Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-hfldf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-16T12:02:46.051Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Mill and Millians on Liberty and Moral Character*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Abstract

This essay critically explores the efforts of John Stuart Mill and contemporary Millian scholarship to provide a utilitarian justification for a categorical principle of personal liberty. What is distinctive about Mill's argument is its pronounced emphasis upon character development as an essential constituent of happiness; the heart of the argument is that freedom of choice promotes a kind of elevated or worthy human character upon which happiness ultimately depends. Hence, society must be prevented from imposing any conventional or customary morality which would restrict individual autonomy. This case for the sovereignty of personal autonomy is infected with a number of difficulties and ambiguities. Central among these are weighty problems associated with Mill's crucial concept of individuality and its relation to human excellence or nobility of character. The refinements upon Millian doctrine introduced by his current supporters do not, and cannot, resolve its inherent ambiguities.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 See Gray, John, Mill on Liberty: A Defence (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ten, C. L., Mill on Liberty (London: Oxford University Press, 1980), particularly Preface, p. viiGoogle Scholar; and Ryan, Alan, John Stuart Mill (New York: Pantheon Books, 1970), chap. 13.Google Scholar

2 For example, see Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977), pp. 198–99 and 272–73.Google Scholar

3 Utilitarianism, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government (New York: E. P. Dutton, 1951), pp. 9596Google Scholar. All subsequent references to On Liberty, Utilitarianism and Considerations on Representative Government are to this edition.

4 This rather stringent formulation is supported by the most prominent examples On Liberty provides of conduct “harmful to others.” While Mill deviates from it when he allows society to prohibit certain public acts as “offences against decency” (On Liberty, p. 206Google Scholar), his argument cannot afford many such deviations.

5 On Liberty, p. 186Google Scholar. Mill is sometimes accused of unrealistically assuming that a person's activity can be sharply divided into two spheres: that which affects and concerns only himself and that which affects and concerns others. To this it is replied that “no man is an island.” This criticism is not entirely fair to Mill. Mill's awareness that no man is an island is evidenced in his acknowledgement of indirect or contingent injuries to others resulting from conduct in the “self-regarding” sphere. The controversial question is whether Mill unduly minimizes the significance of such effects.

6 Ibid., p. 97.

7 Ten, , Mill on Liberty, p. 14.Google Scholar

8 The reader is referred to Mill's discussion of indirect or contingent effects at pp. 183–86.

9 Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15, 63 (1973).Google Scholar

10 Ryan, , John Stuart Mill, p. 240.Google Scholar

11 Mill was asked by a Royal Commission whether state licensing and medical examination of prostitutes would be likely to promote “moral injury.” He responded: “I do think so, because I hardly think it possible for thoughtless persons not to infer, when special precautions are taken to make a course which is generally considered worthy of disapprobation safer than it would naturally be, that it cannot be considered very bad by the law, and possibly may be considered not bad at all, or at any rate a necessary evil” (quoted in Arkes, Hadley, The Philosopher in the City Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981, p. 440).Google Scholar

12 On Liberty, p. 199.Google Scholar

13 According to Rolf E. Sartorius, even “act utilitarianism” is capable of providing such norms. See Sartorius, , Individual Conduct and Social Norms (Encino, California: Dickenson Publishing Co., 1975).Google Scholar

14 Gray, , Mill on Liberty: A Defence, p. 14.Google Scholar

15 Ibid p. 52.

16 Utilitarianism, p. 32.Google Scholar

17 A System of Logic (London: Longmans, Green, 1949), p. 621.Google Scholar

18 On Liberty, p. 153.Google Scholar

19 “[I]ndividuality is the same thing with development, and … it is only the cultivation of individuality which produces or can produce well developed human beings” (On Liberty, p. 162Google Scholar). This is just what classical philosophy said about areté (usually translated as virtue or human excellence).

20 Utilitarianism, p. 14Google Scholar. We are not concerned here with the validity of Mill's effort to derive the good and the noble from the pleasant. Our interest is in the fact that high ethical standards emerge from Mill's argument.

21 Gray, , Mill on Liberty: A Defence, p. 73.Google Scholar

22 Utilitarianism, p. 13.Google Scholar

23 Ten, , Mill on Liberty, pp. 8283.Google Scholar

24 Devlin, Patrick, The Enforcement of Morals (London: Oxford University Press, 1965), p. 108.Google Scholar

25 See particularly Considerations on Representative Government, pp. 334–40.Google Scholar

26 Utilitarianism, p. 38.Google Scholar

27 Ibid., p. 41–2.

28 Stephen, James Fitzjames, Liberty, Equality, Fraternity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), p. 81.Google Scholar

29 Gray, , Mill on Liberty: A Defence, p. 85.Google Scholar

31 On Liberty, pp. 186–87.Google Scholar

32 Ibid., 164.

33 That recent movement calling itself the “Moral Majority” is a case in point. It hardly represents a majority capable of making significant inroads upon our liberal dispensation.

34 On Liberty, p. 171.Google Scholar

35 Ibid., p. 156.

36 See Ten, , Mill on Liberty, p. 70.Google Scholar

37 On Liberty, p. 155.Google Scholar

38 See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, bk. 2.Google Scholar

39 See Burke, Edmund, Reflections on the Revolution in France (Garden City, New York: Doubleday, 1961), particularly pp. 4348.Google Scholar

40 Gray, , Mill on Liberty: A Defence, p. 119.Google Scholar

41 A System of Logic, p. 620.Google Scholar

42 See Gray, , Mill on Liberty: A Defence, p. 99.Google Scholar

43 Supra, pp. 67.Google Scholar

44 Unfortunately, the limits of space do not allow for discussion of one of Mill's important practical arguments against public intervention in “personal conduct.” This is the argument that, when the public interferes with such conduct, “the odds are that it interferes wrongly, and in the wrong place” (On Liberty, p. 188Google Scholar). Mill seems to suppose here that the public and the law are wholly intractable and uneducable in this regard. At any rate, how can a consistent utilitarianism derive from this consideration anything more than a presumption in favor of liberty? For an example of a relentless effort to derive considerably more, see Sartorius, , Individual Conduct and Social Norms, pp. 154–58.Google Scholar

45 Ryan, , John Stuart Mill, p. 255.Google Scholar

46 On Liberty, p. 125.Google Scholar

47 Ibid., pp. 108–09.

48 “It is not too much to require that what the wisest of mankind, those who are best entitled to trust their own judgment, find necessary to warrant their relying on it, should be submitted to by that miscellaneous collection of a few wise and many foolish individuals, called the public” (ibid., p. 109). My point in the following paragraphs above is that this is indeed too much to require.

49 For example, contrast book 3 which ends with the “noble lie” with book 7 which begins with the philosopher's transcendence of the opinions in “the cave” of society.

50 “[U]nder no circumstances will dogmatic belief cease to exist, or, in other words, men will never cease to entertain some opinions on trust and without discussion. If everyone undertook to form all his own opinions and to seek for truth by isolated paths struck out by himself alone, it would follow that no considerable number of men would ever unite in any common belief. … But obviously without such common belief no society can prosper; say, rather, no society can exist” (de Tocqueville, Alexis, Democracy in America [New York, 1945], 2:9Google Scholar). It is of some scholarly interest why Mill, who so much admired Tocqueville's ideas of liberty, did not come more to grips with Tocqueville's ideas of its limiting conditions. See also Democracy in America, vol. 2, chap. 5.Google Scholar

51 On Liberty, p. 153Google Scholar. See also Autobiography of John Stuart Mill (New York: Columbia University Press, 1924), pp. 167–68 and 177–78Google Scholar; comparison of these two passages raises perplexing questions as to Mill's final attitude toward communal consensus. It is not easy to determine whether Mill welcomed an eventual consensus as desirable or thought of it as historically inevitable but inevita bly dangerous.

52 Ten, , Mill on Liberty, p. 127.Google Scholar