Skip to main content
Log in

Call or Question: a Rehabilitation of Conscience as Dialogical

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is by way of the call that one is enabled to wake up to responsibility. What is the illocutionary mood of the ‘call’ of conscience, though? Is this transcendental enabler of responsibility an imposing demand or an invitational question? Both Levinas and Heidegger emphasize the impositional character of the call(er) in conscience. The call seems to be the very essence of imperatives. I develop an apology for questioning by way of appeal to crumbs scattered throughout Jewish traditions as well as throughout the works of Levinas and Heidegger. Perhaps we are invited to be rather than told to be.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Nietzsche writes, ‘Everywhere [responsibility] is sought, it is usually the instinct for punishing and judging which seeks it. One has deprived becoming of its innocence if being in this or that state is traced back to will, to intentions, to accountable acts: the doctrine of the will has been invented [primarily] for the purpose of punishment, that is of finding guilty…’ (Nietzsche 1990, p. 63). Cf. Nietzsche 2008, pp. 65–74; and Nietzsche 2001, §§114–117, 122, 273–275.

  2. Chretien, for instance, claims that the ‘call creates the respondent,’ and ‘springing into being, we answer’ (Chretien 2004, pp. 16–17). Cf. Ricoeur 2000.

  3. Cf. Freud 1961, pp. 11–21.

  4. A pervasive caricature of dialogue and questioning accompanies overemphasis on the call as demand. See, as examples, Levinas 1998a, b, c, d, e, f, g, h and Ricoeur 2000.

  5. Cf. Berling 1987.

  6. Jesus, for example, is depicted asking over three hundred questions throughout the Gospels. The classical literatures of Chan, and the normative models of Zen practice emerging from that literature, are permeated with questions as well. I have addressed this elsewhere (Dickman 2016a).

  7. I want to note here explicitly Plato’s characterization of thought as the soul’s conversation with itself (Plato 1997a, pp. 263a and b , 189e). See also Seeskin 1987.

  8. For broader historical context of reflection on conscience in Western thought, particularly in ethics, see Sorabji 2014. In contrast to Sorabji, I am here concerned more with the ontologically constitutive character of the call of conscience than with the morally constitutive character of the call.

  9. See Nussbaum 1995, Risser 1997, and Vanhoozer 1997.

  10. As Searle writes, ‘There are… five general categories of illocutionary acts. We tell people how things are (Assertives), we try to get people to do things (Directives), we commit ourselves to doing things (Commissives), we express our feelings and attitudes (Expressives), and we bring about changes in the world through our utterances (Declarations)’ (Searle 1979, viii). See also Austin 1976 and Searle 1969.

  11. See also Althusser 1994 and Butler 1997.

  12. Cf. Stenström 1984, p. 39.

  13. See also Hintikka 1976, p. 22.

  14. See also Kearsley 1976, p. 358; Quirk and Greenbaum 1973, p. 197; and Leech and Svartvik 1975, p. 283.

  15. Cf. Butler 1997.

  16. Since this forms the basic theme of this essay, it will be elaborated further below. See especially the section on Heidegger on the constitutive character of the call.

  17. Below we will see that this dimension of the call more adequately accounts for the divine word in creation.

  18. I have addressed this aspect of Speech Act approaches to questions (Dickman 2009b).

  19. See also Fiumara 1990, 2003.

  20. As Heidegger writes, ‘Speaking is at the same time also listening [my emphasis]. It is the custom to put speaking and listening in opposition: one [person] speaks, the other listens. But listening accompanies and surrounds not only speaking such that takes place in conversation…. Speaking is of itself a listening [my emphasis]. Speaking is listening to the language which we speak. Thus, it is a listening not while but before we are speaking. The listening to language also comes before all other kinds of listening that we know, in a most inconspicuous manner. We do not merely speak the language—we speak by way of it. We can do so solely because we have already listened to the language’ (Heidegger 1982a, b, pp. 123–124; my emphasis). We inherit a language, participating in a form of life, and we add to the language by our responses to what and with what we inherit.

  21. This is what teachers expect in active learning from students, that their active engagement includes asking questions. The questions are among the teacher’s clues that students are listening (or not, depending on the character of their questions!).

  22. See Gadamer 2004. Gadamer writes, ‘The close relation between questioning and understanding is what gives the hermeneutic experience its true dimension’ (2004, p. 376).

  23. Cf. Gadamer 2007, pp. 102–104; and Grondin 1994, p. 38.

  24. He writes, ‘The insufficiency of the needy [one is] precisely in that it does not entirely possess its being and consequently is not strictly speaking separate’ (ibid.).

  25. For further elaboration on this, see Levinas 1989, where he writes, alluding to the surplus of the burning bush, ‘The “less” is forever bursting open, unable to contain the “more” that it contains, in the form of “the one for the other”’ (p. 209).

  26. See Heschel 1976, p. 144; Muffs 2005, p. 30; Fishbane 1987; Cohn-Sherbok 2003, pp. 194–209; Jonas 2000; and Kamenetz 2007.

  27. Recall here Chretien on the ontological function of the call: the call creates respondent; springing into being, we answer (2004, pp. 16–17).

  28. In English, the serpent apparently asks the first question (Genesis 3:1), ‘Did God really say: You shall not eat of any tree in the garden?’ In the Hebrew, this might not be a question. See White 1991, p. 130; and Brown et al. 2007, pp. 64–65. In only 5 cases of אַף, out of over 50 other uses, does it seem to work as an interrogative particle. However, in the majority of these instances, it also serves to make the statement an exaggeration. Considered in this way, the serpent, then, attempts to provoke his interlocutor, Isha (אִשָׁה), to put her on the defensive through deliberate overstatement of the biblical God’s prohibition, and thus attempts to draw out a reaction. Alter, for instance, translates the serpent’s statement as follows, ‘Though God said, you shall not eat from any tree in the garden—’ (Alter 2004, p. 24). Isha interrupts the serpent in order to correct him. Deliberate overstatement in a challenging tone does not constitute a question. Thus, rather than the serpent, it seems to be the biblical God who poses the very first question in the entirety of the Hebrew Bible.

  29. See Rashi 2008 and Zornberg 2006, p. 207.

  30. See Cohn-Sherbok 2003, pp. 214–217; Cohn-Sherbok 1999, pp. 78–79; and Jonas 2000.

  31. Early in his analysis of the hermeneutic priority of the question, Gadamer briefly distinguishes between roughly four kinds of questions in order to show that only one of these kinds truly counts as a genuine question. For Gadamer, whereas pedagogical questions have no questioner, rhetorical questions have neither a questioner nor an object in question. Moreover, ‘slanted questions’—or what we may be more familiar with as ‘loaded questions’—are matters that have already been decided, and so are not really questions. These three—the pedagogical, the rhetorical, and the slanted question—are, for Gadamer, not real questions. It is only ‘real’ questions that count as having hermeneutic priority. See Gadamer 2004, pp. 357–358. Cf. Fenves 1993, p. 21.

  32. Consider, for example, the game of Twenty Questions. Technological advances have led to the automation of questioning technologies such as with the popular hand-held game called “20Q.” This game is a version of the traditional game of 20 questions, but instead of playing against another person, it is a computer that asks the questions in order to figure out what the human player is thinking. The inventor claims that the internet version of the game of the same name manifests artificial intelligence. See ‘About Us,’ 2009 and Dickman 2009c.

  33. See Dickman 2009b.

  34. See Plato 1997a, b, pp. 263a and 189e; and Seeskin 1987.

  35. See Ricoeur’s critique of Levinas’s hyperbole (Ricoeur 1995a, b, pp. 319–355; and Ricoeur 2004).

  36. I am here thinking of the early Buddhist metaphysic of ‘pratitya-samutpada,’ or dependent arising. See Ronkin 2009, p. 14; Nāgārjuna 1995; and Matsumoto 1997, p. 166. I address possible relations between Gadamerian hermeneutics and Buddhist ontology elsewhere (Dickman 2016b).

  37. Elsewhere Gadamer writes, ‘…this is the real and fundamental nature of a question: namely to make things indeterminate. Questions always bring out the undetermined possibilities of a thing’ (Gadamer 2004, p. 367). Coltman translates Gadamer this way: ‘Such bringing-into-suspension… is the proper and original essence of questioning. Questioning always allows the possibilities of a situation to be seen in suspension’ (Coltman 1998, p. 109). The following is the original German: ‘…solches In-die-Schwebe-bringen ist das eigene und ursprüngliche Wesen des Fragens. Fragen läßt immer in der Schwebe befindliche Möglichkeiten sehen’ (Gadamer 1965, p. 357).

  38. The type of wonder I am isolating here is in part corroborated by Chretien’s reflections on the call of Beauty. See Chretien 2004.

  39. See also Grondin 1994, p. 38.

  40. For further elaboration, see Dickman 2014.

  41. I think of Socrates in the marketplace here. Cf. Vanhoozer 1997.

  42. See Schleiermacher 1996 and Tillich 2001.

  43. My edit is merited by virtue of Chretien’s statements about the call that follow below. For example, Chretien writes, ‘The question and call are one’ (2004, p. 48).

  44. Cf. Butler 2005.

  45. See Heidegger on the call and ‘guilt’ below.

  46. As Chretien emphasizes, we leave open the possibilities of the ‘caller’ (2004, p. 42).

  47. I do not think that it does. As Gadamer indicates, when we participate in conversation and shared questioning we are trying to understand not the other, but what she says (Gadamer 2004, p. 387). This respects the autonomy of the other without objectifying the other as lower or higher than one. Rather than symmetry or asymmetry, this is a matter of synergy.

  48. See also Chretien 2004, p. 70.

  49. Cf. Levinas 1998b, p. 107.

  50. Heidegger claims that, ‘The posing of the question includes two things: (1) the definite indication of what is put into question, what is interrogated; [and] (2) the indication of that with regards to which what is interrogated is interrogated—what is asked about’ (Heidegger 2000, p. 24).

  51. There are, however, technically three crucial dimensions of a question: (a) the activity of questioning (Fragen), (b) the subject matter which orients the activity (ein Gefragtes), and (c) the interrogated object through which the activity is fulfilled when the search is completed (ein Befragtes) (ibid.). The original German is as follows: ‘Jedes Fragen ist ein Suchen. Jedes Suchen hat sein vorgängiges Geleit aus dem Gesuchen her. Fragen ist erkennendes Suchen des Seienden in seinem Daß- und Sosein. Das erkennende Suchen kann zum »Untersuchen« warden als dem freilegenden Bestimmen dessen, wonach die Frage steht. Das Fragen hat als Fragen nach…sein Gefragtes. Alles Fragen nach…ist in irgendeiner Weise Anfragen bei…Zum Fragen gehört außer dem Gefragten ein Befragtes. In der untersuchenden, d. h. spezifisch theoretischen Frage soll das Gefragte bestimmt und zu Begriff gebracht warden. Im Gefragten liegt dann als das eigentlich Intendierte das Erfragte, das, wobei das Fragen ins Ziel kommt. Das Fragen selbst hat als Verhalten eines Seienden, des Fragers, einen eigenen Charakter des Seins. Ein Fragen kann vollzogen warden als »Nur-so-hin-fragen« oder als explizite Fragestellung. Das Eigentümliche dieser liegt darin, daß das Fragen sich zuvor nach all den genannten konstitutiven Charakteren der Frage selbst durchsichtig wird’ (Heidegger 1977, p. 7). See Klemm 1987, p. 449.

  52. For a closer examination of the differences on questioning between Levinas and Heidegger (through Tillich as a proxy for Heidegger), see Dickman 2009a.

  53. See Ricoeur 1969. I intend this essay as a whole as an exercise in demythology as the existential interpretation of religious symbols and myth, as rooted in Tillich 2001 and, of course, Bultmann 1989.

  54. I have examined this phenomena in religious literature elsewhere (Dickman 2016a).

References

  • “About Us,” (2009). 20Q.net, Inc. http://www.20q.net. Accessed March 17.

  • Alster-Elata, G., & Salmon, R. (1993). Biblical covenants as performative language. In E. Spolsky (Ed.), Summoning: ideas of the covenant and interpretive theory (pp. 27–46). Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, R. (1981). The art of biblical narrative. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, R. (2004). The five books of Moses: a translation with commentary. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Althusser, L. (1994). Ideology and ideological state apparatuses. In S. Zizek (Ed.), Mapping Ideology (pp. 100–140). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1976). How to do things with words, 2nd edition. J. O. Urmson and M. Sbisá (Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Beatty, J. (1999). Good listening. Educational Theory, 49, 281–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, M. (1975). Questioning. Philosophical Quarterly, 25(100), 193–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berling, J. A. (1987). Bringing the Buddha down to earth. History of Religions, 27(1), 56–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blum, R. (1983). Emmanuel Levinas’ theory of commitment. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 44(2), 145–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Francis, S. R. Driver, and Charles A. Briggs. (2007). The Brown-Drivers-Briggs Hebrew and English Lexicon. F. Brown, S. Driver, and C. Briggs (Ed.). Peabody, Mass.: Hendrickson.

  • Buber, M. (1967a). Jewish religiosity. In N. Glatzer (Ed.), On Judaism (pp. 79–94). New York: Shocken Books Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1967b). The holy way. In N. Glatzer (Ed.), On Judaism (pp. 108–148). New York: Shocken Books Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1967c). The dialogue between heaven and earth. In N. Glatzer (Ed.), On Judaism (pp. 214–226). New York: Shocken Books Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bublitz, W. (1988). Supportive fellow-speakers and cooperative conversation. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bultmann, R. (1989). New Testament & mythology: and other basic writings. S. Ogden (Ed. And Trans.). Grand Rapids: Fortress Press.

  • Butler, J. (1997). Conscience doth make subjects of us all. In The psychic life of power: theories in subjection (pp. 106–131). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (2005). Giving an account of oneself. New York: Fordham University Press.

  • Cherbonnier, E. LaB. (1962). The logic of biblical anthropomorphism. The Harvard Theological Review, 55(3), 187–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chretien, J-L. (2004). The call and the response. A. Davenport (Trans.). New York: Fordham University Press.

  • Cohn-Sherbok, D. (1999). Judaism: a short history. London: Oneworld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohn-Sherbok, D. (2003). Judaism: history, belief, and practice. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coltman, R. (1998). The language of hermeneutics: Gadamer and Heidegger in dialogue. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davey, N. (2006). Unquiet Understanding: Gadamer’s Philosophical Hermeneutics. Albany: SUNY Press.

  • Davis, D. (2005). Addressing alterity: rhetoric, hermeneutics, and nonappropriative relation. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 38(3), 191–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1987). On reading Heidegger. Research in Phenomenology, 17(1), 171–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickman, N. E. (2009a). The challenge of asking engaging questions. Currents in Teaching and Learning, 2(1), 3–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickman, N. E. (2009b). Anxiety and the face of the other: Tillich and Levinas on the origin of questioning. Sophia, 48, 267–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickman, N. E. (2009c). Twenty questions. In R. Carlisle (Ed.), The encyclopedia of play. Sage Publications, Inc.

  • Dickman, N. E. (2014). Between Gadamer and Ricoeur: preserving dialogue in the hermeneutic arc for the sake of a God who speaks and listens. Sophia, 53, 553–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickman, N. E. (2016a). The questions of Jesus and Mazu: human or beyond? Literature and Theology, 30, 343–358.

  • Dickman, N. E. (2016b) Linguistically mediated liberation: Freedom and limits of understanding in thich Nhat Hanh and Hans-Georg Gadamer. The Humanistic Psychologist, 44(3),256–279.

  • Dickman, N. E. (2017). Transcendence un-extra-ordinaire: bringing the atheistic I down to earth. Religions, 8. doi:10.3390/rel8010004

  • Ebeling, G. (1963). Theological reflections on conscience. In J. Leitch (Ed.), Word and faith (pp. 407–423). Philadelphia: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenves, P. (1993). “Chatter”: language and history in Kierkegaard. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fichte, J. (1987). The vocation of man. P. Preuss (Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Fishbane, M. A. (1987). Judaism: revelation and traditions. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiumara, G. C. (1990). The other side of language: a philosophy of listening. C. Lambert (Trans.). New York: Routledge.

  • Fiumara, G. C. (2003). The development of hermeneutical prospects. In L. Code (Ed.), Feminist interpretations of Hans-Georg Gadamer (pp. 133–148). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1961). Civilization and its discontents. J. Strachey (Trans.). New York: W.W. Norton and Company, Inc.

  • Gadamer, H.-G. (1965). Wahrheit und Methode: Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik (2nd ed.). Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H-G. (2004). Truth and method, 2nd revised edition. Joel Weinshimer and Donald G. Marshall (Trans). New York: Continuum.

  • Gadamer, H.-G. (2007). Language and understanding. In R. Palmer (Ed.), The Gadamer reader: a bouquet of the later writings. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, R. (2001). When listeners talk: response tokens and listener stance. Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goody, E. N. (1978). Towards a theory of questions. In E. Goody (Ed.), Questions and politeness (pp. 17–43). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graesser, A. C., & Person, N. K. (1994). Question asking during tutoring. American Educational Research Journal, 31, 104–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grondin, J. (1994). Introduction to philosophical hermeneutics. J. Weinsheimer (Trans.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Hancher, M. (1988). Performative utterance, the word of God, and the death of the author. Semeia, 41, 27–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrah, D. (1987). Hintikka’s theory of questions. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Jakko Hintikka (pp. 199–213). Boston: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1977). Gesamtausgabe, Abt. 1, Bd 2, Veröffentlichte Schriften 1914–1917, Sein und Zeit. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.

  • Heidegger, M. (1982a). The way to language. In P. Hertz (Ed.), On the way to language (pp. 111–139). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1982b). The nature of language. In P. Hertz (Ed.), On the way to language (pp. 57–110). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1993). The question concerning technology. In D. Krell & W. Lovitt (Eds.), Basic writings, revised and expanded edition (pp. 307–342). New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1996). Being and time: a translation of Sein und Zeit. J. Stambaugh (Trans.). New York: SUNY Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2000). Introduction to metaphysics. G. Fried and R. Polt (Trans.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Language. In A. Holfstadter (Ed.), Poetry, language, thought (pp. 185–208). New York: Perrenial Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heschel, A. (1976). Man is not alone: a philosophy of religion. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1976). The semantics of questions and the questions of semantics: case studies in the interrelations of logic, semantics, and syntax. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (2000). The concept of God after Auschwitz: a Jewish voice. In M. Morgan (Ed.), A Holocaust reader (pp. 259–270). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamenetz, R. (2007). The Jew and the lotus: a poet’s rediscovery of Jewish identity. New York: HaperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearsley, G. P. (1976). Questions and question asking in verbal discourse: a cross-disciplinary review. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 5(4), 355–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1980). The sickness unto death. H. and E. Hong (Trans.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Klemm, D. (1987). Toward a rhetoric of postmodern theology: through Barth and Heidegger. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 55(3), 443–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koshik, I. (2005). Alternative questions use in conversational repair. Discourse Studies, 7(2), 193–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, R. (2002). The ontology and temporality of conscience. Continental Philosophy Review, 35, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawlor, L. (2003). Thinking through French philosophy: the being of the question. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leech, G., & Svartvik, J. (1975). A communicative grammar of English. London: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1969). Totality and infinity: an essay on exteriority. A. Lingis (Trans.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1989). Revelation in the Jewish tradition. In S. Hand (Ed.), The Levinas reader (pp. 190–210). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1990a). A religion for adults. In S. Hand (Ed.), Difficult freedom: essays in Judaism (pp. 11–24). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1990b). Loving the Torah more than God. In S. Hand (Ed.), Difficult freedom: essays in Judaism (pp. 142–145). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998a). Nonintentional consciousness. In M. Smith & B. Harshav (Eds.), Entre Nous: on thinking-of-the-other (pp. 123–132). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998b). Dying for…”. In M. Smith & B. Harshav (Eds.), Entre Nous: on thinking-of-the-other (pp. 207–218). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998c). Hermeneutics and beyond. In B. Bergo (Ed.), Of God who comes to mind (pp. 100–110). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998d). Hermeneutics and beyond. In M. Smith & B. Harshav (Eds.), Entre Nous: on thinking-of-the-other (pp. 65–76). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998e). Is ontology fundamental? In M. Smith & B. Harshav (Eds.), Entre Nous: on thinking-of-the-other (pp. 1–12). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998f). Notes on meaning. In B. Bergo (Ed.), Of God who comes to mind (pp. 152–171). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998g). The I and the totality. In M. Smith & B. Harshav (Eds.), Entre Nous: on thinking-of-the-other (pp. 13–38). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1998h). Totality and infinity: preface to the German edition. In M. Smith & B. Harshav (Eds.), Entre Nous: on thinking-of-the-other (pp. 197–200). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Llewelyn, J. (2002). Levinas and language. In S. Critchley & R. Bernasconi (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Levinas (pp. 119–138). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Matsumoto, S. (1997). The doctrine of Tathagata-garbha is not Buddhist. In J. Hubbard & P. Swanson (Eds.), Pruning the Bodhi tree: the storm over critical Buddhism (pp. 165–173). Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.

  • Morgan, N., & Saxton, J. (2006). Asking better questions (2nd ed.). Markham, Ontario: Pembroke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muffs, Y. (2005). The personhood of God: biblical theology, human faith and the divine image. Woodstock: Jewish Lights.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nāgārjuna. (1995). The fundamental wisdom of the middle way. J. Garfield (Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Nealon, J. (1997). Ethics of dialogue: Bakhtin and Levinas. College English, 59(2), 129–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neusner, J. (1988). The incarnation of God: the character of divinity in formative Judaism. Philadelphia: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neusner, J. (1993). The way of Torah: an introduction to Judaism (5th ed.). Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1990). Twilight of the idols and the anti-Christ: or how to philosophize with a hammer. R.J. Hollingdale (Trans.). New York: Penguin Books.

  • Nietzsche, F. (2001). The gay science. Josefine Nauckhoff (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Nietzsche, F. (2008). On the genealogy of morals. Douglas Smith (Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Novak, D. (2000). Is the covenant a bilateral relationship? A response to Eugene Borowitz’s Renewing the covenant. In P. Ochs (Ed.), Reviewing the covenant: Eugene B. Borowitz and the postmodern renewal of Jewish theology (pp. 81–90). New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1995). Objectification. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 24(4), 249–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1997a). Sophist. In J. Cooper & D. Hutchinson (Eds.), Plato: complete works (pp. 235–293). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1997b). Theaetetus. In J. Cooper & D. Hutchinson (Eds.), Plato: complete works (pp. 157–234). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quirk, R., & Greenbaum, S. (1973). A concise grammar of contemporary English. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rashi. (2008). The complete Tanach with Rashi. Rabbi A. J. Rosenberg (Ed. And Trans.). New York: Judaica Press. http://www.chabad.org/library/bible_cdo/aid/8167/showrashi/true. Accessed March 19, 2009.

  • Ricoeur, P. (1969). The symbolism of evil. E. Buchanan (Trans.). Boston: Beacon Press.

  • Ricoeur, P. (1974). Religion, atheism, faith. In D. Ihde (Ed.), The conflict of interpretations (pp. 440–467). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1976). Interpretation theory: discourse and the surplus of meaning. Fort Worth: Texas Christian University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1994). Oneself as Another. K. Blamey (Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Ricoeur, P. (1995). Oneself as another. K. Blamey (Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Ricoeur, P. (1995b). The summoned subject in the school of the narratives of the prophetic vocation. In M. Wallace & D. Pellauer (Eds.), Figuring the sacred: religion, narrative, and imagination (pp. 262–278). Minneapolis: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (2000). Experience and language in religious discourse. In D. Janicaud & B. Prusak (Eds.), Phenomenology and the ‘theological turn’: the French debate. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (2004). Otherwise: a reading of Emmanuel Levinas’s otherwise than being or beyond essence. Yale French Studies, 104, 82–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Risser, J. (1997). Hermeneutics and the voice of the other. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ronkin, N. (2009). Theravada metaphysics and ontology. In W. Edelglass & J. Garfield (Eds.), Buddhist philosophy: essential readings (pp. 13–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schleiermacher, F. (1996). On religion: speeches to its cultured despisers. R. Crouter (Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Searle, J. (1969). Speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1979). Expression and meaning: studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). Conversation. In H. Parret & J. Verschueren (Eds.), (On) Searle on conversation (pp. 7–30). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Seeskin, K. (1987). Dialogue and discovery: a study in Socratic method. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shuchat, W. (2006). The Garden of Eden and the struggle to be human: according to the Midrash Rabbah. Israel: Devora Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (2014). Moral conscience through the ages: Fifth Century BCE to the present. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sousa, P., Pinheiro, R., & Silva, R. (2003). Questions about questions: new views on an old prejudice. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 84, 865–878.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stenström, A.-B. (1984). Questions and responses in English conversation. Malmö, Sweden: CWK Gleerup.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tillich, P. (2001). Dynamics of faith. New York: HaperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanhoozer, K. (1997). Human being, individual and social. In C. Gunton (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Christian Doctrine (pp. 158–188). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vawter, B. (1977). On Genesis: a new reading. Garden City: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, S. (1986). Reason and the face of the other. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 54(1), 33–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, H. C. (1991). Narration and discourse in the Book of Genesis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, G., & McTighe, J. (2005). Understanding by design. Expanded (2nd ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, S. (1989). The sublime object of ideology. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zornberg, A. (2006). Seduced into Eden: the beginning of desire. In J. Petrucelli (Ed.), Longing: psychoanalytic musings on desire (pp. 193–226). London: H. Karnac.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathan Eric Dickman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dickman, N.E. Call or Question: a Rehabilitation of Conscience as Dialogical. SOPHIA 57, 275–294 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-017-0588-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-017-0588-7

Keywords

Navigation