Skip to main content
Log in

Estimating representations of time preferences and models of probabilistic intertemporal choice on experimental data

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We here estimate a number of alternatives to discounted-utility theory, such as quasi-hyperbolic discounting, generalized hyperbolic discounting, and rank-dependent discounted utility with three different models of probabilistic choice. The data come from a controlled laboratory experiment designed to reveal individual time preferences in two rounds of 100 binary-choice problems. Rank-dependent discounted utility and its special case—the maximization of present discounted value—turn out to be the best-fitting theory (for about two-thirds of all subjects). For a great majority of subjects (72%), the representation of time preferences in Luce’s choice model provides the best fit.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10
Fig. 11
Fig. 12
Fig. 13
Fig. 14
Fig. 15
Fig. 16
Fig. 17
Fig. 18
Fig. 19

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. One option temporally dominates another if, at any moment of time, the cumulative payoff of the first option up to that moment is at least as high as that of the other option. See Section 2.1 for more details.

  2. In other words, one alternative first-order temporally dominates another if it can be obtained from the other via a sequence of increased and/or bought-forward payments.

  3. The large majority of subjects preferred cash.

  4. The Fechner model of homoscedastic errors does not require F0,s(.) to be the cumulative distribution function of the normal distribution. It could be any monotonically increasing function, e.g., the cumulative distribution function of the logistic distribution, which is known as a softmax choice rule.

  5. Using multiple starting values produced the same results as using the best-fitting parameter for the nested model.

  6. We use the critical value of the chi-squared distribution with two degrees of freedom in the test against the maximization of cumulative payoff, and with one degree of freedom in that against the maximization of present discounted value.

  7. We use the critical value of the chi-squared distribution with three degrees of freedom in the test against the maximization of cumulative payoff, with two degrees of freedom in that against the maximization of present discounted value, and with one degree of freedom in that against discounted-utility theory.

  8. We use the critical value of the chi-squared distribution with six degrees of freedom in the test against maximization of cumulative payoff, and with five degrees of freedom in that against the maximization of present discounted value.

  9. The AIC ranks the different models by penalizing the extra parameters of the less-restrictive models. Formally, the AIC is \( 2k-2\mathit{\ln}\widehat{L} \), with \( \widehat{L} \) being the maximized log-likelihood for a particular model and k the number of model parameters. The lower the value of AIC, the better the model explains the observed behavior.

  10. When we focus the analysis on the subjects whose preferences are best-fitted by RDDU, this convexity is less pronounced.

  11. We use a sign-rank test to test, for each specification of time preferences, the null hypothesis that the subjective discount factor d (b) is the same under the Luce and Fechner models. The sign-rank test rejects the null hypothesis at the 1% level for four comparisons, and at the 5 and 10% levels for one comparison.

  12. By convention, the present is not discounted (the discount factor is one). The delay of one month is discounted with a factor d and that of two months with a factor bd.

  13. I.e., the one with the minimum value of the Akaike information criterion.

References

  • Abdellaoui, M., Bleichrodt, H., & l’Haridon, O. (2013). Sign-dependence in intertemporal choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 47(3), 225–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, S., Harrison, G. W., Lau, M. I., & Rutström, E. E. (2008). Eliciting risk and time preferences. Econometrica, 76(3), 583–618.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J. & Sprenger C. (2012). "Estimating Time Preferences from Convex Budgets." American Economic Review, 102(7), 3333-56

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2017). Probabilistic Intertemporal Choice. Journal of Mathematical Economics 73, 142–148

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2018). Temporal dominance and relative patience in intertemporal choice Economic Theory 65(2), 361–384

  • Blavatskyy, P. R. (2016). A monotone model of intertemporal choice. Economic Theory, 62(4), 785–812.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bøhren, Ø., & Hansen, T. (1980). Capital budgeting with unspecified discount rates. Scandinavian Journal of Economics, 82(1), 45–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavagnaro, D. R., Aranovich, G. J., McClure, S. M., Pitt, M. A., & Myung, J. (2016). On the functional form of temporal discounting: An optimized adaptive test. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 52(3), 233–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chabris, C., Laibson, D., Morris, C., Schuldt, J., & Taubinsky, D. (2008). Individual laboratory-measured discount rates predict field behavior. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 37(2–3), 237–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, G. (1860). Elements of psychophysics. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S. (2005). Cognitive reflection and decision making. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19(4), 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J., & Orme, C. (1994). Investigating generalisations of expected utility theory using experimental data. Econometrica, 62(6), 1291–1326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ida, T., & Goto, R. (2009). Simultaneous measurement of time and risk preferences: Stated preference discrete choice modeling analysis depending on smoking behavior. International Economic Review, 50(4), 1169–1182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans, T. C. (1960). Stationary ordinal utility and impatience. Econometrica, 28(2), 287–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laury, S. K., McInnes, M. M., & Swarthout, J. T. (2012). Avoiding the curves: Direct elicitation of time preferences. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 44(3), 181–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (1992). Anomalies in intertemporal choice: Evidence and an interpretation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 107(2), 573–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., Moffatt, P. G., & Sugden, R. (2002). A microeconomic test of alternative stochastic theories of risky choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24(2), 103–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D. (1959). Individual choice behavior. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meier, S., & Sprenger, C. D. (2015). Temporal stability of time preferences. Review of Economics and Statistics, 97(2), 273–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pan, J., Webb, C. S., & Zank, H. (2015) An extension of quasihyperbolic discounting to continuous time Games and Economic Behavior, 89, 43–55. 14, 31, 69

  • Phelps, E., & Pollak, R. (1968). On second-best national saving and game-equilibrium growth. Review of Economic Studies, 35(2), 185–199.

  • Samuelson, P. (1937). A note on measurement of utility. Review of Economic Studies, 4(2), 155–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tanaka, T., Camerer, C. F., & Nguyen, Q. (2010). Risk and time preferences: Linking experimental and household survey data from Vietnam. American Economic Review, 100(1), 557–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. H. (1981). Some empirical evidence on dynamic inconsistency. Economics Letters, 8(3), 201–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toubia, O., Johnson, E., Evgeniou, T., & Delquié, P. (2013). Dynamic experiments for estimating preferences: An adaptive method of eliciting time and risk parameters. Management Science, 59(3), 613–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vuong, Q. (1989). Likelihood ratio tests for model selection and non-nested hypotheses. Econometrica, 57(2), 307–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilcox, N. T. (2008). Stochastic models for binary discrete choice under risk: A critical primer and econometric comparison. In J. C. Cox & G. W. Harrison (Eds.), Research in Experimental Economics Vol. 12: Risk Aversion in Experiments (pp. 197–292). Bingley: Emerald.

  • Wilcox, N. T. (2011). “Stochastically more risk averse:” A contextual theory of stochastic discrete choice under risk. Journal of Econometrics, 162(1), 89–104.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pavlo R. Blavatskyy.

Additional information

We are grateful to the editor Kip Viscusi and one anonymous referee, as well as the participants of D-TEA 2017 (Paris) and BRIC 2017 (London) for helpful comments.

Appendix

Appendix

Table 3 Questions used in the experiment

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Blavatskyy, P.R., Maafi, H. Estimating representations of time preferences and models of probabilistic intertemporal choice on experimental data. J Risk Uncertain 56, 259–287 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-018-9281-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-018-9281-7

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation