Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Romanticism and Romantic Science: Their Contribution to Science Education

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The unique contributions of romanticism and romantic science have been generally ignored or undervalued in history and philosophy of science studies and science education. Although more recent research in history of science has come to delineate the value of both topics for the development of modern science, their merit for the educational field has not been explored. Romanticism was not only an obvious historical period, but a particular state of mind with its own extraordinary emotional sensitivity towards nature. It is especially the latter which we hope to revisit and reclaim for science education. After discussing several key historical contributions, we describe nine characteristics of ‘Romantic Science’ in order to focus on six ideas/possibilities that we believe hold much value for transforming current science education: (1) the emotional sensitivity toward nature, (2) the centrality of sense experience, (3) the importance of “holistic experience”, (4) the importance of the notions of mystery and wonder, (5) the power of science to transform people’s outlook on the natural world, and (6) the importance of the relationship between science and philosophy. It is argued that in view of a pragmatist/utilitarian conception of school science prevalent today the aforementioned ideas (especially the notion of wonder and the poetic/non-analytical mode of knowledge), can provide food for thought for both science teachers and researchers seeking to work out an aesthetic conception, one that complements current approaches such as inquiry science and conceptual change.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See as examples, Brophy (1987, 1999), Franken (2001), Koballa and Glynn (2007), Pintrich et al. (1993).

  2. Alsop and Watts (1997), Cobern (1996), Hadzigeorgiou (2001a, b), Schulz (2009a, 2014), Solomon (1994).

  3. As discussed by Jenkins and Nelson (2005), Hadzigeorgiou (2005b, 2014), Pugh and Girod (2007).

  4. Abrams (1971), Beiser (1992), Berlin (2001), Bortoft (1996), Heringman (2003), Kodakos (1992), Kloncher (2013), Richards (2002).

  5. While the First Scientific Revolution was associated with the famous names of Newton, Locke, Huygens and Descartes, but also with the founding of scientific academies (Royal Academy in London 1660, the Academie de Sciences in Paris, 1635, and the German Academie Leopoldina, 1652), the Second Scientific Revolution refers to the sudden series of breakthroughs in chemistry, biology and astronomy. And it was the English poet Coleridge who first talked about it during his philosophical Lectures in 1819 (Heringman 2003).

  6. See Beiser (1992, 2003), Cunningham and Jardine (1990), Poggi and Bossi (1994).

  7. The word romantisch derived from the French word ‘roman’, that meant a story, and more specifically “a military tale of awful creatures, heroic knights, and chivalric love. […] It quickly came to indicate an action-filled and passionate adventure, as well as the wild, natural scenery that might be the setting for such a fanciful story” (Richards 2002, p. 20). Holmes (2009) maintains that a defining metaphor of the ‘Romantic’ is the exploratory voyage, entailing peril and solitude.

  8. See Berlin (2001), Heringman (2003), Kloncher (2013).

  9. For example, Goethe was inspired and influenced by Schiller, while Schelling both inspired and was inspired by Goethe. Alexander von Humboldt also inspired and influenced Darwin. Both Goethe and Schiller had been initially enthused by the French Revolution—the new Paris Assembly even made Schiller an honorary citizen of the French Republic in 1798. Some may question whether or not Goethe should be called a “Romantic,” for he is often quoted to have said: “I call the classical healthy and the Romantic sick.” This was uttered in old age, and what the critics often fail to mention is that he also admitted that Schiller had convinced him that “I myself, contrary to my own will, was a Romantic” (quoted in Richards 2002, p. 3). Today in Germany, the life and works of Schiller and Goethe are called “Weimar classicism”, a misleading misnomer, since they sought to unite Enlightenment ideals with Greek classicism and Romantic ideas as the basis of an envisioned new humanism.

  10. Schelling’s view was that all natural creatures were products that are purposive but without a purpose (Richards 2002, p. 162).

  11. The German Romantics, unlike their British counterparts (i.e., natural philosophers), did not believe that there was a Creator who was considered the cause of nature’s creations. All natural creations, all teleological structures in nature, could be explained by reference to nature itself, which reflected the ideas in terms of which nature became understood (see Abrams 1971; Bortoft 1996).

  12. For example, Sir Humphry Davy’s discovery of the laughing gas (nitrous oxide), Volta’s invention of the first battery, infrared radiation (all three in the year 1800!), as well as the theory of evolution, the placebo effect, the discovery of the carbon cycle, and the awareness of the immensity of the universe, were all fruits of the romantic age (Holmes 2009). Included is Karl Burdach, a seminal figure in the history of physiology and neuroanatomy, who first coined the words “morphology” and “biology” (also in 1800), the latter understood initially only as the science of the study of morphology, physiology and psychology of humans (Meyer 1970; Poggi 1994). Lamarck independently used the term one year later, in 1801–1802, but with a decidedly more modern connotation as “a theory of living bodies” (“le theorie des corps vivans”; Barsanti 1994, p. 56) in explicit contrast to the inadequacies of the reigning Enlightenment mechanistic philosophy. It should also be recognized that some contemporary notions as “the mad scientist” and the “diabolical genius” have their origins in the romantic period (Holmes 2009).

  13. See Cunningham and Jardine (1990), Holmes (2009), Poggi and Bossi (1994).

  14. Positivism, as a counter-movement, emerged as a reaction or rather as a response to the inability of philosophy to solve its own philosophical problems (i.e., it rejected philosophical speculation as way to obtaining knowledge of the world). It entirely rejected metaphysics, and accepted the view that only empirical science can provide data, which will then be used to solely account for true knowledge of the world. However its own fundamental tenet—the rejection of speculation—cannot be evaluated through empirical research (see Pickering’s 1993).

  15. In the 1920s Positivism re-emerged under the name of Logical Positivism and was linked to the Vienna Circle. This form of positivism retained the value of empirical research but logic was also added, in order to account for valid knowledge claims (see Friedman’s 1996).

  16. See, for example, Cunningham and Jardine (1990), Heringman (2003), Kloncher (2013), Poggi and Bossi (1994).

  17. The idea of ‘evolution’ was synonymous with the idea of ‘change’ and dynamism, and was implicit in the process of recapitulation, that is, the process during which all organisms recapitulate the history of their species (Bortoft 1996; Richards 2002).

  18. Because the purpose of the ‘Romantic’ scientists was not to manipulate and control nature but to understand it as it appears to us (Abrams 1971; Bortoft 1996), without having to resort to mathematical symbols and models in order to represent it, one cannot use ‘Romantic Science’ to build an airplane, bridge, or rocket—that would require a quantitative, mechanical and mathematical approach to natural phenomena. ‘Romantic Science’, because it involves a qualitative, dynamic and concrete methodology and attitude to nature, can help one approach nature as it appears in concrete experience with all its richness.

  19. This term (German “nature philosophy”) is associated with romantic thinkers like Herder, Goethe and Schelling who explicitly developed an organic conception of nature opposed to the mechanical ideal. This important intellectual tradition emphasized that “nature ceased to be mere product of the Creator’s designs but itself became producer—of itself” (Richards 2002, p. 11). This school of thought would later come to be narrowly confined by critics to Schelling’s philosophy of transcendental idealism, whereupon its significance for the history of science would be downplayed or dismissed. Richards’ scholarly work (and others referenced here) rehabilitates the concept for science and argues the value of romantic science (indeed “romantic biology”) as fundamentally linked with modern evolutionary theory via “romantic scientists” like Goethe, Humboldt, Oken, Burdach, Haeckel and Darwin. Yet he cautions that “all Romantic thinkers were Naturphilosophen, though not all Naturphilosophen were Romantics” (p. 516).

  20. Kant had distinguished between the ‘noumena’, that is, the “things-in-themselves”, and the ‘phenomena’, that is, the things as they appear to us. The former can never be known. This dichotomy was not accepted by Fichte. Rather, for him the existence of Kantian ‘noumena’ implied a reality beyond the Kantian categories of human reason, and thus must lead to skepticism. Instead he suggested and accepted that consciousness cannot be grounded in anything outside of itself. Hence the source of all ‘phenomena’ is self-consciousness, that is, the activity of the ego (see Franks 2005).

  21. See further on, in the next section the difference between the idea of “unity in multiplicity” and that of “multiplicity in unity”.

  22. Wechselwirkung seems to me to be one of the central topoi of romantic science, and the concept is likely to answer some more of the questions about why and how a scientific discipline such as ecology came to develop” (Müller 1994, p. 3).

  23. Vulcanism held that primitive rocks solidified from lava during ancient times while Neptunism held that rocks emerged from out of primitive oceans when the water receded (Richards 2002, p. 366).

  24. “The protracted nature of the debate and its ferocity cannot be explained in purely geological terms, but must be viewed at the level of clashing philosophies of history. Hutton’s Plutonism was part and parcel of Enlightenment history with its penchant for eternalism. Werner’s Neptunism was not merely a system of chemical lithogenesis, but had a consanguinity with both the traditional biblical cosmogony and the more secular view of history held by many Romantics. Goethe saw the controversy in this light, and so did men such as Blumenbach and his friend Jean-André Deluc” (Rupke 1990, pp. 251–252).

  25. Here was another example in the history of physics when seen in hindsight that a hypothesis has borne fruit while conjectured from a mind-set with mistaken theoretical suppositions.

  26. Scerri’s examination of the subject as it relates to the philosophical and historical development of the Periodic Table is insightful: “The reduction of chemistry to quantum mechanics has neither failed completely, as some philosophers of chemistry have claimed, nor has it been a complete success, as some contemporary historians have claimed” (2007, p. 248).

  27. The outcome of Goethe’s ability to observe was the invention of the science of morphology. However he did study many of the natural sciences of his time like geology, botany, zoology, mineralogy, osteology, even meteorology.

  28. See Armitage (2009), Bybee (1977), Chalkins (1862), Comstock (1967), Kohlstedt (2010).

  29. What Goethe was after was the perception of unity. Unity for him was something that cannot be externally displayed, and therefore it must be understood “internally” as a mode of perception. For example, as Bortoft (1996) writes, “we can show a picture of a particular plant, but we cannot show a picture of the unity of the plant. This is something we must see but cannot depict" (p. 247). Goethe’s idea of “metamorphosis” captures the idea of “multiplicity in unity”, that is, a unity of self-difference, according to Bortoft.

  30. See Heringman (2003), Holmes (2009), and Richards (2002).

  31. Emphasized by Abrams (1971) and Richards (2006); see also Friedman and Normann (2006).

  32. Gesellshaft Deutscher Naturforscher und Ärzte (GDNÄ). It was originally founded in Leipzig, but was refounded after the Second World War in Göttingen. Since 1983 it awards the prestigious Lorenz-Oken-Medal for outstanding research in the fields of medicine or the natural sciences as contributing to the betterment of society. Oken’s romantic notion of unity was influenced by political factors as well, for his original idea to establish a “holy alliance of noble-minded men” in 1806 (Jahn 1994, p. 82) must be seen against the background of the Napoleonic wars in Germany and the desire for national unity.

  33. Achievement in university reforms allowed for continuities with some Enlightenment philosophical and educational arguments, especially the concern for freedom of thought and teaching autonomy. The best example is Kant, whose works and immense influence served as both catalyst and contrarian to several Romantic thinkers: “The strong continuity between the Enlightenment and Romanticism can be seen in the contribution of Kant to the reform programme of Humboldt” (Shaffer 1990, p. 39).

  34. See for, instance, Pedretti and Nazir (2011), Walker and Zeidler (2007), Zeidler et al. (2005).

  35. As the “biophilia hypothesis” suggests, our emotional bond with nature is still strong, since our technological development has been so rapid that our evolutionary adaptation to new environments has yet to develop. Human beings, according to this hypothesis, have an innately emotional affiliation to other living organisms, and therefore there is still a need to be within nature (Wilson 1986). Yet this genetic bond behind such a hypothesis may very well be a weak one, thus requiring additional learning experiences (Kellert 2002). The fact that children grow up in a highly technological environment and, more often than not, away and literally cut off from the natural environment, makes learning experiences and knowledge about the latter imperative. It is for this very reason that the school curriculum, including school science, should provide such learning experiences.

  36. Sensory experience simply results in ‘physical knowledge’, which refers to a simple description of physical reality. Such knowledge, though necessary, is not sufficient for an understanding of reality which presupposes the construction of ‘logico-mathematical knowledge’ through certain transformations (see Piaget 1970).

  37. Sensory experience can be passive and result in ‘knowledge as a spectacle’. This knowledge is the basis of what Dewey called ‘the spectator theory of knowledge’ (see Dewey 1966/1916).

  38. It is admitted today one can no longer hold that students (or scientists for that matter) can have unadulterated experiences and perceptions of nature completely free of subjective preconceptions, as once Goethe, the romantics and Husserl maintained: “The possibility of ‘letting nature herself speak’, that is, of a ‘virgin’ perception, untouched by culture, history and language, is nowadays considered obsolete. Most of the inheritors of Husserl’s philosophy (Heidegger, Gadamer, Merleau-Ponty) denied this possibility, seeing all perception as necessarily enmeshed in language and determined by the horizon of the lifeworld (cf. Gadamer). Nevertheless, there is a value in not abolishing the notion of ‘nature’s own voice’, in order not to let our capacities for careful observation, intense listening to and dwelling in the phenomena dwindle” (Østergaard et al. 2008, p. 116).

  39. According to empirical evidence, a demonstration that involved a magnet attracting and holding a paperclip resulted in a sensory experience: the students were able to observe a paper clip attracted and held by a magnet. It was only after they became aware (through questioning) that the magnet attracted and held the paperclip, in spite of the fact that the whole planet was pulling down on it, that they felt surprised and even astonished and started to wonder at and about the force of gravity. It was then that the students had a lived- experience, in the sense that they became conscious of what that simply demonstration meant. In this case, the students did not experience any contradictions in their thinking. It was just the teacher’s questions that help them transform a sensory experience into a lived experience (Hadzigeorgiou 2011).

  40. We believe that this view by Østergaard et al. (2008), is not necessarily true, given that an approach that starts with sense experience can be called constructivist, and there have been such approaches documented in the literature (e.g., Driver 1984).

  41. Both phenomenological and constructivist approaches are based on the notion of subjectivity, even though in the case of social constructivism interactions between the individual and the social environment are central to developing knowledge and understanding. However, while in both constructivist and phenomenological learning subjectivity plays a central role, in phenomenological learning there is always intentionality—thought and consciousness are always involved and cannot be separated from the object of study. This last characteristic of phenomenological learning is not necessarily characteristic of constructivist learning; the purpose of learning, for example, is either ignored or downplayed by constructivist learning (Hadzigeorgiou 2005b, see also van Manen, M. 1990). The most important questions that are associated with the constructivist perspective are: (a) ontological: what do we know? (b) Epistemological: how do we know; (c) communicative: how can we communicate what we know? and (d) Technical: what can we do with our knowledge (see Osborne 1996). Without a question of purpose, intentionality is discouraged, as is the case with many constructivist approaches (Hadzigeorgiou 2005b).

  42. Both Martin Heidegger and Maurice Merleau-Ponty criticized and disputed Husserl's transcendental phenomenology because the latter’s approach to phenomenology was to seek invariant and transcendental structures in the realm of consciousness. In other words, speculative reflection, on which Husserl based his transcendental phenomenological method, could not adequately describe human lived experience (see Merleau-Ponty, M. 1985, chap. 2; Valle, R. and Halling, S. 1989; van Manen, M. 1990).

  43. Commented by e.g., Burnard (1989), Creswell (2007), Joplin (1981), Van Manen (1990).

  44. Michael Matthews, in writing about the critics of science, including the phenomenological philosophers like Husserl, pointed out that “the rich world of human experience cannot be captured by the colourless point masses of Newton, or the emotion- and feeling-less mechanical world of the New Science” (Matthews 2015, p. 157).

  45. It is interesting to note that Østergaard et al. (2008), in discussing philosophical, anthropological and romantic (Goethe’s) phenomenology, and pointing out their differences, choose to address three separate aspects of the phenomenological approach to science education: (a) phenomenology of science education; (b) phenomenology in science education; and (c) phenomenology and science education integrated.

  46. Apparently a lived experience cannot be associated only with students’ everyday world. Any experience involving real life situations, that is, authentic contexts, even contexts far removed from their everyday world, can be a lived experience (e.g., an adventure trip in Alaska where students investigate topics of interest).

  47. Perhaps a strong argument against starting from students’ lived experiences is that such experiences may very well help develop and reinforce certain naïve conceptions or misconceptions. We are both certainly very aware of the extensive research on this subject. This, however, is not or should not be a problem, because such misconceptions can be dealt with right at the beginning of instruction. If the source of the development of such misconceptions are students’ personal experiences (e.g., with heat, motion, forces, sound, etc.), then it is “instructionally” reasonable to start the teaching of science with exactly those personal experiences. Another argument may be the empirical treatment of nature, which presupposes a dualism between epistemic subject and object of study. This argument, which owes its legacy to positivism and the ‘scientific method’ is also under attack, especially when it comes to education (see Elkana 2000; Witz 1996, and especially Dahlin 2001, for a phenomenological critique of science education).

  48. Such an alienation is reinforced by the obstacle of scientific language use in both classroom discourse and texts, termed by Lemke (1990) the “mystique of science” in his insightful pioneering study on the role of language in science education.

  49. Goethe (1988); see also Heinemann (1934), Seamon and Zajonc (1998).

  50. Goethe’s phenomenology is indeed grounded in the fundamental idea of phenomenology, that is, Husserl’s idea of “returning to the things themselves”, since his aim was to start from experience and ‘stay with experience’. Yet whether his special approach to nature is closer to that of transcendental or existential phenomenology is not easy to establish. Heidegger’s notion of “being in the world” appears to be fundamentally linked to Goethe’s methodological approach. On the other hand, Goethe's way was that of seeing all nature as one, with the aim to discover a principle of continuity running through the whole, from a flower and a geological rock to animals, humans, and the processes of aesthetic creation (see Seamon and Zajonc 1998; Spiegelberg 1982).

  51. The process of observation includes vision, perception, looking, noticing, and seeing, and its study has recently become multidisciplinary, including philosophy of perception, philosophy of mind, cognitive psychology, and phenomenology (see Matthews 2015; see also Abercrombie 1960).

  52. The best known examples of flyers (with rotating wheels) are the fruit of the maple- and the lime-tree, and the seeds of coniferous trees.

  53. According to Burnard (1989, p. 14) what defines an experiential learning activity is: (a) action, in the sense there is not passivity, (b) reflection, that is, learning takes place only after the action has been reflected upon, (c) a phenomenological dimension, that is, the student creates and assigns meaning to what is going on, without the teacher’s attempt to force meaning on the student, (d) subjectivity, that is, how the student him/herself views the situation.

  54. The word derives from the Greek work ‘holos’, meaning ‘all’, ‘whole’, or ‘total’. According to the Ancient Greek philosopher Parmenides, the world is characterized by a changeless unity. He had argued that “All is One”, an idea that Spinoza seems to have adopted. Indeed, for Spinoza all the differences and the divisions we see in the world are just manifestations of an underlying single entity or substance, namely, God or nature.

  55. Such connections help a person develop morally, emotionally, physically, intellectually, and spiritually (Miller 2007).

  56. As some have argued, e.g., Dahlin (2001), Hadzigeorgiou (2005b); see also Østergaard et al. (2008).

  57. Almost all of his writing on education illustrate his quest for unity and his rejection of dualisms: School and Society, The Child and the Curriculum, Experience and Education, Democracy and Education.

  58. Such as Girod (2007), Girod et al. (2003), and Pugh (2004, 2010).

  59. Dewey describes ‘an experience’ as follows: “Often times, however, the experience had is inchoate. Things are experienced but not in such a way that they are composed into an experience. There is distraction and dispersion; what we observe and what we think, what we desire and what we get, are at odds with each other…In contrast with such experience, we have an experience when the material experienced runs its course to fulfilment. Then and only then is it integrated within and demarcated in the general stream of experience from experiences. A piece of work is finished in away that is satisfactory; a problem receives its solution; a game is played through; a situation, whether that of eating a meal, playing a game of chess, carrying on a conversation. Writing a book, or taking part in a political campaign, is so rounded out that its close is a consummation and not a cessation. Such an experience is a whole and carries with it its own individualizing quality and self-sufficiency. It is an experience” (Dewey 1934, p. 35).

  60. It should be noted that even though Dewey’s aesthetic philosophy (Dewey 1934) is not explicitly phenomenological, its potential to make a contribution to the literature concerning the phenomenological approach to learning science needs to be acknowledged. One could talk, for example, about a ‘phenomenological/aesthetic’ approach to science as a holistic approach, which, on the one hand, places primacy upon ‘lived experience’ and not simply upon sense experience (e.g., listening, observing), and on the other, considers the qualities of an aesthetic experience. In other words, such an approach includes sense experience, emotions, somatic reason and also the appreciation of the beauty of science and its ideas (especially the role that aesthetic perception plays in the construction of knowledge). Thus, it provides students with opportunities for “careful and exact attention to all the qualities inherent in sense experience” (Dahlin 2001, p. 454, emphasis ours). We choose to talk about ‘a phenomenological/aesthetic’ and not about ‘the phenomenological/aesthetic’ approach to science, because, while the phenomenological approach to science teaching and learning is based primarily on Husserl’s work, and the aesthetic approach on Dewey’s notion of holistic/fulfilled experience, there may be some slight differences in their implementation (see as examples, Dahlin 2001; Hadzigeorgiou 2005a; Pugh and Girod 2007; 2006).

  61. Pugh and Girod (2007) have developed an aesthetic pedagogy based upon Dewey’s notion of aesthetic experience and recommend the following ideas in order to facilitate an aesthetic experience: (a) crafting ideas out of concepts; (b) restoring concepts to the experience in which they had their origin and significance; (c) fostering anticipation and a vital, personal experiencing; (d) using metaphors and “re-seeing” to expand perception; (e) modelling a passion for the content; and (f) enculturating students into ways of valuing and experiencing science ideas.

  62. Dahlin’s (2013) recent work on the “poetization of childhood” can help with the development of a ‘Romantic’ vision for childhood, and hence with the development of ‘Romantic’ early childhood science education, including such elements as freedom, creativity, joy, and wonder.

  63. Understanding the difference between “unity in multiplicity” and “multiplicity in unity” is key to understanding Goethe’s approach to the study of nature. The main difference lies in the fact that human perception derives unity from multiplicity. "For example, when we see the leaves of a plant we just see the generality "leaf" and do not notice the particularity of any one leaf or the differences between the leaves. Attention does not go into sensory experience, but remains on the level of mental abstraction. This is the condition of automization, in which the particular is "tuned out" and only the general form of what things have in common is registered. This is our habitual state of passive awareness, which is reversed by the process of active seeing in Goethean science" (Bortoft 1996, p. 249).

  64. What Goethe sought, according to Steiner (2000), was to bring the diversity back into the unity from which it originally came. Goethe’s idea of “metamorphosis” captures the idea of “multiplicity in unity”, to be exact, a unity of self-difference (Bortoft 1996).

  65. Understanding a phenomenon (e.g., a sunset, a rainbow) philosophically, scientifically and poetically, according to the Romantics, involves “unity in multiplicity”, so it is not holistic like the idea of “multiplicity in unity”. In the case of “unity in multiplicity”, the dualism between subject and object is maintained. Current interdisciplinary and multidisciplinary approaches help students experience “unity in multiplicity”, and this is certainly much more easier than to help them experience “multiplicity in unity”, that is, the truly holistic approach to the study of nature.

  66. See Girod et al. (2003), Pugh (2002, 2004, 2011), Pugh and Girod (2007), and Wickmann (2006).

  67. As examples, Begoray and Stinner (2005), Pantidos et al. (2014), and Watts (2001).

  68. See Hodson (2004), Roth and Desautels (2002), Roth and Lee (2004).

  69. Researchers concerned with including historical and philosophical components of science into science curriculum and instruction have argued for several decades that HPS reforms should comprise another dominant paradigm (e.g. Hodson 2008; Matthews 1994, 2015).

  70. See Girod et al. (2003), Heddy and Sinatra (2013), Pugh (2004, 2011), Pugh and Girod (2007).

  71. The pedagogical value of wonder in the context of science education, according to two empirical studies (Hadzigeorgiou 2011; Hadzigeorgiou and Garganourakis 2010), is that (a) it can encourage involvement with content knowledge, (b) it can be the source of students’ questions and (c) it can even make students view natural phenomena and science, as a school subject, differently after their experience of wonder. These two studies have provided evidence that not only spectacular phenomena but science ideas can be real sources of wonder.

  72. Curiosity is associated with reductionism. In The Star Thrower Loren Eiseley (1978) speaks of two kinds of practitioners in science. One is the “extreme reductionist who is so busy stripping things apart that the tremendous mystery has been reduced to a trifle” and the other is s/he “who still has a controlled sense of wonder before the universal mystery whether it hides in a snail’s eye or within the light that impinges on that delicate organ” (p. 151). For Dawkins, however, even scientific reductionism did not take away anything from the “poetry of science”; it did not diminish the beauty of the natural phenomena. The rainbow, for example, did not lose its beauty when Newton reduced it to prismatic colours. Light, in general, does not lose its beauty when it is refracted, reflected and digitized. The poetry and the wonder are still there. What Dawkins says is crucial, since it has implications for science education: the wonder of natural phenomena can indeed co-exist with mathematics and empirical treatment. But students need to be helped to experience wonder, exactly because wonder, more often than not, needs to be explicitly evoked.

  73. Wonder has the capacity to defamiliarize “the familiar through a refreshed way of looking upon it” (Abrams 1971, p. 379).See also Feynman (1964, 1995).

  74. The experience of wonder, as a holistic experience, facilitates the experience of “multiplicity in unity”.

  75. The specific characteristics of “romantic understanding” make it a quite distinctive kind of understanding, which is not to be confused or conflated with narrative understanding in general. Bruner (1986) first made a distinction between “paradigmatic” and “narrative understanding”. The former derives from the paradigmatic (or logico-mathematical) mode of thinking, which is associated with the formation of hypotheses, the development of arguments, and with rational thinking, generally. The latter derives from the narrative mode of thinking, which is associated with “verisimilitude,” that is, life-likeness and the creation of meaning. Although these two modes of human thinking are complementary, they are irreducible to one another.

  76. See Hadzigeorgiou (2005a), Hadzigeorgiou et al. (2012a, b), and Schulz (2009b). For specific historical case studies see Allchin (2013), Dolphin (2009) and Niaz (2000, 2009, 2010).

  77. Observing, for example, a rainbow or a waterfall and becoming aware of their beauty and feeling a sense of mystery about their origin is different from observing a battery always running out of energy, each time it gets connected to a circuit, despite the fact that the battery was always fully charged. In the first case, the sense of mystery has its source in the aesthetic perception of the rainbow or the waterfall. In the second case there is mystery simply because there is an unexplained situation. In both cases there is a sense of wonder. However, while the first case is associated with a wonder-at and a wonder-about attitude, the second case is associated only with a wonder-about attitude, or simply with curiosity. (Hadzigeorgiou 2014; see also Goodwin 2001, Milne 2010).

  78. Philip Phenix, in stressing the role of imaginative engagement in the process of meaning making, indirectly pointed out the crucial role of mystery: Ordinary, prosaic, and customary considerations do not excite a vital personal engagement with ideas. One of the qualities of good teaching is the ability to impart a sense of the extraordinary and surprising so that learning becomes a continuous adventure. According to this principle, ordinary life situations and the solving of everyday problems should not be the basis for curriculum content. The life of meaning is far better served by using materials that tap the deepest levels of experience (Phenix 1964, p. 12).

  79. Mystery presupposes the familiar or unfamiliar, but also extraordinary and unexplained phenomena and situations that make one wonder at and about such phenomena and situations. A sense of wonder, without doubt, can also arise from taken-for-granted, familiar, and very ordinary objects, entities, phenomena and situations.

  80. Apparently, such a programme should simultaneously train student-teachers with the ability to perform ‘careful observation’.

  81. According to empirical evidence, a demonstration that involved a magnet attracting and holding a paperclip initially meant nothing to the students, who saw only two ordinary objects, namely a paper clip and a magnet. It was only after they became aware (through questioning) that the magnet attracted and held the paperclip, in spite of the fact that the whole planet was pulling down on it, that they felt surprised and even astonished, and started to wonder at and about the force of gravity. As one female student commented: “Although I knew that gravity was the weakest of all forces and I could see that in the numbers on that table about the relative strength of all forces in nature, it was after that simple, and very easy-to-do experiment that I understood it better […] It is really remarkable and very strange now that I know that the force of gravity is very-very weak” (Hadzigeorgiou 2011).

  82. Thus, Hirst (1972, p. 401), Jardine et al. (2003, p. 102), Peters (1967, p. 9), Schank (2004, p. 37).

  83. See Girod et al. (2003), Hadzigeorgiou (2011), Hadzigeorgiou et al. (2012a, b), and Pugh (2004, 2011). Richard Feynman (1968, p. 320) has been explicit about the potential of science to help change the way we perceive the world: “The world looks so different after learning science. For example, trees are made of air, primarily. When they are burned, they go back to air, and in the flaming heat is released the flaming heat of the sun which was bound into convert the air into tree. [A]nd in the ash is the small remnant of the part which did not come from air, that came from the solid earth, instead. These are beautiful things, and the content of science is wonderfully full of them. They are very inspiring, and they can be used to inspire others”.

  84. As examples, the ideas of evolution and the heliocentric system, although they did not have an immediate practical significance in people’s daily lives, they did have a profound emotional significance, since they both shook the foundations of the human soul; they both made people see themselves in new light. By the same token, quantum theory and relativity theory made people view light, particles, space and time quite differently than before, even though those theories did not have any immediate practical impact on their everyday life. The Milky Way and the idea of infinity—indeed two ideas without any practical significance in daily life—had also an immense emotional significance for people, in the sense that they became aware of the immensity of space and, simultaneously, aware of the insignificant size of the planet on which they live (Hadzigeorgiou 2005b).

References

  • Abercrombie, M. (1960). The anatomy of judgement: An investigation into the process of perception and reasoning. London: Hutc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abrams, M. H. (1971). Natural supernaturalism: Tradition and revolution in romantic literature. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2013). Teaching the nature of science. Perspectives and resources. St. Paul, MN: SHiPS Education Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alsop, S., & Watts, M. (1997). A model of informal learning about radiation and radioactivity. Science Education, 81, 633–650.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1998). The metaphysics. (Translated and introduction by Hugh Lawson-Tancred). London: Penguin books.

  • Armitage, K. (2009). The nature study movement. Kansas City: University Press of Kansas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsanti, G. (1994). Lamarck and the birth of biology 1740–1810. In S. Poggi & M. Bossi (Eds.), Romanticism in science. Science in Europe, 1790–1840 (pp. 47–73). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, H. H. (1992). Scientific literacy and the myth of the scientific method. Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begoray, D., & Stinner, A. (2005). Representing science through historical drama. Science & Education, 3–5, 457–471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beiser, F. (1992). Enlightenment, revolution, and romanticism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beiser, F. (2003). Romanticism. In R. Curren (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of education (pp. 130–141). New York, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, I. (2001). The roots of romanticism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bortoft, H. (1996). The wholeness of nature. Goethe’s way toward a science of conscious participation in nature. New York: Lindisfarne Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottazzini, U. (1994). Geometry and “metaphysics of space” in Gauss and Riemann. In S. Poggi & M. Bossi (Eds.), Romanticism in science. Science in Europe, 1790–1840 (pp. 15–30). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brian, R. M., Cohen, R. S., & Knudsen. O. (Eds.). (2007). Hans Christian Ørsted and the Romantic legacy in science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 241, 273–339.

  • Brophy, J. (1987). Synthesis of research on strategies for motivating students to learn. Educational Leadership, 45, 40–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brophy, J. (1999). Toward a model of the value aspects of motivation in education. Educational Psychologist, 34, 75–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. (1986). Actual minds, possible worlds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke, E. (1990). A philosophical enquiry into the origin of our ideas. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnard, P. (1989). Teaching interpersonal skills: A handbook of experiential learning for health professionals. London: Chapman & Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bybee, R. (1977). Toward a third century of science education. The American Biology Teacher, 39, 338–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalkins, N. (1862). Primary object lessons for a graduated course of development. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, A. (1990). Science and its fabrication. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, A. (1999). What is this thing called science?. St. Lucia, Queensland: University of Queensland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. C. (2013). Hans Christian Ørsted. Reading nature’s mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobern, W. (1996). Worldview theory and conceptual change in science education. Science Education, 80, 579–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Comstock, A. (1967). Handbook of nature study. Ithaca, NY: Comstock Publishing Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Creswell, J. W. (2007). Qualitative inquiry and research design: Choosing among five approaches. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, A., & Jardine, N. (Eds.). (1990). Romanticism and the sciences. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlin, B. (2001). The primacy of cognition- or of perception? A phenomenological critique of the theoretical bases of science education. Science & Education, 10, 453–475.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlin, B. (2013). Poetizing our unknown childhood: Meeting the challenge of social constructivism. The Romantic philosophy of childhood and Steiner’s spiritual anthropology. RoSE: Research on Steiner Education, 4, 16–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1998). Unweaving the rainbow: Science, delusion, and the appetite for wonder. New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey (1984/1929). The quest for certainty. In J.A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey : The Later Works, 1925-1953, Vol. 4, Carbondale, Southern Illinois University Press. (First published 1929).

  • Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. New York: Perigree.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1938). Experience and education. New York: Collier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1966/1916). Democracy and education. New York: MacMillan.

  • Dolphin, G. (2009). Evolution of the theory of the earth: A contextualized approach for teaching the history of the theory of plate tectonics to ninth grade students. Science & Education, 18. doi:10.1007/s11191-007-9136-0.

  • Donnelly, J. (1999). Schooling Heidegger: On being in teaching. Teaching and Teacher Education, 15, 933–949.

  • Donnelly, J. (2004). Humanizing science education. Science Education, 88, 762–784.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver, R. (1983). The pupil as scientist?. Kent: Milton Keynes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver, R. (1984). Cognitive psychology and pupils’ frameworks in mechanics. In P. Linjse (Ed.), The many faces of teaching and learning mechanics (pp. 22–25). Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K. (1990). Romantic understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K. (1997). The educated mind. How cognitive tools shape our understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K. (2005). An imaginative approach to teaching. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eiseley, L. (1978). The star thrower. New York: Times Books.

  • Elkana, Y. (2000). Science, philosophy of science and science teaching. Science & Education, 9, 463–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faraday, M. (1861/1978). The chemical history of a candle. Marieta, GA: Cherokee Publishing Company.

  • Feynman, R. (1964). The value of science. In A. Arons & A. Bork (Eds.), Science and ideas (pp. 3–12). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. (1968). What is science? The Physics Teacher, 7, 313–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. (1995). Six easy pieces. Reading, Mass: Helix Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franken, R. (2001). Human motivation. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franks, P. (2005). All or nothing: Systematicity, transcendental arguments, and skepticism in German idealism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1996). Reconsidering logical positivism. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Normann, A. (Eds.). (2006). The Kantian legacy in the nineteenth-century science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girod, M. (2007). A conceptual overview of aesthetics in science education. Studies in Science Education, 43, 38–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girod, M., Ran, C., & Schepige, A. (2003). Appreciating the beauty of science ideas: Teaching for aesthetic understanding. Science Education, 87, 574–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goethe, J. W. V. (1988). Scientific studies. (D. Miller, Ed., Trans.). New York: Suhrkamp.

  • Goodenough, U. (1997). The sacred depths nature. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Goodwin, A. (2001). Wonder in science teaching and learning: An update. School Science Review, 83, 69–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gough, N. (1993). Environmental education, narrative complexity and postmodern science/fiction. International Journal of Science Education, 5, 607–625.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (2003). Defending science—within reason. Between scientism and cynicism. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (1997). Relationships, meaning and the science curriculum. Curriculum and Teaching, 12, 83–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (1999). On problem situations and science learning. School Science Review, 81, 43–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (2001a). Global problems and the curriculum: Toward a humanistic and constructivist science education. Curriculum & Teaching, 16, 39–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (2001b). The role of wonder and “romance” in early childhood science education. International Journal of Early Years Education, 9, 63–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (2005a). Romantic understanding and science education. Teaching Education, 16, 23–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (2005b). On humanistic science education (ERIC DOCUMENT 506504).

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (2011). Fostering a sense of wonder in the science classroom. Research in Science Education, 42, 985–1005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (2014). Reclaiming the value of wonder in science education. In K. Egan, A. Cant, & J. Judson (Eds.), “Wonder-full education”: The centrality of wonder in teaching and learning across the curriculum (pp. 40–65). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y., Fokialis, P., & Kabouropoulou, M. (2012a). Thinking about creativity in science education. Creative Education, 3, 603–611.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y., & Garganourakis, V. (2010). Using Nikola Tesla’s life and experiments as presented in the film “The Prestige” to promote scientific inquiry. Interchange, 41(4), 363–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y., Klassen, S., & Froese-Klassen, C. (2012b). Encouraging a ‘romantic understanding’ of science: The effect of the Nikola Tesla story. Science & Education, 21, 1111–1138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y., & Skoumios, M. (2013). The development of environmental awareness through school science: Problems and possibilities. International Journal of Environmental & Science Education, 8, 405–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y., & Stivaktakis, S. (2008). Encouraging involvement with school science. Journal of Curriculum & Pedagogy, 5, 138–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, C. (1989). Husserl’s phenomenology and the foundations of natural science. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heddy, B. C., & Sinatra, G. M. (2013). Transforming misconceptions: Using transformative experience to promote positive affect and conceptual change in students learning about biological evolution. Science Education, 97, 723–744.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinemann, F. (1934). Goethe’s phenomenological method. Philosophy, 9, 67–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heringman, N. (2003). Romantic science. New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. (1972). Liberal education and the nature of knowledge. In R. Dearden, P. Hirst, & R. Peters (Eds.), Education and the development of reason (pp. 391–414). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (2004). Going beyond STS: Towards a curriculum for sociopolitical action. Science Education Review, 3, 2–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (2008). Towards scientific literacy. A teacher’s guide to the history, philosophy and sociology of science. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, R. (2009). The age of wonder. How the romantic generation discovered the beauty and terror of science. Random House, NY: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of the European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

  • Jahn, I. (1994). On the origin of romantic biology and its further development at the university of Jena between 1790 and 1850. In S. Poggi & M. Bossi (Eds.), Romanticism in science. Science in Europe, 1790–1840 (pp. 75–89). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, D., Clifford, P., & Friesen, S. (2003). Back to the basics of teaching and learning. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, E. (2007). School science: A questionable construct? Journal of Curriculum Studies, 39, 265–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, E., & Nelson, N. (2005). Important but not for me: Students’ attitudes toward secondary school science in England. Research in Science and Technological Education, 23, 41–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joplin, L. (1981). On defining experiential education. The Journal of Experiential Education, 4, 17–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790). Critique of judgement. In: A. Zweig (1970) (Ed.), The essential Kant (pp. 384–412) (James Creed Meredith, Trans.). Mentor: New York.

  • Kellert, S. (2002). Experiencing nature: Affective, cognitive and evaluative development in children. In P. Kahn & S. Kellert (Eds.), Children and nature (pp. 117–151). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kipnis, N. (2005). Chance in science: The discovery of electromagnetism by H. C. Oersted. Science & Education, 14, 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kloncher, J. (2013). Transfiguring the art and science: Knowledge and cultural institutions in the romantic age. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, D. (1990). Romanticism and the sciences. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine (Eds.), Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 13–25). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koballa, T., & Glynn, S. M. (2007). Attitudinal and motivational constructs in science learning. In S. K. Abell & N. Lederman (Eds.), Handbook for research in science education (pp. 75–102). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kodakos, A. (1992). Menschen brauchen Mythen. Eine Studie zum Bildungswert des Mythos. Elfant Verlag, Stuttgart.

  • Kohlstedt, S. (2010). Teaching children science: Hands-on nature study in North America, 1890–1930. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, C. (1990). The power and the glory: Humphry Davy and romanticism. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine (Eds.), Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 213–227). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N. (1992). Students’ and teachers’ conceptions of the nature of science: A review of the research. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 29, 331–359.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N., Abd-El-Khalick, F., Bell, R., & Schwartz, R. (2002). Views of nature of science questionnaire: Toward a valid and meaningful assessment of learners’ conceptions of nature of science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 39, 497–521.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrs, E. (1958). Man or matter: Introduction to a spiritual understanding of matter based on Goethe’s method of training, observation and thought. London: Faber & Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemke, J. (1990). Talking science. Language, learning, values. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Limon, M. (2001). On the cognitive conflict as an instructional strategy for conceptual change. Learning and Instruction, 11, 613–623.

  • Littledyke, M. (1996). Science education for environmental awareness in a postmodern world. Environmental Education Research, 2, 197–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1994). Science teaching: The role of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1997). Scheffler revisited on the role of history and philosophy of science in science teacher education. In H. Siegel (Ed.), Reason and education: Essays in honor of Israel Scheffler (pp. 159–173). Dordrecht: Kluwer Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (Ed.). (1998). Constructivism in science education. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2002). Teaching science. In R. R. Curren (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of education (pp. 342–353). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2015). Science teaching: The contribution of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurice Merleau-Ponty, M. (1985). Between phenomenology and structuralism. New York: St. Martin’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, A. (1970). Karl Friedrich Burdach and his place in the history of neuroanatomy. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery and Psychiatry, 33, 553–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, J. (2007). The holistic curriculum. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milne, I. (2010). A sense of wonder arising from aesthetic experiences should be the starting point for inquiry in primary science. Science Education International, 21, 102–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. H. (1994). Wechselwirkung in the life and other sciences: A word, new claims and a concept around 1800 … and much later. In S. Poggi & M. Bossi (Eds.), Romanticism in science. Science in Europe, 1790–1840 (pp. 1–14). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niaz, M. (2000). The oil-drop experiment: A rational reconstruction of the Millikan–Ehrenhaft controversy and its implications for chemistry textbooks. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 37, 480–508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niaz, M. (2009). Progressive transitions in chemistry teachers’ understanding of nature of science based on historical controversies. Science & Education, 18, 43–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niaz, M. (2010). Science curriculum and teacher education: The role of presuppositions, contradictions, controversies and speculations vs. Kuhn’s ‘normal science’. Teaching and Teacher Education, 26, 891–899.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolson, M. (1990). Alexander Von Humboldt and the geographical vegetation. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine, (Eds.) Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 169-188). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Nola, R., & Irzik, G. (2005). Philosophy, science, education and culture. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Opdal, P. M. (2001). Curiosity, wonder and education seen as perspective development. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 20, 331–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, J. (1996). Beyond constructivism. Science Education, 80, 53–82.

  • Østergaard, E., Dahlin, B., & Hugo, A. (2008). Doing phenomenology in science education: A research review. Studies in Science Education, 44, 93–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Sullivan, E. (2002). The project and vision of transformative education. In E. O’Sullivan, A. Morrell, & M. O’Connor (Eds.), Expanding the boundaries of transformative learning (pp. 1–12). New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pantidos, P., Ravanis, K., Valakas, K., & Vitoratos, E. (2014). Incorporating poeticality into the teaching of physics. Science & Education, 23, 621–642.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papacosta, P. (2008). The mystery in science: A neglected tool in science education. Science Education International, 19, 5–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pedretti, E., & Nazir, J. (2011). Currents in STSE education: Mapping a complex field, 40 years on. Science Education, 95, 863–880.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R. (1967). What is an educational process? In R. Peters (Ed.), The concept of education (pp. 1–23). New York: The Humanity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phenix, P. (1964). Realms of meaning. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1970). Genetic epistemology. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, M. (1993). Auguste Comte: An intellectual biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pintrich, P. R., Marx, R. W., & Boyle, R. A. (1993). Beyond cold conceptual change: The role of motivational beliefs and classroom contextual factors in the process of conceptual change. Review of Educational Research, 63, 167–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, S. (1994). Neurobiology and biology in the romantic age in Germany: Carus, Burdach, Gall, Von Baer. In S. Poggi & M. Bossi (Eds.), Romanticism in science. Science in Europe, 1790–1840 (pp. 143–159). Dordrecht, London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, S., & Bossi, M. (Eds.). (1994). Romanticism in science. Science in Europe, 1790–1840. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, G., Strike, K., Hewson, P., & Gertzog, W. (1982). Accommodation of a scientific conception: Towards a theory of conceptual change. Science Education, 66, 211–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pugh, K. J. (2002). Teaching for transformative experiences in science: An investigation of the effectiveness of two instructional elements. Teachers College Record, 104, 1101–1137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pugh, K. (2004). Newton’s laws beyond the classroom walls. Science Education, 88, 182–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pugh, K. J. (2011). Transformative experience: An integrative construct in the spirit of Deweyan pragmatism. Educational Psychologist, 46, 107–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pugh, K. J., & Girod, M. (2007). Science, art and experience: Constructing a science pedagogy from Dewey’s aesthetics. Journal of Science Teacher Education, 18, 9–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (1987). Darwin and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (1992). The meaning of evolution: The morphological construction and ideological reconstruction of Darwin’s theory. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (2001). A new aesthetic for environmental awareness: Chaos theory, the beauty of nature, and our broader humanistic identity. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 41, 59–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (2002). The romantic conception of life. Science and philosophy in the age of Goethe. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. J. (2006). Nature is poetry of mind or how Schelling solved Goethe’s Kantian problems. In M. Friedman & A. Nordmann (Eds.), The Kantian legacy in the nineteenth century science (pp. 27–50). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, S. (1981). Philosophical mysteries. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, W.-M., & Desautels, J. (Eds.). (2002). Science education as/for sociopolitical action. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, M., & Jornet, A. (2013). Toward a theory of experience. Science Education,. doi:10.1002/sce.21085.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, W.-M., & Lee, S. (2004). Science education as/for participation in the community. Science Education, 88, 263–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupke, N. A. (1990). Caves, fossils and the history of the earth. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine (Eds.), Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 241–262). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saçkes, M., Trundle, K. C., Bell, R. L., & O’Connell, A. A. (2011). The influence of early science experience in kindergarten on children’s immediate and later science achievement: Evidence from the early childhood longitudinal study. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 48, 217–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E. (2007). The periodic table. Its story and its significance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R. (2004). Making minds less well educated than our own. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, I. (1970/1973). Philosophy and the curriculum. In: Reason and teaching (pp. 31–44). London: Routledge, 1973. Reprinted in Science & Education 1992, 1, 384–394.

  • Schiller, F. (1795/1993a). Letters on the aesthetic education of man. In W. Hinderer & D. O. Dahlstrom (Eds.), F. Schiller: Essays (pp. 86–178). New York: Continuum.

  • Schiller, F. V. (1795/1993b). On naïve and sentimental poetry. In W. Hinderer & D. O. Dahlstrom (Eds.), F. Schiller: Essays (pp. 179–260). New York: Continuum.

  • Schiller, F. (2006). Aesthetical and philosophical essays. Retrieved from www.gutenberg.net. February 12, 2014.

  • Schulz, R. (2009a). Reforming science education: Part 1: The search for a philosophy of science education. Science & Education, 18, 225–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, R. (2009b). Reforming science education: Part II. Utilizing Kieran Egan’s educational metatheory. Science & Education, 18, 251–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, R. (2014). Philosophy of education and science education: A vital but underdeveloped relationship. In M. R. Matthews (Ed.), Handbook of research on history, philosophy and science teaching (pp. 1259–1315). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seamon, D., & Zajonc, A. (Eds.). (1998). Goethe’s way of science: A phenomenology of nature. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaffer, E. S. (1990). Romantic philosophy and the organization of disciplines: The founding of the Humboldt University of Berlin. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine (Eds.), Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 38–54). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snelders, H. (1970). Romanticism and Naturphilosophie. Studies in Romanticism, 9, 193–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snelders, H. (1990). Oersted’s discovery of electromagnetism. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine (Eds.), Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 228–240). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, J. (1994). The rise and fall of constructivism. Studies in Science Education, 23, 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1982). The Phenomenological movement: An historical introduction. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, R. (2000). Nature’s open secret. Introductions to Goethe’s scientific writings. (J. Barnes, Trans.). Great Barrington, MA: Anthroposophic Press.

  • Stinner, A. (2003). Scientific method, imagination and the teaching of physics. Physics in Canada, 59, 335–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stone, R. (2006). Curiosity as the thief of wonder. Kronoscope, 6, 205–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strike, K., & Posner, G. (1992). A revisionist theory of conceptual change. In R. Duschl & R. Hamilton (Eds.), Philosophy of science, cognitive psychology, and educational theory and practice (pp. 147–176). New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, C. (1996). Beliefs about science and beliefs about language. International Journal of Science Education, 18, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swimme, B. (1988). The cosmic creation story. In D. R. Griffin (Ed.), The Reenchantment of science: Postmodern proposals (pp. 47–56). New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, J. (1998). Poetic knowledge. The recovery of education. New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, T. (1812). The history of the Royal Society. London: Robert Baldwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1976). Knowing and acting. An invitation to philosophy. New York: McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1982). Cosmopolis: The hidden agenda of modernity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valle, R., & Halling, S. (Eds.). (1989). Existential-phenomenological perspectives in psychology. New York: Plenum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Manen, M. (1990). Researching lived experience: Human science for an action sensitive pedagogy. Ontario: The University of Western Ontario.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verhoven, C. (1972). The philosophy of wonder. New York: McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, K., & Zeidler, D. (2007). Promoting discourse about socio-scientific issues through scaffolded inquiry. International Journal of Science Education, 29, 1387–1410.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, P. (2010). The German genius. Europe’s third renaissance, the second scientific revolution, and the twentieth century. New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watts, M. (2001). Science and poetry: Passion v. prescription in school science? International Journal of Science Education, 23, 197–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wetzels, W. (1990). Johann Wilhelm Ritter: Romantic physics in Germany. In A. Cunningham & N. Jardine (Eds.), Romanticism and the sciences (pp. 199–212). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, M. (1997). Isaac Newton—The last sorcerer. London: Fourth Estate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1933). Adventure of ideas. New York: McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wickmann, P. (2006). Aesthetic experience in science education: Learning and meaning making as situated talk and action. New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. (1986). Biophilia. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. (1998). Consilience. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witz, K. (1996). Science with values and values for science. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 28, 597–612.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humboldt, A. (n.d.). A sketch of a physical description of the universe (Vol. 1, E. Otte, Trans.). New York: Harper.

  • Yager, R. E. (1996). Science/technology/society as reform in science education. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yager, R. (2007). STS requires changes in teaching. Bulletin of Science, Technology & Society, 27, 386–390.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeidler, D., Sadler, T., Simmons, M., & Howes, E. (2005). Beyond STS: A research-based framework for socioscientific issues education. Science Education, 89, 357–377.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yannis Hadzigeorgiou.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hadzigeorgiou, Y., Schulz, R. Romanticism and Romantic Science: Their Contribution to Science Education. Sci & Educ 23, 1963–2006 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-014-9711-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-014-9711-0

Keywords

Navigation