Skip to main content
Log in

Non-Ideal Accessibility

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. It seems very plausible to me that one role of ideal ‘oughts’ is to reveal standards and values, rather than guide action, in which case it is not necessary that they imply ‘can’. See Lawford-Smith (2010). Graham (2011) has argued recently that positive obligations imply ‘can’ while negative obligations do not, e.g., we ought not kill, whether or not we can help it, but we ought give to charity, only if we have the resources to. For a good survey of the “ought implies can” debate, see Vranas (2007). See also Feldman’s (1986) discussion of accessibility.

  2. See the papers collected in (Robeyns and Swift 2008) and the references in (Simmons 2010).

  3. On the duties of individuals to form collectives see (Collins 2012); on the role of members of collectives in discharging collectives’ duties see (Lawford-Smith 2012a).

  4. That is not to suggest that these jobs exhaust moral and political philosophy. Moral philosophy should also tell us what a good person is like, and how persons ought to be; political philosophy should tell us what a good society is like, and how both domestic and international political culture ought to be. Both tell us about what is good or valuable, as well as what ought to be the case.

  5. In general, conditional obligation is not well understood. It cannot involve the material conditional, because the logic of that conditional makes both the “wide-scope” and the “narrow-scope” readings implausible. Perhaps conditional obligation is best understood as primitive; the issue needs further discussion. See discussion in (Lewis 2000).

  6. Some statements about moral obligation imply that ‘closer is better’, while others are silent on what ought to be the case given their failure to be realised. Percentage of income is linear; it seems clear that if you ought to give 10%, and yet you won’t, the next best thing is 9% (assuming for simplicity that the next percentage is not an integer). But what if you ought to ‘help the others rescue that drowning man’? This says nothing about what to do if the others refuse to cooperate, or you yourself are unwilling or unable to play your part.

  7. Standardly P (S | A) is defined as P (S & A)/P (A), but it might be better to read it ‘subjunctively’—see discussion in (Joyce 2009 Ch. 5). It could also be read as the probability of the counterfactual conditional, namely, A □ → S.

  8. More precisely: the proposition that the action occurs.

  9. This definition of accessibility differs substantially from the account of feasibility that I have defended elsewhere, which refuses any threshold. See (Lawford-Smith 2012b; Gilabert and Lawford-Smith 2012).

  10. The alternative is to make it scalar, in which case instead of blocking a requirement (if it’s not the case that S is non-ideally accessible, then it’s not the case that x ought to A), it would count against a requirement in some to-be-specified way (e.g. the more non-ideally inaccessible S is, the less that x ought to A). But then accessibility ceases to play a negative role by restricting the set of actions/states of affairs that are candidates for what ought to be the case, and starts playing a positive role in what ought to be done/brought about. But that would require a much fuller discussion of how much accessibility should matter in deciding what to do. It can’t be straightforwardly that the more accessible an option is the more it ought to be done, because that would show a strong bias toward the status quo, or states of affairs and actions that are easy to bring about/do. For a nearby discussion on scalar feasibility see (Gilabert and Lawford-Smith 2012; Lawford-Smith 2012b.

  11. Whether there is one unique closest world is controversial. See discussion in Feldman (1986 17).

  12. I assume that we can make sense of an intuitive idea of ‘most of the nearby worlds’, even though strictly speaking possible worlds are infinite.

  13. Here I am assuming that there is a unique closest world where A is the case, and that the objective probability of S given A at the actual world is equivalent to the objective probability that the whole counterfactual conditional ‘if it were the case that A, it would be the case that S’ is true at that unique closest A world. But this is controversial; in general it is an open question whether we can translate talk about probabilities into talk about closeness of worlds. David Lewis has proved that conditional probability is not equivalent to the probability of a conditional (Lewis 1976). Williams and Robert (2011) has an interesting discussion about this result for counterfactual conditionals.

  14. For the decision-theoretic discussion about taking beliefs about one’s own future actions into account, see e.g. (Rabinowicz 2002; Spohn 1977; Levi 1989).

  15. (Jackson 1985; Jackson and Pargetter 1986). Those papers are presumably inspired by the earlier discussion in (Goldman 1976).

  16. I owe this suggestion to David Weins in the context of the Moral, Social and Political Theory Reading Group at the Australian National University, and am grateful to David, Geoff Brennan, Nic Southwood, and Seth Lazar for discussion.

  17. I borrow this example from (Louise 2009). Louise argues that both the oughts are relevant, because people genuinely find themselves caught between doing all that they ought to do, and failing in familiar ways and doing only what they ought to do in light of those failures (see esp. p. 346).

  18. I am grateful to Michael Smith for discussion on this point.

  19. On the usual constraints, see discussion in Gilabert and Lawford-Smith (2012).

  20. See Cordes-de Waal’s (1996) discussion of omissions, and the correlation between omitting agents’ blameworthiness when the omission is intended compared with when it is a non-decision (i.e. the time in which a decision could have been made has simply run out).

  21. I borrow this example from Pablo Gilabert. The other way to go, I suppose, is to say that escaping the office building is inaccessible in the low-stakes case and remains inaccessible even in the high-stakes case, but that sometimes we should do inaccessible things. Because I use accessibility as a way to rule-out obligations, I prefer not to go this way. If the actions are things we should do, then they’re things that it is accessible for us to do (because of the assumption that “ought implies non-ideal accessibility”). They can’t be both inaccessible and something we ought to do.

  22. A further alternative is to take the normativity out of the definition of non-ideal accessibility entirely, and put it into the relevant principle. So we could shift to a non-binary definition, e.g. NIAx (S) = maxA P (S | A) (the non-ideal accessibility of a state of affairs for an agent is equal to the probability of the state of affairs given that action of the agent’s which gives the state of affairs the best chance of success), and modify the relevant principle from “non-ideal ought implies non-ideal accessibility” to “non-ideal ought implies accessibility greater than contextually-defined threshold z”.

  23. Åqvist (1991 219) discusses moral oughts indexed to different times, which is one way of their being ideal to differing degrees (as time passes, the space of possibilities narrows).

References

  • Åqvist L (1991) Review essay: doing the best we can. Philos Phenomenol Res 51:215–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan G, Southwood N (2007) Feasibility in Action and Attitude. In: Rønnow-Rasmussen T, Petersson, B, Josefsson J (eds) Hommage à Wlodek. Philosophical papers dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz. Online at www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek

  • Buchanan A (2004) Justice, legitimacy, and self-determination. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen G (2001) Why not socialism? In: Broadbent E (ed) Democratic equality. What went wrong? University of Toronto Press, Toronto, pp 58–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen G (2009) Why not socialism? Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins S. (2012) Collectives’ duties and collectivisation duties. Australas J Philos

  • Cordes-de Waal J (1996) Intention and the omission bias: omissions perceived as nondecisions. Acta Psychol 93:161–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea. Touchstone, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Estlund D (2011) Human nature and the limits (If any) of political philosophy. Philos Publ Aff 39:207–237

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eysenck HJ, Eysenck S (1975) Manual of the Eysenck personality questionnaire. Hodder & Stoughton, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman F (1986) Doing the best we can. D. Reidel Pub. Co., Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilabert P (2012) Feasibility and socialism. J Polit Philos

  • Gilabert P, Lawford-Smith H (2012) Political feasibility: a conceptual exploration. Polit Stud [early view]

  • Goldman H (1976) Dated rightness and moral imperfection. Philos Rev 85:449–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman H (2010) Subjective rightness. Soc Philos Policy 27:64–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin R (2009) Demandingness as a virtue. J Ethics 13:1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham P (2011) ‘Ought’ and ability. Philos Rev 120:337–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorn G (1991) Plausible worlds. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton R (2009) Willing, wanting, waiting. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1985) On the semantics and logic of obligation. Mind 94:177–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F, Pargetter R (1986) Oughts, options, and actualism. Philos Rev XCV:233–255

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce J (2009) The foundations of causal decision theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawford-Smith H (2010) Ideal theory: a reply to Valentini. J Polit Philos 18:357–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawford-Smith H (2012a) The feasibility of collectives’ action. Australas J Philos 90(3):453–467

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawford-Smith H (2012b) Understanding political feasibility. J Polit Philos

  • Levi I (1989) Rationality, prediction, and autonomous choice. Can J Philos 19:339–363

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1976) Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philos Rev 85:297–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (2000) Semantic analyses for dyadic deontic logic. Papers in ethics and social philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 5–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Louise J (2009) I won’t do it! Self-prediction, moral obligation and moral deliberation. Philos Stud 146:327–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinowicz W (2002) Does practical deliberation crowd out self-prediction? Erkenntnis 57:91–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Räikkä J (1998) The feasibility condition in political theory. J Polit Philos 6:27–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robeyns I, Swift A (eds) (2008) Social justice: ideal theory, nonideal circumstances: special issue. Social Theory and Practice 34

  • Schwarz W (2003) The plastic plan. Wo’s weblog. http://www.umsu.de/wo/2003/104#c1758 Accessed 16th January 2012

  • Simmons J (2010) Ideal and non-ideal theory. Philos Publ Aff 38:5–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel H (1976) Utilitarianism and past and future mistakes. Noûs 10:195–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn W (1977) Where Luce and Krantz do really generalize savage’s decision model. Erkenntnis 11:113–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vranas P (2007) I ought therefore I can. Philos Stud 136:167–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams J, Robert G (2011) Counterfactual triviality: a Lewis-impossibility argument for counterfactuals

Download references

Acknowledgments

A version of this paper, then titled “Agent-Relative Feasibility and Weakness of Will”, was presented at the workshop “Feasibility and Political Theory” at Jesus College, Oxford, March 15–16, 2011. I am grateful to my respondent John Filling for his commentary. I would like to thank Geoff Brennan, Bob Goodin, Nicholas Southwood, and audiences at the Australian National University, the University of Oxford, and Århus University for comments and suggestions on that paper; and Stephanie Collins, Wolfgang Schwarz, Daniel Stoljar, Christian Barry, Nicholas Southwood, Al Hájek, the audience at the University of Sheffield, and two anonymous reviewers, for useful discussion on the present version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Holly Lawford-Smith.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lawford-Smith, H. Non-Ideal Accessibility. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 16, 653–669 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-012-9384-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-012-9384-1

Keywords

Navigation