Skip to main content
Log in

Complexity and institutional evolution

  • Article
  • Published:
Evolutionary and Institutional Economics Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper shows which portions of complexity theory are most relevant for studying economic institutional evolution. This question leads to both the two main competing economics complexity theories: dynamic and computational complexity. Central to this is the concept of cumulative causation, invented by a main founder of institutional economics, Thorstein Veblen, a fact not widely recognized. This provides the basis for increasing returns, multiple equilibria, and bifurcations in the evolution of institutions. A central issue in institutional evolution involves both hierarchical emergence, with the interaction of spontaneous emergence with natural selection a central point. Recognizing these points may provide a new synthesis between the old and new institutional economics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the USA, this society has been closely associated with the so-called “old institutional economics”, whereas we shall argue that an evolutionary approach taking into account complexity can unite the old and new approaches.

  2. It is an open debate whether or not Veblen viewed cumulative causation as necessarily implying economies of scale, although he was aware of the importance of economies of scale in industrial systems. Setterfield (1997) recognizes Veblen’s priority in introducing the concept, but argues that Young (1928) and Kaldor (1972) more clearly tied it to the phenomenon of increasing returns.

  3. Veblen was not the first economist to advocate the usefulness for economics of evolutionary theory, with both Marx and Marshall doing so before he did, even as they did so from very different perspectives. The more complicating factor in all this is the fact that Darwin himself was crucially influenced by Malthus’s work on population when he developed his theory of natural selection (Rosser 1992).

  4. That this is not widely known can be seen in that Business Dictionary identifies the originator of the term as Young (1928) [http://www.businessdictionary.com/definition/cumulative-causation.html] and Wikipedia identifies its originator (actually “Circular cumulative causation”) as being Myrdal (1957) [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Circular_cumulative_causation]. Certainly, Myrdal’s use of the term received widespread attention.

  5. See Rosser (2011, Mathematical Appendix) for such a discussion.

  6. The importance of increasing returns in dynamic complexity has been especially emphasized by Arthur (1994).

  7. The question of the relationship between polynomial or P programs and non-polynomial or NP programs, usually posed as the P! = NP problem, is one of the deepest in computer science and remains unsolved, although most mathematicians and computer scientists believe that they do not equal each other. For recent developments on this and connections with economics, see da Costa and Doria (2016).

  8. Clearly, there is no definitive boundary in observing what is essentially discrete data between what is continuous and discontinuous. In biological evolution, one observes different individuals across generations, and, with the exception of identical twins or clones, each individual’s genotype is discretely distinct from every other’s. Likewise with phenotypes, one might depict the possible variations of a certain physical characteristic on a continuous scale, but individuals will still have discrete differences from other individuals on such characteristics, even if these are very small. Thus, the distinction becomes arbitrary. At the lowest level, we see a discontinuous granularity, but higher level defenders of continuity see only gradual changes, especially in population averages, with it completely open to debate how rapid such changes must be before one can call them discontinuous (see Rosser 2000, Chap. 1, for further discussion of distinguishing continuous from discontinuous forms).

  9. The original formulation of Arthur’s model was from Arthur et al. (1987) and their study of Polya urns.

  10. Curiously, Sewall Wright also focused on animal breeding due to his working for the US Department of Agriculture in the 1920s, where his thinking about this led him to certain of his ideas such as random drift, also known as “the Sewall Wright Effect”, sometimes seen as a violation of strict natural selection in how new species might form, although the separation of genetically distinct sub-groups of a population may happen either randomly in nature or through the conscious control and direction by humans as in animal breeding.

  11. The term “meme” as the locus of evolution is due to Dawkins (1976), who also first proposed the idea of “universal Darwinism”.

  12. How evolution of habits and norms determines tax behavior in societies is studied by Torgler (2016).

  13. Sethi and Somanathan (1996) show that in such games there are multiple Nash equilibria, with some supportive and some destructive of the cooperative equilibria that are consistent with sustainable development. Rosser and Rosser (2006) extend this argument.

  14. See also Stokes (1995).

References

  • Alchian AA (1950) Uncertainty, evolution, and economic theory. J Polit Econ 58:211–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur WB (1994) Increasing returns and path dependence in the economy. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur WB, Ermoliev Yu, Kaniovski Yu (1987) Adaptive growth processes modeled by urn schemes. Cybernetics 23:776–789

    Google Scholar 

  • Axtell RL (2005) The complexity of exchange. Econ J 115:F193–F210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogdanov AA (1925–1929) Tektologia: vseobshchaya organizatsionnay nauka, 3 vol, 3rd edn. Kniga, Leningrad

  • Coase RH (1937) The nature of the firm. Economica 4:386–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Commons JR (1924) The legal foundations of capitalism. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Commons JR (1934) Institutional economics. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Crow JF (1955) General theory of population genetics: synthesis. Cold Spring Harb Symp Quant Biol 20:54–59

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • da Costa NCA, Doria EA (2016) On the O’Donnell algorithm for N P complete problems. Rev Behav Econ 3:221–242

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection or the preservation of favored races in the struggle for life. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Day RH (1994) Complex economic dynamics: an introduction to dynamical systems and market mechanisms: vol I. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dopfer K, Foster J, Potts J (2004) Micro-meso-macro. J Evolut Econ 14:263–279

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eigen M, Schuster P (1979) The hypercycle: a principle of natural self-organization. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eldredge NJ, Gould SJ (1972) Punctuated equilibria. In: Schopf DJM (ed) Models of paleobiology. Freeman, Cooper, San Francisco, pp 82–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1972) Altruism and related phenomena, mainly in the social insects. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 3:192–232

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1952) The sensory order: an inquiry into the foundations of theoretical psychology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1967) The theory of complex phenomena. In: Studies in philosophy, politics, and economics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 22–42

  • Hayek FA (1988) The fatal conceit: the errors of socialism. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich J (2004) Cultural group selection, coevolutionary processes, and large-scale cooperation. J Econ Behav Organ 53:3–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM (1993) institutional economics: surveying the ‘old’ and the ‘new’. Metroeconomica 44:1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson GM, Knutsen T (2006) Why we need a generalized Darwinism and why generalized Darwinism is not enough. J Econ Behav Organ 61:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan J (1997) The end of science: facing the limits of knowledge in the twilight of the scientific age. Broadway Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor N (1972) The irrelevance of equilibrium economics. Econ J 82:1237–1255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koppl R, Rosser JB Jr (2002) All I have to say has already crossed your mind. Metroeconomica 53:339–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewes GH (1875) Problems of life and mind. Trübner, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis P (2012) Emergent properties in the work of Friedrich Hayek. J Econ Behav Organ 82:368–375

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menger C (1923) Grundsätze der volkswirtschaftslehre, zweite auflag. Holden-Pichler-Tempsky, Vienna

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikami M (2011) Evolutionary aspects of Coasean economics. Evolut Inst Econ Rev 8:177–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1843) A system of logic: ratiocinative and inductive. Longmans Green, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Minniti M (1995) Membership has its privileges: old and new mafia organizations. Comp Econ Stud 37:31–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski P (2007) Markets come to bits: evolution, computation, and markomata in economic science. J Econ Behav Organ 63:209–242

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan CL (1923) Emergent evolution. Williams and Norgate, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mueller B (2014) Beliefs and the persistence of inefficient institutions. University of Brasilia Working Paper. http://extranet.sioe.org/uploads/isnie2015/mueller.pdf

  • Myrdal G (1957) Economic theory and underdeveloped regions. Methuen, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson RR, Winter SG (1982) An evolutionary theory of economic change. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ng Y-K (1986) Mesoeconomics: a micro-macro analysis. St.Martins, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • North DC (1990) Institutions, institutional change, and economic progress. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom E (1990) Governing the commons. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papageorgiou T, Katselides I, Michaelides PG (2013) Schumpeter, Commons, and Veblen on institutions. Am J Econ Sociol 72:1232–1254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price G (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227:520–521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Radzicki MJ (1990) Institutional dynamics, deterministic chaos, and self-organizing systems. J Econ Issues 24:57–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr (1991) From catastrophe to chaos: a general theory of economic discontinuities. Kluwer, Boston

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr (1992) The dialogue between the economic and ecologic theories of evolution. J Econ Behav Organ 17:195–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr (2000) From catastrophe to chaos: a general theory of economic discontinuities: mathematics, microeconomics, macroeconomics, and finance, vol II. Kluwer, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr (2004) Epistemological implications of economic complexity. Ann Jpn Assoc Philos Sci 16:485–499

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr (2009) Computational and dynamic complexity in economics. In: Rosser JB Jr (ed) Handbook on research in complexity. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 22–35

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr (2011) Complex evolutionary dynamics in urban-regional and ecologic-economic systems: from catastrophe to chaos and beyond. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr, Rosser MV (2006) Institutional evolution of environmental management under economic growth. J Econ Issues 40:421–429

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr, Rosser MV (2015) Complexity and behavioral economics. Nonlinear Dyn Psychol Life Sci 19:201–226

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosser JB Jr, Rosser MV, Ahmed E (2003) Multiple unofficial economy equilibria and income distribution dynamics in systemic transition. J Post Keynes Econ 25:425–447

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter JA (1911) Theorie der wirschaftlichen Entwicklung. Leipzig: von Dunckar & Humblot (English translation, The Theory of Economic Development, 1934). Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • Schumpeter JA (1954) History of Economic Analysis. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Sethi R, Somanathan E (1996) The evolution of social norms in common property use. Am Econ Rev 80:766–788

    Google Scholar 

  • Setterfield M (1997) Rapid growth and relative decline: modelling macroeconomic dynamics with hysteresis. St. Martins, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity. Proc Am Philos Soc 106:467–482

    Google Scholar 

  • Stokes KM (1995) Man and the biosphere. M.E. Sharpe, Armonk

    Google Scholar 

  • Torgler B (2016) Can tax compliance research profit from biology? Rev Behav Econ 3:113–144

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turing AM (1952) The chemical basis of morphogenesis. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B 237:37–72. doi:10.1098/rstb.1952.0012

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg VJ (1997) Institutional evolution through purposeful selection: the constitutional political economy of John R. Commons. Const Political Econ 8:105–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1898) Why is economics not an evolutionary science? Q J Econ 12:373–397

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1899) The theory of the leisure class: and economic study of institutions. Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen TB (1919) The place of science in modern civilization and other essays. Huebsch, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Velupillai KV (2000) Computable economics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy L (1950) An outline of general systems theory. Br J Philos Sci 1:114–129

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener N (1948) Cybernetics: or control and communication in the animal and the machine. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson OE (1985) The new institutional economics and capitalism: firms, markets, relational contracting. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson OE (2000) The new institutional economics: taking stock, looking forward. J Econ Lit 38:596–613

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson EO (2012) The social conquest of earth. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1932) The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding, and selection in evolution. Proc Int Congr Genet 1:356–366

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1951) The genetical theory of populations. Ann Eugen 15:323–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1988) Surfaces of selective value revisited. Am Nat 131:115–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young AA (1928) Increasing returns and economic progress. Econ J 38:527–542

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Barkley Rosser Jr..

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

This paper involves no conflicts of interest.

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rosser, J.B., Rosser, M.V. Complexity and institutional evolution. Evolut Inst Econ Rev 14, 415–430 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40844-016-0060-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40844-016-0060-3

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation