulation of social experience. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 3(3), 173–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H., & Varela, F. J. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. Boston: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Writing as thinking. Language Sciences, 29(5), 621–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (Ed.). (2006). Radical enactivism: focus on the philosophy of Daniel D. Hutto. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moretti, F. (2000). The way of the world: the Bildungsroman in European culture. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neill, A. (1996). Empathy and (film) fiction. In D. Bordwell & N. Carroll (Eds.), Post-theory: reconstructing film studies (pp. 175–194). Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., Myin, E., & Noë, A. (2005). Sensory consciousness explained (better) in terms of “corporality” and “alerting capacity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 369–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ochs, E., & Capps, L. (2001). Living narrative. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsen, S. H. (1987). The end of literary theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 33–87). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelan, J. (2005). Living to tell about it: a rhetoric and ethics of character narration. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quasthoff, U. M., & Becker, T. (2005). Narrative interaction. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1988). Time and narrative, vol. 3. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalise Sugiyama, M. (2001). Food, foragers, and folklore: the role of narrative in human subsistence. Evolution and Human Behavior, 22, 221–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (1996). The constitution of selves. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schechtman, M. (2007). Stories, lives, and basic survival: a refinement and defense of the narrative view. In D. D. Hutto (Ed.), Narrative and understanding persons (pp. 155–178). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2010). Foundational issues in enaction as a paradigm for cognitive science: from the origin of life to consciousness and writing. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 1–31). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2004). Against narrativity. Ratio, XVII, 4, 428–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Torrance, S. (2005). In search of the enactive. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 357–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1997). Patterns of life: intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition, 34, 72–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (2006). The self as narrator. self to self (pp. 203–223). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). In M. Cole, V. John-Steiner, S. Scribner, & E. Souberman (Eds.), Mind in society: the development of higher psychological processes. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, R. (2007). The rhetoric of fictionality: narrative theory and the idea of fiction. Columbus: Ohio State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, R. (2011). The common basis of narrative and music: somatic, social, and affective foundations. Storyworlds, 3, 50–71.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

An early version of this essay was presented at the annual conference of the International Society for the Study of Narrative in St. Louis (April 2011). David Herman has introduced me to enactivism; I am indebted to him for his generous support and invaluable feedback. I would also like to thank two anonymous readers for providing great help in improving this essay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Caracciolo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Caracciolo, M. Narrative, meaning, interpretation: an enactivist approach. Phenom Cogn Sci 11, 367–384 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9216-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-011-9216-0

Keywords

Navigation