Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Evidence for personalised medicine: mechanisms, correlation, and new kinds of black box

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Personalised medicine (PM) has been discussed as a medical paradigm shift that will improve health while reducing inefficiency and waste. At the same time, it raises new practical, regulatory, and ethical challenges. In this paper, we examine PM strategies epistemologically in order to develop capacities to address these challenges, focusing on a recently proposed strategy for developing patient-specific models from induced pluripotent stem cells (iPSCs) so as to make individualised treatment predictions. We compare this strategy to two main PM strategies—stratified medicine and computational models. Drawing on epistemological work in the philosophy of medicine, we explain why these two methods, while powerful, are neither truly personalised nor, epistemologically speaking, novel strategies. Both are forms of correlational black box. We then argue that the iPSC models would count as a new kind of black box. They would not rely entirely on mechanistic knowledge, and they would utilise correlational evidence in a different way from other strategies—a way that would enable personalised predictions. In arguing that the iPSC models would present a novel method of gaining evidence for clinical practice, we provide an epistemic analysis that can help to inform the practical, regulatory, and ethical challenges of developing an iPSC system.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Personalised medicine also includes the production of personalised medical devices and implants, as well as, potentially, patient-specific 3D-bioprinted tissues or organs. For overviews of recent developments, see, e.g., [1, 2]. This paper focuses on pharmacological treatments.

  2. Despite variations in terminology—with PM also discussed in relation to aims of prediction and prevention, for example [3, 4]—there is some agreement that the personalisation of treatment drawing on such data is the most fundamental aspect of PM [5,6,7].

  3. In the United States, precision medicine is the usual term [5, p. 24].

  4. The same principle underpins new methods of online advertising, in which companies aggregate apparently inconsequential data to generate sophisticated ‘virtual identities’ with surprising predictive power [16].

  5. While some of the epilepsies are known to have a genetic component, some involve a large number of genes and proteins, seemingly not in isolation, which would also make it difficult to develop a way to stratify patients by omics data.

  6. This is not to say that mechanistic evidence plays no role in producing such knowledge. The two kinds of evidence work together in various ways: mechanistic evidence can guide judgments about what instances of correlation may be causative and help establish the direction of causation; correlation can aid in sorting out causal links where masking or counteracting causal factors problematise developing mechanistic understanding [30, 31]. Reasoning about mechanisms plays a role in the choice of which connections to test for in correlational studies, as well as in their design and interpretation [32] and in the definition of interventions [33]. Both play roles in theory development and in answering practical clinical questions [34].

  7. Most discussions focus on applying the results of correlational studies to groups other than the experimental group, rather than to particular individuals (the problem of external validity). However, the issue of applying these results to individuals is similar enough that many of the points made in the literature obtain.

  8. While stratified medicine treatments rely in this justificatory way on correlational evidence, it is worth noting that both kinds of evidence may be involved in their development. On the one hand, the approach has been spurred on by observations within trials where a drug has been found to have little to no benefit on average but significant benefit for some individuals. Researchers could then search for a shared feature of these individuals or their conditions. An example is panitumumab (Vectibix), a treatment for metastatic colorectal cancer, which was found to increase survival by two years for patients whose cancer has no mutations in the codon 12 and 13 of the KRAS gene, but by only a few weeks for metastatic colorectal cancer patients overall [47, p. 17]. On the other hand, reasoning about mechanisms can suggest treatment strategies that will work for some patients. For instance, ivacaftor (Kalydeco), a treatment for cystic fibrosis patients with a G551D mutation on their CFTR gene (one among many mutations that can cause cystic fibrosis), was developed from a primarily pathophysiological rationale before being trialled [48].

  9. Some have also proposed model development drawing on theoretical knowledge, but this possibility is much further away, if it is indeed a possibility at all [49]. Our characterisation might be disputed if advanced simulation techniques are thought to constitute a new epistemic method [50, 51]; for a reply, see [52]. We leave this issue aside as we nonetheless consider the method to have the characteristics of a black box.

  10. The amount of argument made for this observation in the literature may make this point appear more controversial than, we think, it can plausibly be taken to be. It has occurred, in part, because the idea is at odds with the way that models—particularly, models as theories or parts of theories—have been discussed in relation to new mechanist approaches. On this view, models are regarded as explanations of mechanisms, and mechanistic explanations should aim at completeness and specificity [56]. In addition, the tendency to focus on explanatory rather than predictive models, and on basic rather than applied sciences, tends to imply the view that abstraction and idealisation are limitations for models to overcome, particularly when combined with traditional assumptions about the relation between prediction and explanation [54, 57, 58]. While our main concern in this paper is to develop an understanding of a potential method in PM, we welcome the opportunity to provide a counter to these foci.

  11. Models of this kind are dubbed ‘phenomenal models’ by Craver [55, p. 841]. A similar notion is discussed by Weisberg as models that aim for a ‘MAXOUT’ ideal [53, p. 109].

  12. These procedures would not occur for every patient, but rather would be part of working out how to define the process of making and using the model, from collection of the sample to interpretation of the results. The same clearly defined procedure would then be used for each patient.

  13. We note that this is consistent with the experience of one of the authors who is a practicing scientist. Eric Winsberg makes a similar point in relation to simulations [51].

  14. Thank you to two anonymous reviewers for pushing us to clarify this point.

References

  1. Mok, Sze-Wing, Razmara Nizak, Sai-Chuen Fua, Ki-Wai Kevin Ho, Ling Qin, Daniël B.F. Saris, Kai-Ming Chan, and Jos Malda. 2016. From the printer: Potential of three-dimensional printing for orthopaedic applications. Journal of Orthopaedic Translation 6: 42–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Wallace, Gordon G., Rhys Cornock, Cathal D. O’Connell, Stephen Beirne, Susan Dodds, and Frederic Gilbert. 2014. 3D bioprinting: Printing parts for bodies. Wollongong: ARC Centre of Excellence for Electromaterials Science.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Abettan, Camille. 2016. Between hype and hope: What is really at stake with personalized medicine? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 19: 423–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. De Grandis, Giovanni, and Vidar Halgunset. 2016. Conceptual and terminological confusion around personalised medicine: A coping strategy. BMC Medical Ethics 17: 43. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12910-016-0122-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Juengst, Eric, Michell L. McGowan, Jennider R. Fishman, and Richard A. Settersten. 2016. From “personalized” to “precision” medicine. Hasting Center Report 46(5): 21–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Schleidgren, Sebastian, Corinna Klingler, Teresa Bertram, Wolf H. Rogowski, and Georg Marckmann. 2013. What is personalized medicine: Sharpening a vague term based on a systematic literature review. BMC Medical Ethics 14: 55. https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-14-55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Parens, Erik. 2015. Drifting away from informed consent in the era of personalized medicine. Hastings Center Report 45(4): 16–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Boenink, Marianne. 2016. Disease in the era of genomic and molecular medicine. In Bloomsbury companion to contemporary philosophy of medicine, ed. James A. Marcum, 65–92. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Wang, Rui-Sheng, Bradley A. Maron, and Joseph Loscalzo. 2015. Systems medicine: Evolution of systems biology from bench to bedside. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Systems Biology and Medicine 7: 141–161.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Vogt, Henrik, Bjørn Hofmann, and Linn Getz. 2016. Personalized medicine: Evidence of normativity in its quantitative definition of health. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 37: 401–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Personalized Medicine Coalition. 2016. Personalized medicine at FDA: 2016 progress report. http://www.personalizedmedicinecoalition.org/Userfiles/PMC-Corporate/file/PM-at-FDA.pdf. Accessed December 10, 2018.

  12. Gamma, Alex. 2013. The role of genetic information in personalized medicine. Perspectives on Biology and Medicine 56: 485–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Horgan, Denis. 2016. European challenges and the way forward. European Alliance for Personalised Medicine. http://www.ema.europa.eu/docs/en_GB/document_library/Presentation/2017/01/WC500219275.pdf. Accessed December 10, 2018.

  14. O’Malley, Maureen A., and John Dupré. 2005. Fundamental issues in systems biology. BioEssays 27: 1270–1276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Price, W.Nicholson. 2015. Black-box medicine. Harvard Journal of Law and Technology 28: 419–467.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Henschke, Adam. 2017. Ethics in an age of surveillance: Personal information and virtual identities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  17. Hood, Leroy, Rudi Balling, and Charles Auffray. 2012. Revolutionizing medicine in the 21st century through systems approaches. Biotechnology Journal 7: 992–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Fatehullah, Aliya, Si Hui Tan, and Nick Barker. 2016. Organoids as an in vitro model of human development and disease. Nature Cell Biology 18: 246–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Du, Xixi, and Jack M. Parent. 2015. Using patient-derived induced pluripotent stem cells to model and treat epilepsies. Current Neurology and Neuroscience Reports 15: 71. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11910-015-0588-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Crook, Jeremy M., Gordon Wallace, and Eva Tomaskovic-Crook. 2015. The potential of induced pluripotent stem cells in models of neurological disorders: Implications on future therapy. Expert Review of Neurotherapeutics 15: 295–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Bourke, Justin L., Anita F. Quigley, Serena Duchi, Cathal D. O’Connell, Jeremy M. Crook, Gordon G. Wallace, Mark J. Cook, and Robert M.I. Kapsa. 2018. Three-dimensional neural cultures produce networks that mimic native brain activity. Journal of Tissue Engineering and Regenerative Medicine 12: 490–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Lancaster, Madeline A., and Juergen A. Knoblich. 2014. Organogenesis in a dish: Modeling development and disease using organoid technologies. Science 345: 1247125. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1247125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Luni, Camilla, Elena Serena, and Nicola Elvassore. 2014. Human-on-chip for therapy development and fundamental science. Current Opinion in Biotechnology 25: 45–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Jeong, Sehoon, Sunja Kim, John Buonocore, C. Jaewon Park, Jane Welsh, Jianrong Li, and Arum Han. 2018. A three-dimensional arrayed microfluidic blood–brain barrier model with integrated electrical sensor array. IEEE Transactions on Biomedical Engineering 65: 431–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Loughlin, Michael, Robyn Bluhm, and Mona Gupta. 2016. Research problems and methods in the philosophy of medicine. In Bloomsbury companion to contemporary philosophy of medicine, ed. James A. Marcum, 29–62. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Andersen, Holly. 2012. Mechanisms: What are they evidence for in evidence-based medicine? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 18: 992–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Howick, Jeremy. 2011. Exposing the vanities—and a qualified defence—of mechanistic reasoning in health care decision making. Philosophy of Science 78: 926–940.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Howick, Jeremy, Paul Glasziou, and Jeffrey K. Aronson. 2010. Evidence-based mechanistic reasoning. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 103: 433–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Ashcroft, R.E. 2004. Current epistemological problems in evidence based medicine. Journal of Medical Ethics 30: 131–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Clarke, Brendan, Donald Gillies, Phyllis Illari, Federica Russo, and Jon Williamson. 2014. Mechanisms and the evidence hierarchy. Topoi 33: 339–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Bluhm, Robyn. 2005. From hierarchy to network: A richer view of evidence for evidence-based medicine. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 48: 535–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Dragulinescu, Stefan. 2016. Inference to the best explanation and mechanisms in medicine. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 37: 211–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Walker, Mary Jean. 2018. Patient-specific devices and population-level evidence: Evaluating therapeutic interventions with inherent variation. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 21: 335–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Hey, Spencer Phillips. 2015. What theories are tested in clinical trials? Philosophy of Science 82: 1318–1329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Hutchison, Katrina J., and Wendy A. Rogers. 2012. Challenging the epistemological foundations of EBM: What kind of knowledge does clinical practice require? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 18: 984–991.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Howick, Jeremy, Paul Glasziou, and Jeffrey K. Aronson. 2013. Problems with using mechanisms to solve the problem of extrapolation. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 34: 275–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Clarke, Brendan, and Federica Russo. 2016. Causation in medicine. In Bloomsbury companion to contemporary philosophy of medicine, ed. James A. Marcum, 297–322. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Guyatt, Gordon H., Jana L. Keller, Roman Jaeschke, David Rosenbloom, Jonathan D. Adachi, and Michael T. Newhouse. 1990. The n-of-1 randomized controlled trial: Clinical usefulness: Our three-year experience. Annals of Internal Medicine 112: 293–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Guyatt, Gordon. 2016. N of 1 randomized trials: A commentary. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 76: 4–5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Mirza, R.D., S. Punja, S. Vohra, and G. Guyatt. 2017. The history and development of N-of-1 trials. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 110: 330–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Henry, Stephen G. 2010. Polanyi’s tacit knowing and the relevance of epistemology to clinical medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16: 292–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Braude, Hillel D. 2016. Clinical reasoning and knowing. In Bloomsbury companion to contemporary philosophy of medicine, ed. James A. Marcum, 323–342. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cartwright, Nancy, and Jeremy Hardie. 2012. Evidence-based policy: A practical guide to doing it better. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  44. Evidence-Based Medicine Working Group. 1992. Evidence-based medicine: A new approach to teaching the practice of medicine. Journal of the American Medical Association 268: 2420–2425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Howick, Jeremy, Paul Glasziou, and Jeffrey K. Aronson. 2013. Can understanding mechanisms solve the problem of extrapolating from study to target populations (the problem of ‘external validity’)? Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine 106: 81–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Nicholls, S.G., B.J. Wilson, D. Castle, H. Etchegary, and J.C. Carroll. 2014. Personalized medicine and genome-based treatments: Why personalized medicine ≠ individualized treatments. Clinical Ethics 9: 135–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Fleck, Leonard M. 2010. Personalized medicine’s ragged edge. Hastings Center Report 40(5): 16–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Kapoor, Harit, Astha Koolwal, and Ankur Singh. 2014. Ivacaftor: A novel mutation modulating drug. Journal of Clinical and Diagnostic Research 8: SE01–SE05.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Wolkenhauer, Olaf. 2014. Why model? Frontiers in Physiology 5: 21. https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2014.00021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Winsberg, Eric. 1999. Sanctioning models: The epistemology of simulation. Science in Context 12: 275–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Winsberg, Eric. 2001. Simulations, models, and theories: Complex physical systems and their representations. Philosophy of Science 68: S442–S454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Frigg, Roman, and Julian Reiss. 2009. The philosophy of simulation: Hot new issues or same old stew? Synthese 169: 593–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Weisberg, Michael. 2013. Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  54. Love, Alan C., and Marco J. Nathan. 2015. The idealization of causation in mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science 82: 761–774.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Craver, Carl F. 2010. Prosthetic models. Philosophy of Science 77: 840–851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Levy, Arnon, and William Bechtel. 2013. Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 80: 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Douglas, Heather. 2004. Prediction, explanation, and dioxin biochemistry: Science in public policy. Foundations of Chemistry 6: 49–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Ramsey, Jeffry L. 2007. Calibrating and constructing models of protein folding. Synthese 155: 307–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  60. Jebeile, Julie, and Anouk Barberousse. 2016. Empirical agreement in model validation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 56: 168–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Nagel, Kai, and Michael Schreckenberg. 1992. A cellular automaton model for freeway traffic. Journal de Physique I 2: 2221–2229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Chanson, Hubert. 2004. The hydraulics of open channel flow. 2nd ed. London: Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ettema, R., R. Arndt, P. Roberts, and T. Wahl. 2000. Hydraulic modeling: Concepts and practice. Reston, VA: American Society of Civil Engineers.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Cartwright, Nancy. 1994. Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  65. Baird, Davis. 2004. Thing knowledge: A philosophy of scientific instruments. Oakland: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Vergouwe, Yvonne. 2003. Validation of clinical prediction models: Theory and applications in testicular germ cell cancer. Rotterdam: Erasmus University.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Debray, Thomas P.A., Yvonne Vergouwe, Hendrik Koffijberg, Daan Nieboer, Ewout W. Steyerberg, and Karel G.M. Moons. 2015. A new framework to enhance the interpretation of external validation studies of clinical prediction models. Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 68: 279–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Christopher, Hitchcock, and Elliott Sober. 2004. Prediction versus accommodation and the risk of overfitting. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was supported by Australian Research Council (Grant ID CE140100012). The authors would like to thank colleagues in the Ethics, Policy and Public Engagement theme at the Centre of Excellence for Electromaterials Science (ACES) for their comments on drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mary Jean Walker.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Walker, M.J., Bourke, J. & Hutchison, K. Evidence for personalised medicine: mechanisms, correlation, and new kinds of black box. Theor Med Bioeth 40, 103–121 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-019-09482-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-019-09482-z

Keywords

Navigation