Skip to main content
Log in

Biological Essentialism and the Tidal Change of Natural Kinds

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The vision of natural kinds that is most common in the modern philosophy of biology, particularly with respect to the question whether species and other taxa are natural kinds, is based on a revision of the notion by Mill in A System of Logic. However, there was another conception that Whewell had previously captured well, which taxonomists have always employed, of kinds as being types that need not have necessary and sufficient characters and properties, or essences. These competing views employ different approaches to scientific methodologies: Mill’s class-kinds are not formed by induction but by deduction, while Whewell’s type-kinds are inductive. More recently, phylogenetic kinds (clades, or monophyletic-kinds) are inductively projectible, and escape Mill’s strictures. Mill’s version represents a shift in the notions of kinds from the biological to the physical sciences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, non-natural kinds, like pencil can also have essences, as Michael Devitt pointed out to me (see his Devitt 2005).

  2. Which of course is not unchallenged in modern philosophy of language and logic. Kripke and Plantinga, among others (e.g., Parsons 1969), permit individual essences, although Hull (1977) noted that with respect to taxa, this would mean that any object that had the same individual essence would need to be the same object (which is, of course, Leibniz’s principle of the identity of indiscernibles).

  3. Since I hold there never was any kind of taxonomic essentialism in natural history, of course this is an introduction, not a reintroduction. And it is not clear to me that Devitt’s version is taxonomic.

  4. Gordon McOuat (2009) covers much the same territory I do here, although he tends to take a more political view than I do. I believe he is correct that underlying much of this debate is concern over the political implications of these ideas but I think that is ancillary to the point I am making here. McOuat also cautions against being an essentialist about essentialism—we should not presume that historical periods have essential characters either, with which I fully agree; but he sees essentialists where I see merely taxonomists using diagnostic definitions (for example, in his McOuat 1996).

  5. Something Aristotle did not do, in the modern sense of essentialism (Charles 2002). He was not engaged upon any kind of taxonomic project, so far as I can tell, and was neither a Lockean conventionalist, nor a Leibnizian modal essentialist. However, he did in his natural histories sometimes seem to think that science could be done, at least in part, by definition. Where Locke was the clearer of the undergrowth for science, Aristotle is its gardener, tidying up the mess of ordinary knowledge. Charles, in his Chap. 12, has a full discussion, in which he notes that Aristotle’s distinct classes are formed on the basis of his “soul function” theory from De Anima. Aristotle’s kinds are functional kinds, not taxonomic kinds. This is a recurring theme in biological essentialism, right up to Darwin’s distinction between adaptive similarity and affinities.

  6. Locke’s friend John Ray (1686, Tome I, Libr. I, XX: 40) introduced the technical natural history meaning of species in 1686, in his Historia Plantarum Generalis:

    After long and considerable investigation, no surer criterion for determining species has occurred to me than the distinguishing features that perpetuate themselves in propagation from seed. Thus, no matter what variations occur in the individuals or the species, if they spring from the seed of one and the same plant, they are accidental variations and not such as to distinguish a species […] Animals likewise that differ specifically preserve their distinct species permanently […] one species never springs from the seed of another nor vice versa.

    Within a century, this was the consensus meaning of naturalists. It is, for example, Linnaeus’ usage, for Linnaeus never defines what he means by the term species (although Müller-Wille and Orel 2007, make out a good case that he had something in mind based on reproduction).

  7. My edition is the ninth (1875). The quoted text is unchanged from the first to the ninth editions.

  8. It was first published in 1812 under the title “Discours préliminaire” to his Recherches sur les ossemens fossiles de quadrupeds (Cuvier 1812). It was reprinted separately as the Discours sur les révolutions de la surface du globe: et sur les changements qu'elles ont produits dans le règne animal in 1825 and listed as the third edition, and is often referred to as the Règne Animal. It may be this that Whately has read. The English edition (Cuvier 1831, p. 73) gives this translation:

    This inquiry calls for the definition of a species, which may serve as the foundation for the use which is made of the term. A species, then, includes the individuals which descend from one another, or from common parents, and those which resemble them as strongly as they resemble one another. Thus we only call the varieties of a species, those races more or less different, which may have proceeded from them by generation. Our observations on the distinctions between ancestors and descendants are consequently our only rational rule; for every other would enter into hypothesis without proofs. [italics original, p. 125 in the 1825 French edition].

  9. Among the philosophers, however, things were different. Diderot, Maupertuis and others discussed the nascent taxonomic conventions extensively.

  10. I think it was Paul Griffiths.

  11. Mill saw himself in conflict with Whewell for political and moral reasons as well as for logical and methodological reasons (Snyder 2006, Chap. 3).

  12. If the thesis of the historical portion of this paper is correct, that Mill is the founder of essentialistic natural kinds into philosophy, then he may be taken to have uttered the first such conflation.

  13. Dewey is not to be dismissed lightly, however. His treatment of species focused quite correctly on the generative aspects:

    This formal activity which operates throughout a series of changes and holds them to a single course; which subordinates their aimless flux to its own perfect manifestation; which, leaping the boundaries of space and time, keeps individuals distant in space and remote in time to a uniform type of structure and function: this principle seemed to give insight into the very nature of reality itself. To it Aristotle gave the name, είδος. This term the scholastics translated as species.

    Wilkins (2009) argues that generation and morphological similarity were the constituent elements of what I term the Generative Conception of Species, which underlies pretty well all research on biological kinds from the classical era until the turn of the twentieth century and the discovery of genetics. Dewey’s rhetoric is a little over-extended, but is well within that tradition.

  14. The history and reasons for this confusion are given in Wilkins (2009), and by Chung (2003). The originator of the notion that before Darwin, everyone was a “typologist” is, I believe, George G. Simpson (1961, pp. 36–47).

  15. In his discussion of Hamilton’s philosophy, he writes: “We have now attained a theory of Classification, of Class Notions, and of Class Names…” showing that for him, classification was a matter of conceptual kinds (Mill 1889, p. 402). As Snyder (2006, p. 164) observes, Mill had less direct experience of science than Whewell, whose classificatory ideas were formed when he studied mineralogy with Mohs. Oddly, Whewell doesn’t employ the type-kind approach to minerals.

  16. But the “nature” that Socrates is discussing here is social: the cut he is considering is that of delineating what is Justice (dike).

  17. Despite this claim of priority being repeated often, it is unlikely that Venn meant much by this; see his discussion in chapter III, Sect. 3 of the 1876 and later editions. He did not mean by “natural kind” what Mill did. In fact he most probably meant what Whewell or even Cuvier did (see the later editions, III. 6, 17)—kinds formed by descent. In particular I don’t think that he was keying into the debates about artificial and natural classification earlier that century.

  18. Discussed in Wilkins (2009).

  19. In the text he says, “… how erroneous is the idea of assuming any particular organ as the sole source of the Essential Character” and in the note, “It is not to the Essential Character itself, as defined by Fabricius, (Phil. Ent. p. 96) that I object; but to the impossibility of finding such. “Character essentialis optimus facillimus at vix possibilis.” Why then trouble ourselves with hunting after such a chimera?” Clearly this is for diagnosis—Macleay believes diagnostic characters can be found. The term “Essential character” was widely used in botanical works of the time as the diagnostic properties of a genus or order, etc. (vide Lindley 1830).

  20. Linnaeus may have, according to speculation by his biographer Lisbet Koerner (1999, 48f), developed his scheme of short names and simple diagnostic descriptions based on generic and specific characters, in order for his students to name the food plants that cattle were eating, for agricultural research, in his 1749 tract, Pan Svericus.

  21. As McOuat (2003) points out, Bentham (1983) was continuing his uncle’s program of reforming education and politics, and in the process of critiquing Whately he introduced a number of innovations, including quantification.

  22. Some French commentators held that a classification was “natural” if it was agreeable to human cognition (McOuat personal communication). However, the debate over natural classification that began in English via the impact of Locke on systematists, continued with Milne-Edwards (1844) in French, famously influencing Darwin. Most of those taxonomists who used the phrase “natural system” and cognates, meant by it something like the Adansonian view that many characters were to be used.

  23. Other than apparent resemblance; a particularly nice instance of which is John Lindley’s (1830) influential botanical work, in the preface of which he says that the modern botanists are able to “make their classification coincide with natural affinities” (vi), and that “the natural system of Botany” is founded on the principles that “those plants which are most alike should be arranged next to each other”, and that “those which have the smallest mutual resemblance should be placed at the greatest distance”. This is, he writes, “obviously the method of classification pointed out by nature and reason” (v). Any higher taxon (that is, of an arrangement of species, for “Nature herself, … creates species only”, vii), is “called natural, not because it exists in Nature, but because it comprehends species naturally resembling each other more than they resemble anything else” (viii). Lindley is clearly influenced by Adansonian principles in respect of the naturalness of classification (Stafleu 1963; Winsor 2004).

  24. Owen’s (1843, p. 374) definition was “Homologue. The same organ in different animals under every variety of form and function”.

  25. In the History, Whewell (1884, p. 639) ascribes the term homology to the German school (presumably Oken and Goethe), and implies that Owen has merely taken it over into English. The definition Owen gives is in a glossary to the work, so it may be he was using a term that had some currency already, but which most readers would find unfamiliar. I have been unable to find prior uses in English. Geoffroy does use the term “analogy” in French to mean something more like what Owen meant by homology, and the term “homologue” is used to apply to chemical kinds, but nothing biological that I can locate. However, both Whewell and Owen (1848) are right, in that the Germans used the term, particularly Oken (1847) in the Physiophilosophie. I am indebted to Gareth Nelson for assistance with tracking down these uses.

  26. After this time, the topic was generally the domain of librarians, such as Richardson (1901), although Dewey treated it as an instrumental good (Dewey 1920).

  27. Woodger’s (1937) and Gregg’s (1954) set theoretic accounts are exceptions, but influential mostly later on. One person Woodger did affect was Hennig.

  28. There is considerable variation for the wording of this quote. A common variant is “All science is either physics or stamp collecting.” Rutherford should have used the quote given in the text, however.

  29. Another interpretation here is that Rutherford recognized that physics needs to have observed clusters of properties in order to apply to the world, and with this I must agree, but I doubt that was his intent. [Author specific comment deleted].

  30. Or rather, specimens—the raw “data” of a phylogenetic inference are individual specimens. One may take them to be stand-ins for their species, but even in the molecular period, the data sets being analyzed are usually those of single individuals who have been sequenced.

  31. Darwin used the terms “affinity” for sets of homologous characters, and “analogy” for homoplasious characters, directly influenced by the discussions of, among others, Swainson (1835) and Milne-Edwards (1844). See, for instance, Whewell’s discussion in Bk VIII, Chap. II, Sect. 4, in which he notes that mere resemblance is not enough for a natural system; one must also use “natural affinity” (Whewell 1847, vol 1, p. 488). In 1843 Owen defined “homology” (1843), and in 1870 Lankester the term “homoplasy” (1870). A slew of similar terms in molecular systematics have also since been invented, such as paralogy, and orthology, xenology, gametology, and sinology (Fitch 2000; Mindell and Meyer 2001). For a review of the history of homology, see Laubichler (2000).

  32. Alas for philosophy, “Raptors” has now been divided into two disparate clades, the order Falconiformes, which include around 290 species of diurnal birds of prey, and the order Accipitriformes, which include around 225 species, including eagles, hawks and New World vultures (see Hackett et al. 2008). Though this makes the example less pleasing, it in fact strengthens the point, as inductive inferences will now no longer be as projectible between them (just as the group “vultures” ceased to be so projectible when it was discovered that Old World vultures were more closely related to the Accipitridae, eagles and kites, etc., than to New World vultures, which are more closely related to Cathartidae, such as storks).

  33. Hans Reichenbach (1949) proposed a “straight rule” for induction in his The theory of probability, in which induction was justified when increasing observations converged upon an asymptote. See also Salmon (1991).

  34. Hence Elliot Sober’s (1999, 2008) recent proposal for a form of logical inference he calls modus Darwin, in which common ancestry can be inferred from similarity, misrepresents what Darwin and subsequent phylogeneticists actually did when inferring phylogenies. With the notions of “analogy”, and later with “homoplasy”, being clearly understood and used, it has always been known that mere similarity is insufficient to infer common ancestry, or else bats, birds and pteranodons can be assigned to a single group, a point made by, among others, T. H. Huxley. In fine case of historical irony, Huxley’s (1957) grandson Julian tried to hoist a homoplasious group for thinking beings—Psychozoa.

  35. However, I really doubt this will be true—even when traits like legs are lost, as in the case of snakes, the genes that were involved in making legs are not excised, but are silenced or down-regulated. They remain there and are available to sequencing (and what is more, I predict this in the absence of empirical knowledge based on phylogenetic considerations).

References

  • Avise, J. C., & Ball, R. M., Jr. (1990). Principles of genealogical concordance in species concepts and biological taxonomy. In D. Futuyma & J. Atonovics (Eds.), Oxford surveys in evolutionary biology (pp. 45–67). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. F. (2006). Are Emotions Natural Kinds? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1(1), 28–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. F., Lindquist, K. A., Bliss-Moreau, E., Duncan, S., Gendron, M., Mize, J., et al. (2007). Of mice and men: Natural kinds of emotions in the mammalian brain? A response to Panksepp and Izard. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 2(3), 297–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, G. (1827). An outline of a new system of logic. With a critical examination of Dr. Whately’s “Elements of Logic’’. London: Hunt and Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, G. (1832–1836). Labiatarum genera et species: Or, A description of the genera and species of plants of the order Labiatæ; with their general history, characters, affinities, and geographical distribution. London: J. Ridgeway and sons.

  • Bentham, J. (1983). In M. J. Smith & W. H. Burston (Eds.), Chrestomathia. Oxford, New York: Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press.

  • Bentham, G., & Hooker, J. D. (1920). Handbook of the British flora: A description of the flowering plants and ferns indigenous to, or naturalized in, the British Isles. For the use of beginners and amateurs (Revised, 5th ed.). London: L. Reeve & Co. (Original edition, 1858).

  • Blomberg, S. P., & Garland, T. (2002) Tempo and mode in evolution: Phylogenetic inertia, adaptation and comparative methods. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 15, 899–910.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species, new interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–186). Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camardi, G. (2001). Richard Owen, morphology and evolution. Journal of the History of Biology, 34(3), 481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charland, L. C. (2002). The natural kind status of emotion. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53(4), 511–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charles, D. (2002). Aristotle on meaning and essence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chung, C. (2003). On the origin of the typological/population distinction in Ernst Mayr’s changing views of species, 1942–1959. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 34, 277–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuvier, G. (1812). Discours préliminaire. In Recherches sur les ossemens fossiles de quadrupèdes. Paris: Deterville.

  • Cuvier, G. (1825). Discours sur les révolutions de la surface du globe: et sur les changements qu’elles ont produits dans le règne animal (3e ed.). Paris: G. Dufour et E. d’Ocagne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuvier, G. (1831). A discourse on the revolutions of the surface of the globe, and the changes thereby produced in the animal kingdom: Tr. from the French with illustrations and a glossary. Philadelphia: Carey & Lea.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (2007). Species concepts and species delimitation. Systematic Biology, 56(6), 879–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, A. J. (1984). Archetypes and ancestors: Palaeontology in Victorian London, 1850–1875. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, A. J. (1989). The politics of evolution: Morphology, medicine, and reform in radical London, science and its conceptual foundations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2005). Rigid application. Philosophical Studies, 125, 139–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75(3), 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2010). Species have (partly) intrinsic essences. Philosophy of Science, 77(5), 648–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1920). Reconstruction in philosophy. New York: Henry Holt and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1997). The influence of Darwin on philosophy and other essays, Great books in philosophy. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1981). Natural kinds and biological taxa. The Philosophical Review, 90(1), 66–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1999). Kant and the platypus: Essays on language and cognition. London: Vintage/Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farber, P. L. (1976). The type-concept in zoology during the first half of the nineteenth century. Journal of the History of Biology, 9(1), 93–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, W. M. (2000). Homology: A personal view on some of the problems. Trends in Genetics, 16, 227–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Zoology, 23, 536–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1997). Metaphysics and the origin of species. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson. (1954). Fact, fiction and forecast. London: University of London, The Athlone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregg, J. R. (1954). The language of taxonomy: An application of symbolic logic to the study of classificatory systems. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Squaring the circle: Natural kinds with historical essences. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species, new interdisciplinary essays (pp. 209–228). Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (2004). Is emotion a natural kind? In R. C. Solomon (Ed.), Thinking about feeling: Contemporary philosophers on emotions (pp. 233–249). Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hackett, S. J., Kimball, R. T., Reddy, S., Bowie, R. C. K., Braun, E. L., Braun, M. J., et al. (2008). A phylogenomic study of birds reveals their evolutionary history. Science, 320(5884), 1763–1768.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1991). A tradition of natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 109–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hettema, H., & Kuipers, T. A. F. (1988). The periodic table—its formalization, status, and relation to atomic theory. Erkenntnis, 28(3), 387–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1965). The effect of essentialism on taxonomy: Two thousand years of stasis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 15, 314–326, 316, 311–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1976). Are species really individuals? Systematic Zoology, 25, 174–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1977). The ontological status of species as evolutionary units. In R. Butts & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Foundational problems in special sciences (pp. 91–102). Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1979). The limits of cladism. Systematic Zoology, 28, 416–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1982). Exemplars and scientific change. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1982, 479–503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1984). Cladistic theory: Hypotheses that blur and grow. In T. Duncan & T. Stuessy (Eds.), Cladistic perspectives on the reconstruction of evolutionary history (pp. 5–23). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1988). Science as a process: An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1994). Contemporary systematic philosophies. In E. Sober (Ed.), Conceptual issues in evolutionary biology (pp. 295–330). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, J. (1957). New bottles for new wine. London: Chatto and Windus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jevons, W. S. (1878). The principles of science: A treatise on logic and scientific method (2nd ed.). London: Macmillan. (Original edition, 1873).

    Google Scholar 

  • Joseph, H. W. B. (1916). An introduction to logic (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. (Original edition, 1906).

    Google Scholar 

  • Koerner, L. (1999). Linnaeus: Nature and nation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lankester, E. R. (1870). On the use of the term homology in modern zoology, and the distinction between homogenetic and homoplastic agreements. Annals and Magazine of Natural History, 4(6), 34–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaPorte, J. (1996). Chemical kind term reference and the discovery of essence. Nous, 30(1), 112–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laubichler, M. D. (2000). Homology in development and the development of the homology concept. American Zoologist, 40(5), 777–788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1996). New essays on human understanding (P. Remnant & J. Bennett, Trans). Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press. (Original edition, 1765).

  • Levit, G. S., & Meister, K. (2006). The history of essentialism vs. Ernst Mayr’s ‘‘Essentialism Story’’: A case study of German idealistic morphology. Theory in Biosciences, 124, 281–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindley, J. (1830). An introduction to the natural system of botany: Or, A systematic view of the organisation, natural affinities, and geographical distribution, of the whole vegetable kingdom: together with the uses of the most important species in medicine, the arts, and rural or domestic economy (1st ed.). London: Longman, Rees, Orme, Brown, and Green.

  • Locke, J. (1690). An essay concerning human understanding. London: Thomas Basset.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macleay, W. S. (1819). Horae entomologicae, or, essays on the annulose animals. London: Printed for S. Bagster.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maund, B. (2008). Color. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/color/.

  • Mayr, E. (1978). Origin and history of some terms in systematic and evolutionary biology. Systematic Zoology, 27(1), 83–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McOuat, G. R. (1996). Species, rules and meaning: the politics of language and the ends of definitions in 19th century natural history. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 27, 473–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McOuat, G. R. (2001). Cataloguing power: Delineating ‘competent naturalists’ and the meaning of species in the British Museum. The British Journal for the History of Science, 34, 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • McOuat, G. R. (2003). The logical systematist: George Bentham and his Outline of a new system of logic. Archives of Natural History, 30(2), 203–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McOuat, G. R. (2009). The origins of natural kinds: Keeping “Essentialism” at bay in the age of reform. Intellectual History Review, 19(2009), 211–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer-Abich, A. (1926). Logik der Morphologie, im Rahmen einer Logik der gesamten Biologie. Berlin: Nelson, E. C.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1889). An examination of Sir William Hamilton’s philosophy, and of the principal philosophical questions discussed in his writings (6th ed.). London, New York: Longman, Green and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (2006a). A system of logic ratiocinative and inductive, being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation (books I–III). In J. M. Robson (Ed.), The collected works of John Stuart mill (33 Vols., Vol. VII). Toronto, London: University of Toronto Press, Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Original edition, 1974).

  • Mill, J. S. (2006b). A system of logic ratiocinative and inductive, being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation (books IV–VI and appendices). In J. M. Robson (Ed.), The collected works of John Stuart mill (33 Vols., Vol. VIII). Toronto, London: University of Toronto Press, Routledge and Kegan Paul (Original edition, 1974).

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milne-Edwards, H. (1844). Considérations sur quelques principes relatifs à la clasification naturelle des animaux, et plus particulièrement sur la distribution méthodique des mammifères. Annales des Sciences Naturelles (Zoologie), 3d(1), 65–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mindell, D. P., & Meyer, A. (2001). Homology evolving. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 16(8), 434–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille, S., & Orel, V. (2007). From Linnaean species to Mendelian factors: Elements of hybridism, 1751–1870. Annals of Science, 64(2), 171–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, G. J. (1978). Ontogeny, phylogeny, paleontology, and the biogenetic law. Systematic Zoology, 27, 324–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Numbers, R. L. (2009). Galileo goes to jail: And other myths about science and religion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oken, L. (1847). Elements of physiophilosophy (A. Tulk, Trans.) London: The Ray Society. (Original edition, Lehrbuch der Naturphilosophie (Jena: Friedrich Frommann, 1831, 2nd ed.)).

  • Owen, R. (1843). Lectures on the comparative anatomy and physiology of the invertebrate animals, delivered at the Royal College of Surgeons, in 1843. By Richard Owen. From notes taken by William White Cooper and revised by Professor Owen. London: Longman, Brown, Green, and Longmans.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Owen, R. (1848). The archetype and homologies of the vertebrate skeleton. London: J. van Voorst.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1969). Essentialism and quantified modal logic. The Philosophical Review, 78(1), 35–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1957). The poverty of historicism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery (K. Popper, J. Freed and L. Freed, Trans.). London: Hutchinson.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1948). On what there is. Review of Metaphysics, 2(5), 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1953). From a logical point of view: 9 Logico-philosophical essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969a). Natural kinds. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Essays in honour of Carl G. Hempel: A tribute on the occasion of his sixty-fifth birthday (pp. 5–27). Dordrecht, Holland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969b). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray, J. (1686). Historia plantarum species hactenus editas aliasque insuper multas noviter inventas & descriptas complectens : In qua agitur primò De Plantis in genere, Earúmque Partibus, Accidentibus & Differentiis; Deinde Genera omnia tum summa tum subalterna ad Species usque infimas, Notis suis certis & Characteristicis Definita, Methodo Naturæ vestigiis insistente disponuntur; Species singulæ accurate describuntur, obscura illustrantur, omissa supplentur, superflua resecantur, Synonyma necessaria adjiciunctur; Vires denique & Usus recepti compendiò traduntur/Auctore Joanne Raio, E Societate Regiâ,… (3 Vols., Vol. I). Londini: Clark.

  • Reichenbach, H. (1949). The theory of probability, an inquiry into the logical and mathematical foundations of the calculus of probability (2nd ed.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, E. C. (1901). Classification, theoretical and practical I. The order of the sciences (2 Vols., Vol. 1). New York: Scribner.

  • Rupke, N. A. (1994). Richard Owen: Victorian naturalist. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1991). Hans Reichenbach’s vindication of induction. Erkenntnis, 35(1), 99–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E. R. (2007). The periodic table: Its story and its significance. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, J. Y. (1925). Landmarks in the struggle between science and religion. London: Hodder and Stoughton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, G. G. (1961). Principles of animal taxonomy. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder, L. J. (2006). Reforming philosophy: A Victorian debate on science and society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1999). Modus Darwin. Biology and Philosophy, 14(2), 253–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: the logic behind the science. Cambridge, UK, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stafleu, F. A. (1963). Adanson and the « Familles des plantes». In G. H. M. Lawrence (Ed.), Adanson: The bicentennial of Michel Adanson’s « Familles des plantes» (pp. 123–264). Pittsburgh, PA: Carnegie Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, P. F. (1994). The development of biological systematics: Antoine-Laurent de Jussieu, nature, and the natural system. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swainson, W. (1834). Preliminary discourse on the study of natural history. London: Longman, Rees, Orme, Brown, Green and Longman.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swainson, W. (1835). A treatise on the geography and classification of animals. In R. D. Lardner (Ed.), The cabinet cyclopaedia: Natural history. London: Longman Rees, Orme, Brown & Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Templeton, A. R. (1989). The meaning of species and speciation: A genetic perspective. In D. Otte & J. Endler (Eds.), Speciation and its consequences (pp. 3–27). Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Venn, J. (1866). The logic of chance: An essay on the foundations and province of the theory of probability, with especial reference to its application to moral and social science. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary essentialism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(2), 425–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whately, R. (1875). Elements of logic (9th (octavo) ed.). London: Longmans, Green & Co. (Original edition, 1826).

  • Whewell, W. (1840). The philosophy of the inductive sciences: Founded upon their history (2 Vols.). London: John W. Parker.

  • Whewell, W. (1847). The philosophy of the inductive sciences: Founded upon their history (2nd ed., 2 Vols.). London: John W. Parker.

  • Whewell, W. (1849). Of induction with especial reference to J.S. Mill’s system of logic. London: John W. Parker.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, W. (1884). History of the inductive sciences, from the earliest to the present time (3rd ed., 2 Vols.). New York: D. Appleton.

  • Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Species: A history of the idea, species and systematics. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment, and the innate-acquired distinction. In W. Bechtel (Ed.), Integrating scientific disciplines (pp. 185–208). Dordrecht: Martinus-Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Winsor, M. P. (2000). Species, demes, and the omega taxonomy: Gilmour and the new systematics. Biology and Philosophy, 15(3), 349–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsor, M. P. (2003). Non-essentialist methods in pre-Darwinian taxonomy. Biology and Philosophy, 18, 387–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsor, M. P. (2004). Setting up milestones: Sneath on Adanson and Mayr on Darwin. In D. M. Williams & P. L. Forey (Eds.), Milestones in systematics: Essays from a symposium held within the 3rd systematics association biennial meeting, September 2001 (pp. 1–17). London: Systematics Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winsor, M. P. (2006). The creation of the essentialism story: An exercise in metahistory. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 28, 149–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodger, J. H. (1937). The axiomatic method in biology. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Michael Devitt, Gordon McOuat, Polly Winsor, Paul Griffiths, Karola Stotz, and Dominic Murphy for critical comments and suggestions. I also thank Philip Sloan for his discussions at ISHPSSB 2009, and the audience there. This work was undertaken with funding from an Australian Research Council postdoctoral fellowship DP0984826, based on work done under a previous ARC grant FF0457917.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John S. Wilkins.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Wilkins, J.S. Biological Essentialism and the Tidal Change of Natural Kinds. Sci & Educ 22, 221–240 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9450-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-012-9450-z

Keywords

Navigation