Skip to main content
Log in

The way things go: moral relativism and suspension of judgment

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A popular accusation against moral relativism is that it goes too far in its vindication of tolerance. The idea behind accusations like this can be summarized in the slogan, frequently attributed to relativism, that “anything goes”. The aim of this paper is to defend moral relativism from the accusation that it is an “anything goes” view; from the accusation that it forces us to suspend our judgment in cases in which we do not think we should even be allowed to. In the end, relativism is not an “anything goes” view because it is not a view about what goes, but about the way things go—about what goes on when we say that something is morally right or wrong. There is indeed a view, sometimes called “relativism”, that forces us to suspend our judgment about practices that do not allow for such comfort, but it is not so much moral relativism as moral contextualism. Apparently, though, the most salient alternative to “anything goes” views such as contextualism is not moral relativism. It is moral objectivism, according to which there is a fact of the matter about moral issues. However, I show that moral objectivism too ends up being an “anything goes” view unless the objectivist takes herself to be endowed with “God’s point of view”, which I prove troublesome.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Two examples of this kind of view that will be mentioned throughout this paper are Harman’s (1975/2013) and Dreier’s (1990), both presented as varieties of relativism by their proponents.

  2. I would also be comfortable with saying, as Brandom (1994, 2000) does, that a proposition is just whatever can serve as a premise or conclusion in an argument, whether it tells us something about how the world is or not.

  3. As we will see, there are other standards, besides Alice’s and Beth’s, that Alice could take into account when assessing Beth’s claim. This is why, if the views are characterized in this way, there are at least three options as to how Alice should answer to the question whether Beth has said something true.

  4. I intend this characterization to be neutral as to whether contextualism is better understood as an indexical or nonindexical view (see, for instance, MacFarlane, 2009 for the distinction). These are two different ways in which the idea that the truth of moral claims is relative to moral standards can be implemented. On the one hand, we can say that the content of a moral claim includes a moral standard, so that the same moral claim can vary in truth-value depending on the occasion, for it has a different content each time. This is what an indexical contextualist would say. On the other hand, we can say that the content of a moral claim is always the same, but whether this content is true or false depends on the occasion; in this case, too, the same moral claim can be true under some circumstances and false under others. This is the option pursued by nonindexical contextualism. Everything I say about contextualism in this paper is intended to apply to both versions of contextualism.

  5. Applying MacFarlane’s relativism to moral claims supposes extending his theory beyond the cases for which it is intended. MacFarlane does not develop nor argue for moral relativism—he does propose to use relativism to explain the behavior of claims featuring “ought” (Kolodny & MacFarlane, 2010; MacFarlane, 2014: chapter 11), but this is a prudential, rather than a moral, “ought”. Still, I think moral relativism too is best characterized in terms of the context of assessment.

  6. In the first case, we would be talking about indexical contextualism; in the second case, about nonindexical contextualism (see n. 4 for the distinction).

  7. Thanks to María José Frápolli for suggesting this objection to me. For a similar objection, see Baghramian & Coliva (2020: 83–84).

  8. In fact, we will see in Sect. 5 that there are versions of objectivism that do not make Alice intolerant, but have other problems. Let us keep things simple for now, though.

  9. It has been discussed whether there is such a thing as faultless disagreement. Some authors, such as Stojanovic (2007) or Iacona (2008), have argued that, as long as there is no fault in the exchange, it cannot count as a disagreement. Here, however, I will leave this discussion aside and assume that it makes sense to talk about faultless disagreement, and that it is something we should expect a theory to account for.

  10. Baghramian & Coliva (2020: 228) call views that are only committed to (i) “weak” forms of relativism, and views that are committed to both (i) and (ii) “strong” forms of relativism.

  11. Boghossian, Baghramian, and Williamson characterize relativism as committed to Equal Validity in the context of their criticizing epistemic relativism, but they arguably intend their characterization to apply to moral relativism as well.

  12. This is reminiscent of Moore’s “What’s at issue?” problem (Moore, 1903/1993: Sect. 11; see also Gibbard, 2003: 23–29).

  13. Thanks to David Bordonaba for making me aware of the importance of emphasizing this.

  14. See Herbert (2001: 25–28) for a collection of some further examples that show that relativism is not committed to Equal Validity.

  15. The kind of argument that Dreier (2005: 253–257) offers for his view, which resembles the argument for relativism advanced in this paper, may drive us to think that he is indeed a relativist, as he claims, and not a contextualist, as I do. However, for Dreier’s argument to work he needs moral standards to be relative to the context of assessment, and not to the context of use, which is the one that plays a role in the characterization he gives of his view (Dreier, 2005: 251–252). Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for Philosophical Studies for suggesting me to take Dreier’s argument into consideration.

References

  • Baghramian, M. (2019). The virtues of relativism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 93, 247–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baghramian, M., & Coliva, A. (2020). Relativism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B., & Bloor, D. (1982). Relativism, rationalism and the sociology of knowledge. In M. Hollis & S. Lukes (Eds.), Rationality and relativism (pp. 21–47). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2006). Fear of knowledge: Against relativism and constructivism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlow, N. (2014). The problem with the Frege-Geach problem. Philosophical Studies, 167(3), 635–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (1990). Internalism and speaker relativism. Ethics, 101(1), 6–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (2005). Moral relativism and moral nihilism. In D. Copp (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theory (pp. 240–264). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1999). Conquest of abundance. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2009). Epistemology without metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 143(2), 249–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2018). Epistemology from an evaluativist perspective. Philosophers’ Imprint, 18(2).

  • Frápolli, M. J. (Ed.). (2019a). Introduction: Expressivisms, knowledge and truth. In Expressivisms, knowledge and truth (pp. 1–9). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J. (Ed.). (2019b). Propositions first: Biting Geach’s bullet. In Expressivisms, knowledge and truth (pp. 87–110). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking how to live. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1975/2013). Moral relativism defended. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Ethical theory: An anthology (pp. 35–43). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Herbert, C. (2001). Victorian relativity: Radical thought and scientific discovery. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hirvonen, S. (2016). Doing without judge dependence. In C. Meier & J. van Wijnberger-Huitink (Eds.), Subjective meaning: Alternatives to relativism (pp. 47–68). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Iacona, A. (2008). Faultless or disagreement. In M. García-Carpintero & M. Kölbel (Eds.), Relative truth (pp. 287–295). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (2002). Truth without objectivity. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kölbel, M. (2004). Faultless disagreement. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104(1), 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N., & MacFarlane, J. (2010). Ifs and oughts. Journal of Philosophy, 107(3), 115–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M. (2019). Relativist stances, virtues and vices: A comment on Maria Baghramian’s paper. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 93, 271–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2009). Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese, 166(2), 231–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903/1993). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Pérez-Navarro, E. (2021). No matter who: What makes one a relativist? Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 36(2), 231–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2007). The emotional construction of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (1986). The elements of moral philosophy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2007). Perspectival thought: A plea for (moderate) relativism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stace, W. T. (1937). The concept of morals. New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stojanovic, I. (2007). Talking about taste: Disagreement, implicit arguments, and relative truth. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30(6), 691–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2015). Tetralogue: I’m right, you’re wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (2006). Intuitionism, realism, relativism and rhubarb. In P. Greenough & M. P. Lynch (Eds.), Truth and realism (pp. 38–60). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Manuel Almagro, David Bordonaba, Cristina Corredor, María José Frápolli, Manuel García-Carpintero, Manuel de Pinedo, Huw Price, Esther Romero, Andrés Soria, Neftalí Villanueva, and three anonymous reviewers for Philosophical Studies, as well as audiences at talks in Berkeley, Cluj-Napoca, Donostia, Granada, Salzburg, and Tepic, for their helpful comments and suggestions.

Funding

This paper has been funded by the Spanish Ministry of Education under the grant FPU14/00485, by the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation under the research projects “Contemporary Expressivisms and the Indispensability of Normative Vocabulary: Scope and Limits of the Expressivist Hypothesis” (FFI2016-80088-P) and “Disagreement in Attitudes: Normativity, Affective Polarization and Disagreement” (PID2019-109764RB-I00), by the Regional Government of Andalusia under the research projects “Public Disagreements, Affective Polarization and Immigration in Andalusia” (B-HUM-459-UGR18) and “The Inferential Identification of Propositions: A Reconsideration of Classical Dichotomies in Metaphysics, Semantics and Pragmatics” (P18-FR-2907), and by the University of Granada under a “Contrato Puente” fellowship and the excellence unit FiloLab-UGR (UCE.PPP2017.04).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eduardo Pérez-Navarro.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pérez-Navarro, E. The way things go: moral relativism and suspension of judgment. Philos Stud 179, 49–64 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01650-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01650-z

Keywords

Navigation