Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-hfldf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-07T01:55:36.646Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Socrates as Political Partisan*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 November 2009

Neal Wood
Affiliation:
York University

Abstract

Socrate, le partisan

Plutôt qu'un philosophe engagé dans la recherche détachée, désintéressée et transcendantale de la Vérité, Socrate semble avoir été un authentique partisan politique, voire même l'un des plus grands idéologues de tous les temps. Une telle affirmation n'a pas pour but de dénigrer ni la personne ni la philosophie de Socrate, mais bien de permettre une meilleure compréhension de son activité intellectuelle et, possiblement, de la philosophie en général. Contrairement à l'opinion généralement répandue selon laquelle Socrate était d'origine populaire, il appert que sa provenance familiale, son éducation, son mariage et ses revenus (en début de carrière, tout au moins) le classent probablement dans une strate sociale supérieure à la moyenne de ses concitoyens athéniens. Parmi ses amis et ses connaissances, d'un statut social similaire au sien, on retrouve plusieurs opposants à la démocratie athénienne et défenseurs de la politique de Sparte. On conçoit done facilement que les idées politiques de Socrate aient été enracinées dans une conceptualisation foncièrement anti-démocratique composée des éléments suivants: une antipathie fondamentale à l'égard des assises de la pratique démocratique que sont l'égalité et le consensus; un mépris ouvert pour les milieux populaires; une critique forcenée des institutions et des dirigeants de la démocratie athénienne; et une admiration pour les institutions et la politique de Sparte. De plus, il apparaît que ses propositions philosophiques les plus importantes, concernant les notions de définition, de connaissance et d'âme, traduisent, en même temps qu'elles leur procurent des assises intellectuelles, et son idéologie anti-démocratique et sa position de classe. Toutes ces considérations nous permettent de mieux comprendre – à défaut d'excuser – la condamnation de Socrate par le peuple et les dirigeants athéniens en 399 av. jc, à la suite de leur désastreuse défaite aux mains de Sparte et de l'expérience traumatisante du terrorisme sous les Trente Tyrans.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Political Science Association (l'Association canadienne de science politique) and/et la Société québécoise de science politique 1974

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For most of what follows I have relied upon the anthology of opinions about Socrates edited by Herbert Spiegelberg, in collaboration with Morgan, Bayard Quincy, The Socratic Enigma: A Collection of Testimonies through Twenty-Four Centuries (Indianapolis, 1964).Google Scholar

2 Ibid., 83: Bentham, Jeremy, Deontology, or The Science of Morals (London, 1834), I, 39Google Scholar; conversation reported in The Works of Jeremy Bentham (Edinburgh, 1843), x, 583.

3 Ibid., 97: Macaulay, T.B., Diary (July, 1853)Google Scholar, in Trevelyan, G. Otto, Lord Macaulay, Life and Letters (New York, 1878), II, 235ff.Google Scholar

4 Ibid., 115: Russell, Bertrand, A History of Western Philosophy (New York, 1945), 142.Google Scholar

5 Ibid., 258, 262: Nietzsche, Friedrich, Die fröhliche Wissenschaft (1882)Google Scholar, no. 340, in Werke, VI, 290–1; “Das Problem des Sokrates,” Götzendämmerung (1888), in Werke, X, 245–51.

6 Ibid., 62: Erasmus, Convivium Religiosum (1522), in Opera, I, 683.

7 Ibid., 93: Shelley, , “Fragments connected with Epipsychidion,” line 33, in The Complete Works (New York, 1904), 469.Google Scholar

8 Ibid., 183: Voltaire, “Homélie sur l'Interprétation du Nouveau Testament,” in Œuvres, xxx, 353.

9 Ibid., 69: Milton, Satan speaking in Paradise Regained, Bk. iv, 11, 272–7, 293–4, in Works, ii, 2, 469.

10 Ibid., 73: Third Earl of Shaftesbury, “Miscellaneous Reflections” (1711), Pt. V, sec. 1, in Characteristics, iii, 244.

11 Ibid., 300: Kierkegaard, Søren, Journals, no. 663 (1847), 208.Google Scholar

12 Ibid., 274: Heidegger, Martin, Was Heisst Denken? (Tübingen, 1954), 56.Google Scholar

13 History of Political Philosophy, ed. Strauss, Leo and Cropsey, Joseph (Chicago, 2nd ed., 1972), 17.Google Scholar

14 Socrates (Garden City, N.Y., 1953), 132.

15 Crossman, R.H.S., Plato Today (New York, 1939), 86–8, 304–5Google Scholar; Popper, Karl R., The Open Society and Its Enemies (Princeton, 1950), esp. 126–30, 184–9.Google Scholar

16 Who Was Socrates? (New York, 2nd ed., 1960), passim.

17 Chroust, Anton-Hermann, Socrates Man and Myth: The Two Socratic Apologies of Xenophon (Notre Dame, Ind., 1957), esp. 191–7, 223.Google Scholar

18 A History of Political Theory (New York, 3rd ed., 1961), 32–4.

19 Gulley, Norman, The Philosophy of Socrates (London, 1968)Google Scholar; Guthrie, W.K.C., A History of Greek Philosophy (Cambridge, 1969)Google Scholar, vol. iii, “The Fifth Century Enlightenment,” pt. ii, “Socrates,” 323–507.

20 My position is directly opposed to that of Dante Germino. See his Beyond Ideology: The Revival of Political Theory (New York, 1967), esp. 7, 9, 11, 28–9, 37–8. The problem with Germino's contentions is that he simply asserts a position without adequately supporting it. In what follows I do not mean to imply that any political theorist of the first rank is completely time-bound. Obviously, as man, citizen, and thinker, he may have something of value to impart to men, citizens, and thinkers in the future.

21 Winspear, Alban D. comments in a perceptive, but neglected study originally published in 1940, The Genesis of Plato's Thought (New York, 2nd ed., 1956)Google Scholar, v: “nowhere can the social roots of philosophy be more sharply seen and more firmly apprehended than when one is dealing with the origins of Western philosophy among the Greeks.” I hope to elucidate in a much more detailed way the relationship between political ideology and “non-political” philosophy in a forthcoming book-length study on the politics of John Locke's epistemology. For a somewhat different approach see Wood, Ellen Meiksins, Mind and Politics: An Approach to the Meaning of Liberal and Socialist Individualism (Berkeley, 1972).Google Scholar

22 In this I have followed Guthrie. The chronology of Plato's early works is that of Robinson, R.G.F., “Plato,” Oxford Classical Dictionary (Oxford, 2nd ed., 1970), 842.Google Scholar

23 For biographical data I have relied primarily on Guthrie, A History, vol. III, 378–90; and Taylor, Socrates, 37–129. Still of value are Burnet, John, Greek Philosophy: Thales to Plato (London, 1955), 126–50Google Scholar; Zeller, Eduard, Socrates and the Socratic Schools, tr. Reichel, O.J. (New York, 3rd ed., 1962), 5370.Google Scholar The portrayal that emerges particularly in regard to Socrates’ social class and connection is fundamentally my own.

24 Chroust, Socrates Man and Myth, xii, states that the following are the only indisputable facts about Socrates: “that Socrates lived; that he was called Socrates; that the name of his father was Sophroniscus while that of his mother was Phaenarete; that he belonged to the deme Alopece; that he was an Athenian citizen; that he probably participated in some military compaigns; that he was connected with the trial of the generals in 406; that he was tried and condemned to death; and that he died in 399.”

25 180e.

26 An account of Archelaus is given in Guthrie, A History, vol. II, “The Presocratic Tradition from Parmenides to Democritus,” 339–44. Also see his treatment of Anaxagoras’ life, 266–9, and vol. iii, 422. Taylor, Socrates, 59–71, should be consulted on the problem of chronology. Barker, Ernest in Greek Political Theory: Plato and His Predecessors (London, 1960), 99Google Scholar n.1, writes, agreeing with Guthrie and Taylor: “Archelaus of Athens was the first Athenian citizen to turn to philosophy. Socrates had been his disciple, and he may have succeeded him as the head of the school which he had founded.” Also see Barker, , The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (New York, 1959), 25.Google Scholar

27 The subsequent details about the social structure of Athens are mainly drawn from Jones's, A.H.M. reconstruction in Athenian Democracy (Oxford, 1957), 7596.Google Scholar

28 Plutarch, Aristides, 1. Taylor, Socrates, 42–3, thinks there is reason to believe the story; Zeller, Socratic Schools, 55 n.l, rejects it.

29 Most of the following information about family connections is derived from Davies, J.K., Athenian Propertied Families 600–300 B.C. (Oxford, 1971).Google Scholar

30 Plutarch, Cimon, 4. Guthrie, A History, vol. ii, 339 n.l, refers to Wilamowitz (Glaube, 2.212) who concludes from Plutarch's account that Archelaus belonged to the “vornehme Gesellschaft.” At least it might indicate that he was sympathetic to the aristocratic-oligarchic opposition to Periclean democracy.

31 On Thucydides, son of Melesias, see Bowra, C.M., Periclean Athens (London, 1971), 175204Google Scholar; Connor, W. Robert, The New Politicians of Fifth-Century Athens (Princeton, 1971), 24Google Scholar; Ehrenberg, Victor, From Solon to Socrates: Greek History and Civilization During the Sixth and Fifth Centuries B.C. (London, 1968), 226–8.Google Scholar

32 For an evaluation of Xenophon as a military and political thinker see my “Xenophon's Theory of Leadership,” Classica et Mediaevalia, XXV (1964), 33–66.

33 36b.

34 Xenophon, Memorabilia, i, ii, 18; iii, xiv; Zeller, Socratic Schools, 69–70, comments: “With more intimate friends he frequently had common meals, which, however, can scarcely have been a fixed institution.”

35 See the brief remarks on the mutual political support of fellow-demesmen in Connor, New Politicians, 22 n.35.

36 Apology, 31c–33b; Memorabilia, i, vi, 15.

37 473e. Unless otherwise specified translations of Plato are those from The Collected Dialogues of Plato Including the Letters, ed. Hamilton, Edith and Cairns, Huntington (Princeton, 1963).Google Scholar

38 521a.

39 521d.

40 iv, ii, 11. Translations of Xenophon are those of Benjamin, Anna S., trans, and ed., Xenophon, Recollections of Socrates and Socrates’ Defense Before the Jury (Indianapolis, 1965).Google Scholar

41 iv, ii, 2.

42 290a–292e.

43 Laches, 179a–e; Protagoras, 319b; Gorgias, 515a–517e; Meno, 93a–94e.

44 21b–22a,31d–e, 32e.

45 90a–95a.

46 i, vi, 15.

47 Memorabilia, i, i, 16.

48 Memorabilia, iv, ii. Also, iii, i, 4–5; iv, 1; vi, 20–4; ix, 10–13; iv, ii, 2, 6–8, 11.

49 Memorabilia, ii, i.

50 Memorabilia, i, ii, 12–16.

51 Memorabilia, i, ii, 17–18. Cf. with Alcibiades’ remarks in the Symposium, 216b–c: “Socrates is the only man in the world that can make me feel ashamed. Because there's no getting away from it, I know I ought to do the things he tells me to, and yet the moment I'm out of his sight I don't care what I do to keep in with the mob. So I dash off like a runaway slave, and keep out of his way as long as I can, and then next time I meet him I remember all that I had to admit the time before, and naturally I feel ashamed. There are times when I'd honestly be glad to hear that he was dead, and yet I know that if he did die I'd be more upset than ever – so I ask you, what is a man to do?”

52 Apology, 33a–b.

53 Apology, 31c–d.

54 Apology, 36b–c.

55 Apology, 31e–32a.

56 Apology, 30e–31a.

57 Apology, 36c.

58 New Politicians, chs. 3–4.

59 Ibid., 194–5.

60 Ibid., 196–7.

61 Ibid., 197.

62 Memorabilia, ii, ii, 60.

63 Memorabilia, iii, vii, 5–9.

64 Euthyphro, 4a.

65 474a.

66 Guthrie, A History, iii, 470.

67 Alcibiades I, 110d.

68 Alcibiades I, 120b (Jowett translation).

69 Alcibiades I, 131a–b. In Hippias Major, 284e, whose authenticity is also questioned, Socrates agrees that the multitude does not know truth.

70 See below, 25. However, it would seem that men are unequal by birth and not simply nurture. Socrates is hard to pin down on this point, but not Plato, for example, Republic, 415a–b, 431c, 442e, 491d–492a, 519a–d, 590c–d.

71 Laches, 184e.

72 Memorabilia, iii, ix, 10.

73 Gorgias, 515e.

74 Laches, 179a–e; Protagoras, 319e–320b; Gorgias, 515a–519e; Meno, 93a–94e. Interestingly enough the great democratic legislator of the end of the sixth century, Cleisthenes, who was a much exalted hero of the democrats, is never mentioned, nor does his name appear in any of the writings of Plato and Xenophon. Was this a conscious conspiracy of silence on the part of the anti-democrats?

75 Gorgias, 516e.

76 Gorgias, 518e–519a.

77 See Meno, 94e, where Anytus, later to bring the indictment against Socrates, is reported as saying to Socrates, after one of his characteristic attacks upon Athenian statesmen: “You seem to me, Socrates, to be too ready to run people down. My advice to you, if you will listen to it, is to be careful. I dare say that in all cities it is easier to do a man harm than good, and it is certainly so here, as I expect you know yourself.”

78 515e.

79 See the summary in Morrow, Glenn R., Plato's Cretan City: A Historical Interpretation of the Laws (Princeton, 1960), 42–3.Google Scholar

80 Memorabilia, iii, v. 13–14.

81 Memorabilia, iv, iv, 15–17.

82 342a–343b.

83 52e.

84 iii, vii, 5–6.

85 iii, vii, 9.

86 Memorabilia, iii, i, 1–5; iv; v, 21–24.

87 Memorabilia, iv, ii, 2.

88 Memorabilia, iv, ii, 6–7.

89 319b–d. Cf. Gorgias, 455b–d.

90 Apology, 22d.

91 161a–164e.

92 For example, Memorabilia, iv, vi, 12.

93 One problem with contemporary philosophic analysis when applied to a classic text is that by ignoring the historical context it may distort or fail to perceive the meaning and significance of statements. So, for example, Hanna Pitkin in an otherwise insightful essay asserts that Socrates, in feeling obliged to accept the death sentence of the Five Hundred, “can find no fault with the Athenian laws, nor even with the Athenian way of administering them… Socrates’ past consent is not so much compelling in its own right, as it is a way of expressing and reinforcing his present judgment that there is nothing basically wrong with the system, no justification for resistance” (67). To the contrary, as we have seen, Socrates’ obedience to the law is so arresting and interesting for the very reason that he thinks nearly everything is basically wrong with the system, including the fundamental assumptions upon which it is premised. See Pitkin, Hanna, “Obligation and Consent,” Philosophy, Politics and Society Fourth Series, ed. Laslett, Peter, Runciman, W. G., and Skinner, Quentin (Oxford, 1972), 4585.Google Scholar

94 Memorabilia, iv, iv, 14–18.

95 Apology, 29d.

96 50–3.

97 On the question of Socrates’ attitude to the law in the Apology and Crito in general, and in regard to his “natural-law position” in particular, see Woozley, A.D., “Socrates on Disobeying the Law,” in The Philosophy of Socrates: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Vlastos, Gregory (Garden City, N.Y., 1971), 299318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

98 Xenophon does suggest in Memorabilia, iv, iv, 19–25, that Socrates believed in certain divine laws such as honouring parents, prohibiting incest, and returning good with good. But nothing indicates precisely how Socrates views these norms, particularly in relation to the law of the polis. See the remarks in Ernest Barker, Political Thought, 52: “For him there was no rule of natural justice outside the law: law is justice, he held, and what is just is simply what is commanded in the laws.” The question would seem to be more complex and Socrates’ position more ambiguous than Barker implies.

99 Philosophy of Socrates, 173–4.

100 Political Thought, 51.

101 Socrates 149–52.

102 Guthrie, A History, vol. III, 415–16.

103 History of Political Thought (New York, 1924), 43.

104 Sabine, History of Political Theory, 32–4.

105 Masters of Political Thought (Boston, 1941), vol. I, “Plato to Machiavelli,” 19–22.

106 Political Theory: Philosophy, Ideology, Science (New York, 1961).

107 History of Political Philosophy, 1–7.

108 Political Ideas and Ideologies: A History of Political Thought (New York, 1970), 56–61.

109 Throughout the subsequent discussion I am indebted to Gulley and Guthrie for the explication of Socrates’ philosophic position, but the conclusions I draw in relating it to his political ideology are my own.

110 For Socrates on definition see: Memorabilia, i, i, 16; iv, i, 5; v, 11–12; vi, 1; Laches, 190c–d; Charmides, 159a; Protagoras, 361c; Euthyphro, 7c–d; Gorgias, 474d ff.; Meno, 72a ff.; Phaedrus, 263a ff.

111 See esp. Memorabilia, iii, ix, 5; iv, vi, 6; Laches, 190b; Protagoras, 319a–320c, 349e–350a, 360a–361a; Meno, 71a, 87b ff.

112 Memoriabilia, iii, viii, 4–8; ix, 4–5; iv, vi, 8–9; Protagoras, 358b–d; Gorgias, 474d–475a; Meno, 87d–e.

113 i, ii, 53.

114 i, iv, 13.

115 iv, iii, 14.

116 i, iv, 9; iv, iii, 14.

117 i, ii, 54.

118 29d–30b.

119 Apology, 29e–30a; Memorabilia, i, ii, 2.

120 Memorabilia, i, ii, 1–4.

121 47e–48a.

122 38a; cf. Alcibiades I, 129a.

123 47d–48a.

124 Xenophon, Oeconomicus, iv, 2–3. Cf. Republic, 495a–b and with the words of Creon's herald in Euripides, Suppliants (E.P. Coleridge, translation), 420, called by Guthrie, A History, vol. iii, 411, “pure Socratic doctrine”: “Besides, how shall the people, if it cannot form true judgments, be able rightly to direct the state? Nay, ‘tis time, not haste, that affords a better understanding. A poor hind, granted he be not all unschooled, would still be unable from his toil to give his mind to politics. Verify the better sort count it no healthy sign when the worthless man obtains a reputation by beguiling with words the populace, though aforetime he was naught.” See n.70 above for the question of inequality by nature or nurture.

125 80a–82d; cf. Alcibiades I, 129a–130a.

126 248c–e.

127 This brief summary of fourth-century Athens owes most to the views of Ehrenberg, Solon to Socrates, 375; Jones, Athenian Democracy, 90ff.; Finley, M.I., Aspects of Antiquity: Discoveries and Controversies (New York, 1968), 5888Google Scholar; Morrow, Glenn R., Introduction, Plato's Epistles (Indianapolis, 1962), 131–2.Google Scholar

128 Bowra, Periclean Athens, 190–7.

129 Chroust, Socrates Man and Myth, 170. Plato in the Seventh Epistle, 325b, comments upon the democrats’ return to power in 403: “but in general those who returned from exile acted with great restraint.” (Morrow translation)

130 Taylor, Socrates, 103.