Skip to main content
Log in

Content, design, and representation in chemistry

  • Published:
Foundations of Chemistry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to engage with the interplay between representational content and design in chemistry and to explore some of its epistemological consequences. Constraints on representational content arising from the aspectual structure of representation can be manipulated by design. Designs are epistemologically important because representational content, hence our knowledge of target systems in chemistry, can change with design. The significance of this claim is that while it has been recognised that the way one conveys information makes a difference to the inferences one can draw from representations in spite of the invariance of informational content, the present paper argues that in chemistry and biochemistry it is often the case that designs have cognitive priority relative to informational content.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I draw here on Lopes (1996, pp. 3–4).

  2. For details of the experimental probing of C60, see for example Curl and Smalley (1988) and Kroto (1988)

  3. By “abstract representation”, I do not mean “abstract direct representation”—a strategy of theory construction Weisberg (2007) contrasts with the “indirect” representation of phenomenon via modelling. The kinds of abstract representations I refer to here are model-based representations.

  4. However, the medium of representation will impact on aspectual structure here.

  5. Nor is Goodman interested in the use of symbols in linguistic pragmatics—the use of symbols in illocutionary acts because these have little to do with “the nominative or predicative aspect of symbols, not their assertive or interrogative force, and [I] have taken characters more as predicates or labels than as sentences” (ibid, pp. 154–155).

  6. See also Woody (2004, p. 781), where she draws in John Haughland’s idea of a “scheme in which a broad set of possible contents can be represented by a corresponding set of representations, themselves governed by unified sets of rules for both generation and application”.

References

  • Carson, M.: Ribbon models of macromolecules. J. Mol. Graph. 5(2), 03–106 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carson, M., Bugg, C.: Algorithm for ribbon models of proteins. J. Mol. Graph. 4(2), 121–122 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H., Fisher, G.: What the ravens really teach us: the intrinsic contextuality of evidence. In: Twining, William, Dawid, Philip, Vasilaki, Dimitra (eds.) Evidence, Inference and Enquiry—Proceedings of the British Academy, vol. 171, pp. 345–370. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, M.L.: Solvent-accessible surfaces of proteins and nucleic acids. Science 221, 709–713 (1983)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G.: Scientific representation, interpretation, and surrogative reasoning. Philos. Sci. 74, 48–68 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curl, R.F., Smalley, R.: Probing C60. Science 242, 1017–1022 (1988)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N.: Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Oxford University Press, London (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, M.: Visual representations in science. Philos. Sci. 76, 372–390 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M.B.: Models and Analogies in Science, 2nd edn. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, R., Laszlo, P.: Representation in chemistry. Angew. Chem. Int. Ed. 30(1), 1–16 (1991)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kermack, W.O., Robinson, R.: An explanation of the property of induced polarity of atoms and an interpretation of the theory of partial valencies on an electronic basis. J. Chem. Soc. 121, 427–440 (1922)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, U.: Experiments, Models, Paper Tools: Cultures of Organic Chemistry in the Nineteenth Century. Stanford University Press, Stanford (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T.: Modelling and representing: an artefactual approach to model-based representation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 42, 262–271 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kroto, H.: Space, stars, C60, and soot. Science 242, 1139–1145 (1988)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J.: Images. Routledge, New York (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D.: Understanding Pictures. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mezey, P.G.: Shape in Chemistry: An Introduction to Molecular Shape and Topology. Wiley, Hoboken (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, A.S., Spackman, M.A.: Molecular surfaces from the promolecule: a comparison with Hartree–Fock ab initio electron density surfaces. J. Comput. Chem. 21(11), 933–942 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morffew, A.J.: Editorial. J. Mol. Graph. 1(1), 3–4 (1983)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nye, M.J.: From Chemical Philosophy to Theoretical Chemistry—Dynamics of Matter and Dynamic of Disciplines, 1800–1950. University of California Press, Berkeley (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  • Perini, L.: Truth in pictures. Philos. Sci. 72, 262–285 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, J.S.: Early Ribbon Drawings of Proteins. Nat. Struct. Biol. 7(8), 624–625 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, J.S., Richardson, D.C.: Doing molecular biophysics: finding, naming, and picturing signal within complexity. Annu. Rev. Biophys. 42, 1–28 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schummer, J.: Aesthetics of chemical products: materials, molecules, and molecular models. Hyle 9(1), 77–108 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  • Teschner, M., Henn, C., Vollhardt, H., Reiling, S., Brickmann, J.: Texture mapping: a new tool for molecular graphics. J. Mol. Graph. 12, 98–105 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M.: Representing with imaginary models: formats matter. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 42, 287–295 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vorms, M.: Formats of representation in scientific theorizing. In: Humphreys, P., Imbert, C. (eds.) Models, Simulations, and Representations, pp. 250–273. Routledge, New York (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M.: Who is a modeler? Br. J. Philos. Sci. 58, 207–233 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woody, A.I.: Putting quantum mechanics to work in chemistry: the power of diagrammatic representation. Philos. Sci. 67(Proceedings), S612–S627 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woody, A.I.: More telltale signs: what attention to representation reveals about scientific explanation. Philos. Sci. 71, 780–793 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thanks the participants of the 20th Annual Symposium of the International Society for the Philosophy of Chemistry at Florida Atlantic University for their questions and comments, especially Ann-Sophie Barwich and Tami Spector.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Grant Fisher.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fisher, G. Content, design, and representation in chemistry. Found Chem 19, 17–28 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-017-9275-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10698-017-9275-6

Keywords

Navigation