Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-skm99 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-29T20:56:49.471Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Legal Concept of Community

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 July 2014

Roger Cotterrell
Affiliation:
Queen Mary and Westfield College, University of London, UK

Abstract

The concept of community has a new importance for legal theory and legal sociology. It allows an escape from traditional conceptions of the relationship between law, state and political society. It makes possible the development of a pluralistic view of law that realistically recognises powerful globalising and localising pressures shaping contemporary law. Community is best thought of initially in terms of four ideal types of collective involvement, derived from Weber's types of social action. These imply different kinds of trusting relationships and different regulatory needs. A sense of attachment and a degree of stability in relationships is also necessary to community. Actual groups combine relationships of community in many different ways. Law's contemporary task is to express and coordinate the regulatory needs surrounding structures of community within and beyond the nation state.

Résumé

Le concept de communauté a pris, dans la théorie du droit et dans celle de la sociologie du droit, une nouvelle dimension. Il permet de s'échapper des conceptions traditionnelles de la relation entre le droit, l'État et la communauté politique. Il rend possible la définition d'une vision pluraliste du droit qui reconnaît la réalité des mouvements de globalisation et de régionalisation influençant le droit contemporain. Dans sa conception d'origine, la communauté repose sur quatre types d'implication collective, inspirés des formes d'action sociale proposées par Weber. Celles-ci soustendent qu'il existe plusieurs formes de relations de confiance et donc différents besoins d'encadrement juridique. Pour que se forme une communauté, un sentiment d'appartenance et un certain degré de stabilité des relations est nécessaire. Certains groupes échafaudent leurs relations de multiples façons. La tâche du droit contemporain est de formuler et de coordonner les besoins d'encadrement juridique en vue de circonscrire la communauté au sein de l'État nation et au-delà.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Law and Society Association 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Petersen, H. & Zahle, H., eds., Legal Polycentricity: Consequences of Pluralism in Law (Aldershot: Dartmouth, 1995)Google Scholar.

2. A.-J. Arnaud, “Legal Pluralism and the Building of Europe” in Petersen & Zahle, eds., ibid. 149.

3. Suggesting a less direct and subordinate relation to a national centre than the older conception of “provinces.” See Anderson, P., The Invention of the Region: 1945-1990 (EUI Working Paper EUF 94/2) (Florence: European University Institute, 1994)Google Scholar.

4. Axford, B., The Global System: Economics, Politics and Culture (Cambridge: Polity, 1995) at 164ff.Google Scholar

5. Baumann, Z., Intimations of Postmodernity (London: Routledge, 1992) c. 9Google Scholar; Smart, B., Postmodernity (London: Routledge, 1993) at 5758Google Scholar.

6. Woolf, S., Europe and the Nation-State (EUI Working Paper HEC 91/11) (Florence: European University Institute, 1991)Google Scholar.

7. See Lacey, N., “Community in Legal Theory: Idea, Ideal or Ideology?” in Sarat, A. & Silbey, S., eds, Studies in Law, Politics and Society, vol. 15 (New York: JAI Press, 1996) 105 at 120Google Scholar.

8. Fitzpatrick, P., “Being Social in Socio-Legal Studies” (1995) 22 Journal of Law and Society 105CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9. A convenient local illustration, for this writer, of the problems that arise when these relations are unclear is the longstanding, fundamentally ambiguous situation of Scotland, having its own law (Scots law) and yet not its own law (Scots law being ultimately subordinate to United Kingdom law and the legislative will of the United Kingdom Parliament). The combination of autonomy and dependence has made indeterminate for a long time (and, for some political purposes, conveniently) the nature of the social/political entity which, as Scotland, law defines. The recent decision in favour of creating a Scottish parliament will undoubtedly begin to change, or at least further complicate, this situation.

10. Hamilton, P., “Editor's Foreword” in Cohen, A. P., The Symbolic Construction of Community (London: Routledge, 1985) 7 at 7Google Scholar.

11. Cohen, ibid. at 19.

12. Ibid. at 9.

13. Schutz, A., “Equality and the Meaning Structure of the Social World” in Schutz, A., Collected Papers: Studies in Social Theory, vol. 2, ed. by Brodersen, A. (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1964) 226 at 250–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

14. Gurvitch, G., Sociology of Law (London: Routledge, 1973)Google Scholar.

15. Belley, J.-G., “Georges Gurvitch et les professionels de la pensée juridique” (1986) 4 Droit et Société 353CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Belley, J.-G., “Deux Journées dans la vie du droit: Georges Gurvitch et Ian R. Macneil” (1988) 3 C.J.L.S. 27CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

16. Dworkin, R., Law's Empire (London: Fontana, 1986) c. 6Google Scholar.

17. Hamilton, supra note 10 at 8.

18. Finnis, J., Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980) at 141ff.Google Scholar Finnis treats what he calls relationships of play as fundamentally distinct from business relationships. Ibid. at 140. But the players of a game may well be motivated to associate by a convergence of their individual interests—for example in stretching their wits, exercising their skill, being amused or gaining the various rewards of winning—so that, within my classification of community, their association might be best understood in terms of the ideal type of community of interest.

19. Weber, M., Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, trans. Fischoff, E. et al. , (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978) at 2425.Google Scholar

20. Anderson, B., Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, rev. ed. (London: Verso, 1991) at 141ff.Google Scholar

21. Cohen, supra note 10 at 15.

22. Ibid. at 9, 12.

23. Anderson, supra note 20 at 113–14.

24. Ibid. at 7, 141.

25. Kantorowitz, E. H., The King's Two Bodies: A Study in Mediaeval Political Theology (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1957) at 232ff.Google Scholar

26. See e. g. Matthew's Gospel, c. 5, verses 43–48.

27. Cohen, supra note 10 at 12.

28. Neumann, I. B., Collective Identity Formation: Self and Other in International Relations (EUI Working Paper RSC 95/36) (Florence: European University Institute, 1995) at 10ffGoogle Scholar; Lacey, supra note 7 at 112, 124.

29. Simmel, G., “The Stranger”, trans. Levine, D. N. in Simmel, G., On Individuality and Social Forms: Selected Writings (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1971) 143 at 144Google Scholar.

30. Welsh, J. M., A Peoples' Europe? European Citizenship and European Identity (EUI Working Paper ECS 93/2) (Florence: European University Institute, 1993) at 13ff.Google Scholar

31. Schmitt, C., The Concept of the Political, trans. Schwab, G. (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1976) at 26Google Scholar.

32. Hogg, M. A. & Abrams, D., Social Identifications: A Social Psychology of Intergroup Relations and Group Processes (London: Routledge, 1988) at 17Google Scholar.

33. Schutz, supra note 13 at 254–56.

34. Ibid. at 247.

35. Ibid. at 251–52.

36. Finnis, supra note 18 at 153.

37. In fact, Finnis later seems to de-emphasise this element in his specification. Ibid. at 156.

38. Cotterrell, R. B. M., Law's Community: Legal Theory in Sociological Perspective (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995) c. 15Google Scholar.

39. For a recent survey of the idea of trust as a topic in the literature of social theory, see Misztal, B. A., Trust in Modern Societies: The Search for the Bases of Social Order (Cambridge: Polity, 1996)Google Scholar.

40. Luhmann, N., “Trust: A Mechanism for the Reduction of Social Complexity” in Luhmann, N., ed., Trust and Power: Two Works, trans. Davis, H., Raffan, J. & Rooney, K. (Chichester: John Wiley, 1979) 4Google Scholar.

41. Barber, B., The Logic and Limits of Trust (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1983)Google Scholar.

42. Cotterrell, R. B. M., “Trusting in Law: Legal and Moral Concepts of Trust” (1993) 46 Current Legal Problems 75 at 9095CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43. Cohen is right to argue that conditions of community are “not reducible to a body of rules.” See Cohen, supra note 10 at 16. But informal rules about appropriate behaviour are surely an important expression of the understandings that constitute community.

44. Gerth, H. H. & Mills, C. W., eds., From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1948) at 78Google Scholar.

45. Lacey, supra note 7 at 135.

46. Anderson, supra note 20.

47. New government policies since the election of a Labour administration in May 1997 now seek actively to promote a degree of regional self-government within the United Kingdom.