Skip to main content
Log in

The dispositional architecture of epistemic reasons

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Epistemic reasons are meant to provide justification for beliefs. In this paper, I will be concerned with the requirements that have to be met if reasons are to discharge this function. It is widely recognized, however, that only possessed reasons can justify beliefs and actions. But what are the conditions that have to be satisfied in order for one to possess reasons? I shall begin by motivating a particular condition, namely, the ‘treating’ requirement that has been deemed to be necessary for possessing reasons. In Sect. 1, I explain and criticize some of the existing accounts of the treating requirement for reason-possession. In Sect. 2, I will suggest a dispositional account of reason-possession in which the treating condition features prominently. Section 3 will deal with the some of the consequences of this account for such issues as the structure of epistemic defeat, the immediacy of perceptual justification and logical knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Broome (2007).

  2. See, for example, Schroeder (2011) for an account in terms of ‘presentational mental states’ which include beliefs and experiences.

  3. See, for example, Scanlon (1998), Schlosser (2012) and Sylvan (2015).

  4. Parfit (2001, p.118).

  5. Sylvan (2015).

  6. Ibid.

  7. Sylvan (2015, 2016) and Sylvan and Sosa (Forthcoming).

  8. I have said that we do not, for our current purposes, need to identify what sort of attitude the treating states involve. This raises the question of how to explain the dispositions they ground. So far, I have relied on our intuitions in cases where being in a treating state makes a difference to whether a subject possesses a particular reason. Shortly I shall present some methodological remarks that are meant to address this question. The idea is that an illuminating explanation of such dispositions need not involve a non-circular analysis of their nature. Rather, a more realistic model of philosophical analysis is one that involves the elucidations of concepts rather than their reductive dismantling. Thanks to anonymous referee of this journal for asking me to signpost this issue.

  9. An anonymous referee correctly points out that, as it stands, (T) might have some puzzling implications in so far as it helps itself to the notion of ‘disposition to possess a reason’. The thought is that one can have a disposition to possess a reason as a reason to believe p without in fact yet possessing that reason as a reason to believe p. I agree. It is quite possible that there are weak-willed people who have strong reasons for holding a belief and yet fail to be motivated by them. So a weaker version of (T) that recognizes this fact would be more plausible. This is actually the motivation behind Sylvan’s appeal (2015) to the notion of “being attracted to treat R like an objective reason” in his account (C). The referee suggests ‘dispositional possession’ as a more accurate description of what (T) entails. However, while acknowledging this point, for ease of expression (too many occurrences of ‘disposition’ in one sentence), I am going to leave (T) as it is though admonishing the reader to bear this point in mind.

  10. It is important to distinguish between the ground of a disposition and the disposition itself as when we say, for example, that salt’s disposition to dissolve is grounded in its molecular structure. Likewise, being in a treating state, with respect to a reason R and a proposition p, grounds the subject’s disposition to possess R as evidence or reason to believe that p. It is the treating state, not the disposition it grounds, that reflects the fact that the subject appreciates the force of his reason. So my account is not vulnerable to the objection that was raised against Sylvan’s proposal.

  11. Since the manifestation of a disposition involves a process running from a stimulus to a response, it is always possible that the response comes about without that particular disposition being manifested (this is generally known as the problem of the deviant causal chains). Thus, a subject might be in two treating states with respect to a reason (R) and two distinct propositions p and q. When she is exposed to R, she comes, by (T), to possess R as evidence or reason. But which proposition R is reason for depends on which disposition it is that is manifested. She would possess R as reason for believing that p, rather than q, if her possession of R is the manifestation of the disposition that is grounded in the treating state involving R and p (rather than q).

  12. Here I am indebted to an anonymous referee of this journal for both urging me to address the circularity issue as well as suggesting the distinction between metaphysical and conceptual circularity in order to clarify my position.

  13. Elsewhere (Vahid 2016), I have argued for a dispositional account of how the two notions of propositional and doxastic justification are related to one another. I have shown how the extant theories describing the relationship between these two notions turn out to correspond closely to the way in which the theories about the semantic analysis of dispositional sentences have been introduced in the dispositions debate in metaphysics.

  14. Strawson (1995, p. 16).

  15. Schiffer (1972, p. 15).

  16. Strawson (1992, p. 19).

  17. Williamson (2000, p. 179).

  18. See, for example, Pryor (2000) and Huemer (2001).

  19. See, for example, Pryor (2000), Huemer (2001) and Tucker (2010).

  20. Bengson (2015, p. 738).

  21. See, for example, Conee (2013) and Tooley (2013).

  22. Pryor (2000) and Bengson (2015).

  23. Huemer (2001).

  24. Pollock (1995, p. 41, my emphasis).

  25. Sturgeon (2014, p. 117).

  26. Martin (1994).

  27. Lewis (1997).

  28. See Johnston (1992) and Bird (1998).

  29. See, for example, Cohen (2010) and Wedgewood (2013).

  30. Balcerak Jackson (2016).

  31. Boghossian (2003).

  32. Williamson (2003).

References

  • Balcerak Jackson, M. (2016). Perceptual fundamentalism and a priori bootstrapping. Philosophical Studies, 173(8), 2087–2103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2015). The intellectual given. Mind, 124(495), 707–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (1998). Dispositions and antidotes. Philosophical Quarterly, 48, 227–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2003). Blind reasoning. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 77(1), 225–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2007). Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4(3), 349–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2010). Bootstrapping, defeasible reasoning, and a priori justification. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 141–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E. (2013). Seeming evidence. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and justification: New essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2001). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1997). Finkish dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 143–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (1994). Dispositions and conditionals. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2001). On what matters. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1995). Cognitive carpentry. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34, 517–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1972). Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, M. (2012). Taking something as a reason for action. Philosophical Papers, 41(2), 267–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2011). What does it take to “have” a reason? In A. Reisner & A. Steglich-Petersen (Eds.), Reasons for belief (pp. 201–222). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1992). Analysis and metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1995). My philosophy. In P. Sen & R. Verma (Eds.), The philosophy of P.F. Strawson. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, S. (2014). Pollock on defeasible reasons. Philosophical Studies, 169, 105–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, K. (2015). What apparent reasons appear to be. Philosophical Studies, 172(3), 587–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, K. (2016). Epistemic reasons I. Philosophy Compass, 11, 364–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, K., & Sosa, E. (Forthcoming). The place of reasons in epistemology. In D. Star (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of reasons and normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Tooley, M. (2013). Michael huemer and the principle of phenomenal conservatism. In C. Tucker (Ed.), Seemings and justification: New essays on dogmatism and phenomenal conservatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, C. (2010). Why open-minded people should endorse dogmatism. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 529–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vahid, H. (2016). A dispositional analysis of propositional and doxastic justification. Philosophical Studies, 173, 3133–3152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgewood, R. (2013). A priori bootstrapping. In A. Casullo & J. Thurow (Eds.), The a priori in philosophy (pp. 226–246). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2003). Blind reasoning. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 77(1), 249–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank an anonymous referee of this journal for extremely helpful comments. Thanks also to Ruth Chang, Robert Audi, Muhammad Legenhausen and Tim Williamson for valuable comments and feedback on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hamid Vahid.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vahid, H. The dispositional architecture of epistemic reasons. Philos Stud 176, 1887–1904 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1102-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1102-y

Keywords

Navigation