Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The Political Epistemology of Science-Based Policy-Making

  • Social Science and Public Policy
  • Published:
Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Improving the use and impact of science-based policies and practices at the national and transnational level is important for enhancing the quality and legitimacy of democratic governance systems. The purpose of this paper is to provide an overview of the major drivers behind strengthening the creation, application and mediation of scientific expertise for policy-making. Science-based policy-making can take different forms, such as evaluation of practices, implementation of independent or commissioned research, application of quantitative and qualitative analyses, or the development of statistical and environmental monitoring systems. However, scientific evidence is only one among several factors contributing to sound democratic decisions. Scientific expertise needs to be mediated through a complex process of social and political deliberation. The paper aims to identify the main policy challenges behind science advisory bodies and to set out an agenda for rebuilding public trust in science-based policy-making.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Estlund’s theory – which he calls epistemic proceduralism – avoids epistocracy, or the rule of those who know. He argues that while some few people probably do know best, this can be used in political justification only if their expertise is acceptable from all reasonable points of view. If we seek the best epistemic arrangement in this respect, it will be recognisably democratic – with laws and policies actually authorised by the people subject to them.

  2. In New Zealand, chief science adviser Peter Gluckman has described this dual justification in the following way. “Crucially, science advisers are obliged to advise in the context of the policy process. This means elucidating the evidence-informed options, rather than simply advocating a course of action. (…) There are many other appropriate inputs to policy, including fiscal considerations and public opinion. Policy-makers and elected officials rightly guard their responsibility to define policy — and this means choosing between options with different trade-offs” (Gluckman 2014: 164).

  3. In a recent article, Nico Stehr (2013) has labeled this tendency the inconvenience of democracy. Among the voices of this argument are the Australian scholars David Shearman and Joseph W. Smith who in their book The Climate Change Challenge and the Failure of Democracy from 2007 wrote: “We need an authoritarian form of government in order to implement the scientific consensus on greenhouse gas emissions” (cited from Stehr 2013: 58) Furthermore, climate scientist Mark Beeson has claimed that “[…] forms of good authoritarianism, in which environmentally unsustainable forms of behavior are simply forbidden, may become not only justifiable, but essential for the survival of humanity[…]” (cited from Stehr 2013: 58).

  4. Here, I quote in extenso from Arimoto and Sato (2012).

Further Reading

  • Arimoto, T., & Sato, Y. 2012. Rebuilding Public Trust in Science for Policy-making. Science and Society, 337, 1176–1177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bocking, S. 2013. Science and Society: The Structures of Scientific Advice. Global Environmental Politics, 13(2), 154–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Budtz Pedersen, D., & Hendricks, F. H. 2013. Science Bubbles. Philosophy & Technology, 45(3), 250–266.

  • Commission, E. 2008. Scientific Evidence for Policy Making. Brussels: European Commission Directorate-General for Research. Brussels.

  • Contandriopoulos, D., Lemire, M., Denis, J.-L., & Tremblay, E. 2010. Knowledge Exchange Processes in Organizations and Policy Arenas: A Narrative Systematic Review of the Literature. The Milbank Quarterly, 88(4), 444–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, D. M. 2011. Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • EurActiv. 2013. Top EU scientist calls for ethical standards to ease suspicion of industr, Published 11 April 2013, available at: http://www.euractiv.com [accessed 1 November 2013].

  • EuroBarameter 2010. Science and Technology Special Report. Brussels: European Commission. (online version http://ec.europa.eu/public_opinion/archives/ebs/ebs_340_en.pdf)

  • Gardiner, H., & Broad, W. J. 2009. “Scientists Welcome Obama’s Words”, New York Times. January, 21, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gieryn, T. F. 1983. Boundary-Work and the Demarcation of Science from Non-Science: Strains and nterests in Professional Ideologies of Scientists. American Sociological Review, 48(6), 781–795.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gluckman, P. 2014. The art of science advice to government. Nature, 507, 163–165 (13 March 2014).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holdren, J.P. 2011. Next Steps to Ensuring Scientific Integrity, Communication from the White House, October 31, 2011 available at: www.whitehouse.gov [accessed 1 November 2013].

  • Jasanoff, S. 2009. The Essential Parallel between Science and Democracy, Seed Magazine.com, 17 February 2009.

  • Kappel, K. 2012. Democratizing Science: What could it mean?, lecture at the conference “Democratizing Science”, 14 December 2012, University of Copenhagen.

  • Lentsch, J., & Weingart, P. (Eds.). 2011. The Politics of Scientific Advice: Institutional Design for Quality Assurance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowotny, H., Scott, P., & Gibbons, M. 2001. Re-thinking Science: Knowledge and the Public in an Age of Uncertainty. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pielke, R. A. 2007. The Honest Broker: Making Sense of Science in Policy and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stehr, N. 2013. An Inconvenient Democracy: Knowledge and Climate Change. Society, 50(1), 55–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, W. J., Bellingan, L., Bellingham, J. R., Blackstock, J. J., Bloomfield, R. M., et al. 2012. A Collaboratively-Derived Science-Policy Research Agenda. PLoS ONE, 7(3), e31824. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0031824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Budtz Pedersen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pedersen, D.B. The Political Epistemology of Science-Based Policy-Making. Soc 51, 547–551 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12115-014-9820-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12115-014-9820-z

Keywords

Navigation