Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-7qhmt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-27T15:57:47.130Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE BIRTH OF HOMO ŒCONOMICUS: THE METHODOLOGICAL DEBATE ON THE ECONOMIC AGENT FROM J. S. MILL TO V. PARETO

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 September 2022

Michele Bee
Affiliation:
Michele Bee: Cedeplar, Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais; Centre Walras-Pareto, Université de Lausanne, michelebee@cedeplar.ufmg.br
Maxime Desmarais-Tremblay
Affiliation:
Maxime Desmarais-Tremblay: Goldsmiths, University of London; Centre Walras-Pareto, Université de Lausanne, M.Desmarais-Tremblay@gold.ac.uk.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper proposes a genealogy of the concept of homo œconomicus as it emerged from the methodological debate on the economic agent of political economy. If John Stuart Mill gave birth to the economic man in his 1836 essay “On the Definition of Political Economy,” he certainly did not baptize him. The expression was introduced by Francis A. Walker after Mill passed away in the 1870s. Economic man acquired its Latin name of homo œconomicus under the pen of French Catholic economist Claudio Jannet in 1878. Yet, only at the end of the century did Maffeo Pantaleoni (1889) proudly reclaim homo œconomicus as a building block of pure economics. In reaction to the evolutionary hedonism of Pantaleoni, Vilfredo Pareto then cleansed the concept of homo œconomicus and realized the Millian project of an abstract science based on an economic agent.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the History of Economics Society

I. INTRODUCTION

References to homo œconomicus are ubiquitous in economics. For some, he is a defining icon of the science since the eighteenth century. Thorstein Veblen (Reference Veblen1899), for one, traced the origin of the economic manFootnote 1 to Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations. The Enlightenment certainly provided an important background to all nineteenth-century discussions of human nature. The search for a universalistic conception of human beings was a central concern of David Hume, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Adam Smith, Jeremy Bentham, and Immanuel Kant, among others.

Recent historiography identifies John Stuart Mill as the “creator” of the economic man (Blaug Reference Blaug1992, p. 55; Persky Reference Persky1995) and even of the homo œconomicus (Morgan Reference Morgan2006). Joseph Persky (Reference Persky1995) advances that the expression “homo œconomicus” was first used by the Italian economist Vilfredo Pareto in Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure1906, but Edward O’Boyle (Reference O’Boyle2009) found that it was used before by his Italian colleague Maffeo Pantaleoni in 1889. We may never be able to trace with absolute certainty the first usage of the expression “homo œconomicus.” Already in 1891, Pareto asked Pantaleoni, “Who was the first one to consider the homo œconomicus?” (Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, p. 97). Alas, Pantaleoni never responded to Pareto, or his response was destroyed.

In this paper, we provide a genealogy of the homo œconomicus. We argue that Mill can be attributed the paternity of the economic man because he provided the first extended discussion of the method of political economy centered on specific motivations of human agents. As John Neville Keynes (Reference Keynes1891, p. 10) remarked, Adam Smith was not particularly concerned with the “right method of economic inquiry.” If Mill gave birth to the economic man, he did not baptize him. Indeed, he never used the expression “economic man” himself.Footnote 2

This paper reconstructs the methodological debate on the economic agent from J. S. Mill to Vilfredo Pareto. With the exception of Claudio Jannet, a forgotten French economist who first used the expression “homo œconomicus,” we focus on economists who had a significant impact on the discipline in the nineteenth century. The authors we select form a coherent corpus, as the later ones explicitly refer to their forefathers. Although the twin expressions of “economic man” and “homo œconomicus” might have been coined independently, both referred to the methodological views enunciated by Mill. The expressions became synonymous with the Latin variant being at first more common in Italian and in French, whereas “economic man” was used by British and American economists. By providing extensive quotations, our conceptual genealogy aims at disentangling the features of the economic man that could be attributed to Mill from those that have been developed by the next generation of economists. Moreover, by situating the homo œconomicus within the ninteenth-century methodological debate in which he was born, our genealogy suggests how some contemporary critics of the homo œconomicus miss their target (see, for instance, Thaler Reference Thaler2016).

An economic theory inspired by Mill’s programmatic vision of the 1830s saw the light of day only in the 1890s. Mill enunciated methodological principles that broke away from classical economists, but he did not follow them strictly in his own political economy. In the middle decades of the century, economists commented on Mill’s programmatic vision of the science by painting the economic man under varying shades of color. In every case, the critical light under which they portrayed the economic man reflected their view of what was the appropriate method for the economic science.

Toward the end of the century, neoclassical economists like Francis Y. Edgeworth and Pantaleoni reclaimed the economic man to make it a positive figure of the science. Under the influence of Herbert Spencer, Pantaleoni wanted to demonstrate the realism of the homo œconomicus by arguing that the maximization of utility assumed in pure economics coincided with what he thought was the principal motive of real individuals, namely self-preservation. Pareto disagreed. Scientific economics could be based on an abstract subject only if it abandoned any reference to the motives of actions. For Pareto, a movement of gradual adaptation of ideas to the empirical reality characterized both the behavior of homo œconomicus and the experimental method of the pure economist. Pareto’s refinement of the concept of homo œconomicus was also intended as a response to the criticisms addressed to Mill’s project of an abstract science based on an economic subject. Reasoning at the margin did not radically change the conception of the economic man, but neoclassical economists were the first to make him into the ordinary hero of economic analysis.

II. FORGING THE CONCEPT: A QUESTION OF METHOD

John Stuart Mill and the Pursuit of Wealth in the 1836 Essay

John Stuart Mill was in his twenties when he drafted the essay that became the reference text on the methodology of economics for decades. It was probably intended as a rejoinder of the a priori method used by his Radical father, James Mill, against the attack of the Whig historian Thomas Babington Macaulay (Whitaker Reference Whitaker1975; Cook Reference Cook2009, p. 24). Macaulay (Reference Macaulay1829) did not think the formal a priori method used by utilitarians like James Mill could produce any meaningful result in the science of government. In his autobiography, John Stuart Mill confessed he was not happy with how his father addressed the “famous attack” of Macaulay. In his opinion, his father should have argued: “I was not writing a scientific treatise on politics. I was writing an article for parliamentary reform" (J. S. Mill [1873] Reference Mill2006, p. 165). Over time, Mill concluded that both Macaulay and his father were mistaken (J. S. Mill [1873] Reference Mill2006, p. 165).

In his essay “On the Definition of Political Economy; and on the Method of Investigation Proper to It,” first published in the London and Westminster Review in 1836, Mill argued that one should not confuse the “essentially distinct, though closely connected, ideas of science and art” (J. S. Mill [1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 312). In this, Mill was repeating the first sentence of Bentham’s “Manual of Political Economy” ([1800] Reference Bentham and Bowring1843), a text he had read and annotated with his father a few years earlier (Guidi Reference Guidi2010). However, Bentham was concerned with the art of government, not with pure science. Bentham formulated a utilitarian political philosophy to reform the law. In an essay of Reference Mill1863, Mill would engage with the utilitarian art of morals and legislation (on which, see Persky Reference Persky2016), but he did not make utility a central concept of the definition or the method of political economy. For the young Mill, political economy was “the science which treats of the production and distribution of wealth, so far as they depend upon the laws of human nature” ([1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 318). Mill borrowed Jean-Baptiste Say’s definition of political economy while removing the centrality of consumption.Footnote 3 Moreover, rather than focusing on commodities, Mill positioned man, with his “mental nature,” as the agent of political economy ([1836] Reference Mill2006, 319). To base a science of political economy on psychological laws was a radically new idea.

A passage of the essay will be the reference point for discussion on the method of economics for seventy years:

It does not treat of the whole of man’s nature as modified by the social state, nor of the whole conduct of man in society. It is concerned with him solely as a being who desires to possess wealth, and who is capable of judging of the comparative efficacy of means for obtaining that end. It predicts only such of the phenomena of the social state as take place in consequence of the pursuit of wealth. It makes entire abstraction of every other human passion or motive; except those which may be regarded as perpetually antagonising principles to the desire of wealth, namely, aversion to labour, and desire of the present enjoyment of costly indulgences. … Political Economy considers mankind as occupied solely in acquiring and consuming wealth; and aims at showing what is the course of action into which mankind, living in a state of society, would be impelled, if that motive, except in the degree in which it is checked by the two perpetual counter-motives above adverted to, were absolute ruler of all their actions. … The science then proceeds to investigate the laws which govern these several operations, under the supposition that man is a being who is determined, by the necessity of his nature, to prefer a greater portion of wealth to a smaller in all cases, without any other exception than that constituted by the two counter-motives already specified. Not that any political economist was ever so absurd as to suppose that mankind are really thus constituted, but because this is the mode in which science must necessarily proceed. ([1836] Reference Mill2006, pp. 321–322)

The central claim advanced by Mill in the previous quote was that political economy studied an abstract conception of man in the pursuit of wealth. Before John Stuart Mill, other economists had argued that wealth was the subject of political economy. The starting point of James Mill’s essay “Government” was to assume that “the actions of men are governed by their wills, and their wills by their desires: That their desires are directed to pleasure and relief from pain as ends, and to wealth and power as the principal means” (Reference Mill1820). Then, in his Introductory Lecture on Political Economy delivered at Oxford University in 1826, Nassau Senior argued that the theoretical branch of political economy rested on a few self-evident propositions such as “every person is desirous to obtain, with as little sacrifice as possible, as much as possible of the articles of wealth” (Senior Reference Senior1827, p. 35).

Contrary to what his father argued for the science of government, for John Stuart Mill, in political economy there was no need to go back to the primitive desire for pleasure and the aversion of pain. The starting assumption was the pursuit of wealth, and individuals were characterized by their ability to judge “the comparative efficacy of means for obtaining that end” (Mill [1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 321; our emphasis). Whereas Senior took the desire for wealth as universal and evident from scrutinizing one’s consciousness, for the young Mill it was only a simplifying assumption in an attempt to build a science.

Political economy studied wealth, and its main protagonist was man as a wealth-seeking creature. Wealth required effort and it could be accumulated. Yet, John Stuart Mill ([1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 314) did not wish to restrict the definition of wealth to material objects: wealth could be any agreeable object of desire limited in quantity.Footnote 4

In order to understand how mankind would act in real economic settings where a large set of motives are at work, the student of political economy must first understand mankind’s behavior under the influence of one motive at a time. In the 1830s, Mill stated that political economy was an abstract science that followed the a priori method. Like geometry, it reasoned deductively from an assumed hypothesis:

Geometry presupposes an arbitrary definition of a line, ‘that which has length but not breadth.’ Just in the same manner does Political Economy presuppose an arbitrary definition of man, as a being who invariably does that by which he may obtain the greatest amount of necessaries, conveniences, and luxuries, with the smallest quantity of labour and physical self-denial. ([1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 326).

In both cases, the conclusions of the scientist are true only in the abstract ([1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 326). The domain of political economy is restricted to the parts of human life for which wealth, broadly conceived, is the object. Yet, even within this realm, when the laws of political economy are applied in a particular case, it is “necessary to take into account all the individual circumstances of that case” ([1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 330). When the “laws of the mind” deduced in political economy do not correspond to the observed phenomena, it does not mean that they are false, or that they admit exceptions, but rather that a countervailing tendency was at play in the particular case under study. Likewise, in mechanics, friction is not an exception to the law of gravity but a disturbing cause that counteracts the tendency of heavy bodies to fall ([1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 337).

A Broader Scope in Mill’s Logic and PPE

Following Auguste Comte, Mill recast political economy as a branch of the social science, also known as sociology. Comte did not think much of the scientific pretenses of political economists. In the last volume of his Cours de philosophie positive, he argued that all the components of social phenomena were mutually interconnected and could not be studied separately (Comte Reference Comte1839, p. 272). Despite his great admiration for Comte’s intellectual enterprise, Mill reaffirmed in his System of Logic ([1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006) the separateness of political economy based on the different set of causes that could be isolated from the other causes at work in complex social phenomena. Moreover, he argued that social science followed the “concrete deductive method.” Also known as the “direct deductive method,” it was applicable to complex phenomena, like those studied by astronomy, that could not be understood merely by direct observation (Mill [1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006, pp. 454, 462). It consisted of three steps: induction, ratiocination, and verification. The scientist would start from laws of nature, obtained through induction, then deduce tendency laws, before “collating the conclusion of the ratiocination with the concrete phenomena themselves” ([1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006, p. 896). In the distinct branch of political economy, however, Mill considered that direct verification of the theory was not possible because of the absence of empirical laws generalized from specific cases and the impossibility of controlled experiments ([1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006, p. 908).Footnote 5

Despite this reframing of the method of political economy within a broader philosophy of science, Mill still quoted at length the same passage from his 1836 essay. Political economy dealt with phenomena “in which the immediately determining causes are principally those which act through the desire of wealth, in which the psychological law mainly concerned is the familiar one, that a greater gain is preferred to a smaller” (Mill [1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006, p. 901). This desire for a greater gain operated both in the sphere of production and in the sphere of distribution.

However, Mill had already remarked in 1836 that political economy studied “man’s nature as modified by the social state” (Mill [1836] Reference Mill2006, p. 321). This qualification of the domain of political economy grew into an important line of defense of mainstream economists against their critics (more below). In his Logic, Mill remarked that even if the method was universal, “the conclusions of the science, being all adapted to a society thus constituted, require to be revised whenever they are applied to any other” ([1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006, p. 903). This also meant that his deductive method for political economy was better adapted to a stable state of society.

When he came to write his Principles, Mill wanted to write a broad treatise like Smith’s Wealth of Nations. As the title stated, the Principles of Political Economy with Some of Their Applications to Social Philosophy ([1848] Reference Mill2006) “was not a book merely of abstract science, but also of application, and treated Political Economy not as a thing by itself, but as a fragment of a greater whole; a branch of Social Philosophy, so interlinked with all the other branches, that its conclusions, even in its own peculiar province, are only true conditionally” (Mill [1873] 2006, p. 242). Most commentators of Mill, starting from Nassau Senior (Reference Senior1848, p. 304), noted the discrepancy between the programmatic essay with its narrow conception of the individual and strict method, and the broad scope of the Principles. Footnote 6

In the middle decades of the nineteenth century, political economy appeared as a mature and successful science in the eyes of the British public. The prosperity that followed the repeal of the Corn Laws boosted the economists’ confidence in their outlook. Mill ([1848b] Reference Mill2006, p. 456) had famously remarked in his Principles that “happily, there is nothing in the laws of Value which remains for the present or any future writer to clear up.” John Elliot Cairnes restated the Millian methodological creed in his Character and Logic Method of Political Economy in Reference Cairnes1857.

The Mental Calculus

Mill had tried to salvage the core propositions of Ricardian theory and policy from its criticisms by recasting them in a rigorous scientific foundation, but in the process, he broke away from classical political economy by putting the individual at the center of a methodological program. When we study the whole range of his writing, we can see in Mill a commitment to individual agency and an understanding of how societies can progress by institutional design (Schabas Reference Schabas2005, p. 126; Fontana Reference Fontana1986). In the province of political economy narrowly conceived, Mill’s focus of the human “mental nature” paved the way for the psychological turn in the second half of the century (Schabas Reference Schabas2005, p. 133).

William Stanley Jevons combined Bentham’s political calculus of pleasure and pain with Mill’s search for economic laws based on individual psychology. In the first sketch of his “Mathematical Theory of Political Economy,” presented in Reference Jevons1862, Jevons argued, “A true theory of economy can only be attained by going back to the great springs of human action—the feelings of pleasure and pain” (p. 158). Yet, echoing Mill’s methodological prescriptions, Jevons also remarked that “economy does not treat of all human motives. There are motives nearly always present with us, arising from conscience, compassion, or from some moral or religious source, which economy cannot and does not pretend to treat. These will remain to us as outstanding and disturbing forces; they must be treated, if at all, by other appropriate branches of knowledge” (Jevons Reference Jevons1866, p. 282).

Within a few years, Jevons had produced a theory that rid economics of “the cost of production doctrine of value, the natural rate of wages, and other misleading or false Ricardian doctrines” (Jevons [1879] Reference Jevons2013, p. ixvii). With respect to preceding English theories of political economy, it’s fair to say that—together with Carl Menger and Léon Walras—Jevons instigated a “Marginal Revolution” (Hutchison Reference Hutchison1978, p. 66ff.). He broke new ground particularly on the use of mathematics (Schabas Reference Schabas1990). Nonetheless, even if he reasoned differently and arrived at different results, Jevons’s individualistic starting point of economic inquiry was in continuity with Mill (De Marchi Reference De Marchi1972).

However, Mill’s wealth-seeking man was a simplifying fiction, whereas Jevons’s Reference Jevons1871 “mechanics of human interest” applied indiscriminately to “persons” even though he restricted his investigation to a limited domain of wants.Footnote 7 More importantly, Mill relied only on a mechanistic analogy to describe the scientific method, whereas Jevons saw mechanics in the head of individuals. Jevon’s early interest in the working of abacuses led him to conceptualize the human psyche as operating like a counting machine and to describe human behavior with the same logic (Maas Reference Maas1999). Although Jevons acknowledged that a person’s mind is “inscrutable” to another person, the natural laws of the mind, such as “that every person will choose the greater apparent good,” would be observed at the aggregate level of a nation (Jevons Reference Jevons1871, pp. 21–24). So, even though he did not use the expression “economic man” himself, Jevons prepared the way for the neoclassical reappropriation of the concept by Edgeworth, Pantaleoni, and Pareto in the last two decades of the century (see section IV below). In the meantime, the abstract and deductive approach advocated by Mill and Jevons for political economy had been the subject of various criticisms.

III. CRITICIZING THE CONCEPT: THE EMERGENCE OF THE EXPRESSION

Baptizing the Economic Man

The expressions “economic man” and “homo œconomicus” emerged in the 1870s in critical discussions of English political economy. The first English occurrence of the expression of “economic man” appeared in a review of Cairnes’s Some Leading Principles of Political Economy published in Reference Walker1874 by the American economist Francis Amasa Walker. He used the opportunity of his review to quote and mildly criticize the famous passage from Mill’s [1836] Reference Mill2006 essay: “Mr. Mill does not in his later writings abide by his own definition of the economic man, but generally assumes other ‘motives and passions’ than those with which alone, he says, political economy is concerned” (Walker Reference Walker1874, p. 320). Walker did not claim the paternity of a new concept and assumed that the readers of The Nation would understand his personification of Mill’s assumptions regarding human nature as studied in political economy. Two years later, Walker used again the expression “economic” man in The Wages Question.

In 1872, a group of German social reformers had created an association to promote scientific research and policies to address the social question (Hagemann Reference Hagemann, Augello and Marco2001). In a speech given at one annual meeting of the Verein für Socialpolitik, the secretary of the association, Adolf Held, directly attacked the “old” English political economy. In the words of the Catholic professor: “The new school demands a complete abandonment of the endeavor to set up natural laws of universal application, … It demands, above all, the abandonment of the premise that man in his economic action is influenced only by egoism. … It demands that the economic man [Wirtshaftende Mensch] shall be considered a member of an organized society (Held Reference Held1877, p. 164; also cited by von Philippovich Reference Philippovich1891, p. 224). Held’s plea for a policy-oriented social and historical political economy directly attacked what he perceived to be the central tenets of the classical methodology defended by Mill: the universalism of economic laws, the deductive method, and the selfish economic man isolated from institutions. It is worth noting that Mill never claimed that the wealth-seeking man assumed in political economy was selfish. By characterizing the economic man as selfish, critics of political economy amalgamated Mill and his followers with the loathed “selfish system” attributed to Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Mandeville.Footnote 8

In Victorian England, Thomas Carlyle and John Ruskin attacked political economy, but they did not seem to refer precisely to the economic man. Finer methodological criticisms were formulated by the Irish economists Cliffe Leslie and later by John Ingram, both of them influenced by Auguste Comte, Wilhelm Roscher, and Henry Maine (Hutchison Reference Hutchison1978, p. 78; Cook and Tribe Reference Cook, Tribe, Faccarello and Kurz2016, p. 305). In an essay first published in 1875, Leslie argued that economists throughout Europe could be roughly divided according to the methodological conception they held, either English or German (Leslie Reference Leslie, Ingram and Bastable1888, p. 83). Ingram (Reference Ingram1878) brought this methodological analysis further. He acknowledged that Mill and Cairnes had refined the methodology of orthodox political economy. Whereas David Ricardo assumed he was “dealing with human beings as they actually exist,” Mill and Cairnes recognized that the “economic man” was based on “unreal assumptions” (Ingram Reference Ingram1885, p. 381). For Ingram, the future belonged to the German historical approach and the sociology of Comte. The “radical vice” of unscientific orthodox economics lay “in the too individual and subjective aspect under which it has been treated” (Ingram Reference Ingram1885, p. 400). The individualistic perspective had to be subordinated to an organic vision of society. The fact that some English-writing authors such as Leslie and Ingram, and later Arnold Toynbee and William Cunningham, defended the historical method against the deductive abstractness of Ricardo, Mill, and their followers led some to speak of an “English Methodenstreit” (Koot Reference Koot1987).

In his introductory lecture at University College London in 1876, Jevons observed that political economy was in an “almost chaotic” state. He agreed with Leslie that history was relevant, but he posited it belonged to the “concrete part” of the science. Applying Spencer’s evolutionary idea to the science itself, Jevons argued for the “differentiation” of the branches of political economy (Jevons Reference Jevons1876, pp. 623–624). Properly reformed, the “abstract” branch of mathematical “economics” could follow a deductive method (Jevons [1879] Reference Jevons2013, p. xxxvii). In his Reference Jevons1879 review of the second edition of Jevon’s Theory, Leslie responded to Jevons that historical analysis should be at the heart of political economy, not relegated to another sociological branch (Leslie Reference Leslie, Ingram and Bastable1888, p. 66). While Leslie was sympathetic to Jevons’s attack on Ricardian economics, and particularly on Cairnes’s doctrinal synthesis of it, he nonetheless criticized Jevons for his overreliance on the deductive method (Leslie Reference Leslie, Ingram and Bastable1888, p. 197).

The Nebulous Beginning of Homo Œconomicus

If the economic man acquired its English name in the context of the mild criticism that Walker addressed to Mill in Reference Walker1874, the Latin variant of homo œconomicus first appeared in the harsher criticism made by French Catholic economist Claudio Jannet in Reference Jannet1878. Born in 1844, Jannet received a doctorate in law from the University of Aix in 1867 and later came under the influence of the French sociologist Frédéric Le Play. Jannet became the first professor of political economy at the Université Catholique de Paris in 1877. While he is a completely forgotten figure of the history of economic thought, in the eponymous entry of the Dictionary of Political Economy, it was said that “Jannet was probably the most scholarly and certainly one of the best and most widely informed of the French economists of his generation” (Castelot Reference Castelot and Palgrave1896, p. 472; Reference Castelot1894). There is no evidence that Jannet knew about Walker’s work in the 1870s, and thus it is possible he had not encountered the expression “economic man,” but he was certainly very familiar with Mill’s work and the methodological debates in political economy.

Jannet defended a peculiar form of Social Catholicism.Footnote 9 He supported freedom of contract and free trade, and he was grateful to liberal economists for having combated socialism. Even if he was sympathetic to the historical inclination of Wilhelm Roscher, he vigorously disapproved of the interventionist policies advocated by the Socialists of the Chair, such as Adolf Held and Adolph Wagner, on the basis of their “fake science.” History was not a tool for social transformation, but it could reveal the natural organization of societies. For Jannet, the laws of political economy were universal because they were given by God.

With Comte, Jannet denied the separateness of political economy. Social science was one and had to study the whole of mankind whose goal is happiness. English political economy took humanity out of the equation: “The influence of national life, that of the family, the connection of men to places, custom, the action of the idea of right [droit] and the sentiments of social benevolence are eliminated” (Jannet Reference Jannet1878, p. 1067). Writing a long survey of the state of the social science in the Catholic periodical Le Correspondant, Jannet dismissed the caricatural conceptions of man given by the “old school,” which tried to reduce man either to “algebraic equations” or to a statistical “homme moyen”—a probable reference to the work of Adolf Quetelet. Jannet asserted: “In reality, this sort of homo economicus is like Rousseau’s natural man: it never existed!” (Jannet Reference Jannet1878, p. 1067).Footnote 10 For Jannet, the natural goodness of man assumed by Rousseau was a false dogma of the French Revolution. At the opposite end, neither could the individualistic and aggressive nature of individuals postulated by Hobbes, “Homo Homini Lupus,” serve as a foundation for a true science compatible with Christian teaching (Jannet et al. Reference Jannet, Stiegler, Gide and Passy1890, p. 30). Rather, the necessary starting point of social science should be the “constant action of the original sin,” as Frédéric Le Play had observed in his studies (Jannet Reference Jannet1878, p. 1074). This explained the necessity of domestic authority, of religion to fight vice, and of the duty of wealth towards members of the lower classes. Thus, “the subject of economic observation should be the family and not the isolated individual” (Jannet Reference Jannet1878, p. 1074).Footnote 11

In his Groundwork of Economics published in Reference Devas1883, Charles S. Devas, a lecturer in political economy in a Catholic college near London, probably made the only direct reference to Jannet’s conceptual innovation. Referring to the above passage in Jannet’s article and paraphrasing it, but without attributing to him the paternity of the expression, Devas denounced the English economists of the first half of the nineteenth century who “dressed up a ridiculous homo oeconomicus, just as in political science Rousseau had dressed up a ridiculous homme de la nature” (Devas Reference Devas1883, p. 43). For Devas, these excesses had led to an agnostic historical reaction that denied the centrality of “good will” and “revelation” in guiding men’s moral behavior in society.

Jannet and Devas addressed a methodological criticism to English political economy. Like some German economists with similar conservative political views, they were probably as upset as those economists, if not more, by the liberal assumptions of English political economy.

Conciliatory Approaches

In the middle of the decade, the business journalist Walter Bagehot wrote the “Postulates of English Political Economy.” Bagehot did not use the expression “economic man.” He defended the deductive and abstract method of political economy as appropriate to analyze “a society of grown-up competitive commerce” ([1876] Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 17). Mill would probably have agreed. After all, he had criticized Bentham for offering a general social philosophy that was in fact applicable to “organizing and regulating the merely business part of the social arrangements” (Mill [1838] Reference Mill2006, p. 99).Footnote 12 For Bagehot, only in England could one talk of non-wealth-seeking motivations in terms of “frictions” (Bagehot [1876] Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 17). It was “absurd” to try to apply the conclusions of the abstract political economy to less developed nations (Bagehot Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 80). Since commercial activities had changed the nature of men, Bagehot did not see a contradiction between the abstract and the deductive methods (Bagehot [1876] Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 15). The “first men,” just like the “present savage men,” “did not conform to the standard of economical man; the being of reality was not the being of the hypothesis” (Bagehot Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 83). In particular, they could not appreciate the commodities called “wealth”: “The desire, so strong in civilised man, for wealth, has been excited in him by the experience of ages, and has been transmitted to him by inheritance” (Bagehot [1876] Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 15). Just as political economy takes a “one-sided view of man,” it also “takes an abstract one-sided view of wealth” (Bagehot Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 81). Political economy takes human wants as given and does not judge of the goodness of articles of wealth for human life, whether it is a beer or a book of religion. And yet, this conceptualization of wealth, inseparable from the definition of political economy and its method, was not relevant to study non-commercial societies (Bagehot Reference Bagehot and Hutton1880, p. 80). Historical methods were thus useful to understand the evolution of societies toward the commercial stage of economic men. After Charles Darwin and Herbert Spencer, many economists like Bagehot, who defended the abstract method of political economy centered on the economic man, also felt the need to relativize the context of its applicability.

Even if very few thinkers were directly influenced and bought into the whole set of Darwin’s ideas, most held to a general view that species and societies evolve through time (Hull Reference Hull, Creath and Maienschein2000, p. 48). Thus, what separated the early nineteenth-century representation of man from its late-century variants was the role of history and the theory of evolution that had to be accounted for in the explanation of social phenomena (see Claeys Reference Claeys and Claeys2019).

While the debate between induction and deduction certainly spilled over countless pages throughout the nineteenth century, attempts to establish an uncontestable methodological canon led some economists to compromise. When academic economists tried to solidify a corpus of principles of economics in the 1880s, they attempted to respond to these criticisms while presenting a unified vision of the science. Commenting again on the famous passage from Mill, Walker—who, in the meantime, had become president of the American Statistical Association—remarked in his treatise on Political Economy that “we have here all the elements of the economic man” (Walker Reference Walker1883, p. 16). Using a bodily metaphor, Walker argued that historical and social knowledge could be added on top of the abstract construction: “Such a scheme should constitute the skeleton of all economical reasoning; but upon this ghastly framework should be imposed the flesh and blood of an actual, vital Political Economy, which takes account of men and societies as they are, with all their sympathies, apathies, and antipathies; with every organ developed, as in life” (Walker Reference Walker1883, p. 18).

From his chair of moral philosophy at Cambridge, Henry Sidgwick reflected upon the evolution of political economy over the nineteenth century. Sidgwick wrote his Principles of Political Economy to restate the core of the science while acknowledging important points recently made by critics (Sidgwick Reference Sidgwick1883, p. 7). He used the concept of “economic man” a few times in the Principles, defining it as the characteristic of men “always seeking to obtain for the commodity that they exchange the largest real return that they know to be obtainable taking all kinds of gain and loss into account” (Sidgwick Reference Sidgwick1883, p. 391). Sidgwick explained the discrepancy between this behavior and what is observed in society at large by the effect of “custom,” or what we would today call “social norms.” It is very likely that Sidgwick borrowed the expression “economic man” from Walker since he quoted his Wages Question (Reference Walker1876) many times.

The other Cambridge professor, Alfred Marshall, also positioned himself as a conciliatory figure in the methodological debate. In the 1880s, Alfred Marshall referred explicitly to Walker’s “admirable Political Economy” as well as to Sidgwick’s Principles of Political Economy. Highly influenced by evolutionism and German philosophy of history, Marshall adopted an ecumenical approach: “induction and deduction go hand in hand” (Reference Marshall1890, ch. v). Comte and Roscher were right when they claimed that other methods were useful, but they were wrong when they denied the usefulness of deductions, since facts alone were silent (Marshall Reference Marshall1885, p. 39; Reference Marshall1890, p. 74). On the other side, contrary to what was often claimed, Ricardo and his followers were not establishing universal truths but only developing “machinery to aid us in reasoning,” an “engine for the discovery of concrete truth” (Marshall Reference Marshall1885, p. 22).

Marshall defended John Stuart Mill, at the cost of turning the economic man on his head.Footnote 13 He thought that Mill’s passage on the economic man from his 1836 essay had been misunderstood: “It is an English habit to leave much to be supplied by the common sense of the reader” (Marshall Reference Marshall1890, p. 80n1). Marshall went as far as arguing that when economists had assumed a selfish economic man, “they did not express their meaning exactly” (Reference Marshall1885, p. 27; Reference Marshall1890, p. 78). In his view, the economic man is not selfish, since wealth is primarily pursued for the benefit of the family: “he is generally hard at work saving capital chiefly for the benefit of others” (Reference Marshall1885, p. 28). Marshall argued that economists dealt with individuals of flesh and blood. In the end, the wealth-seeking man was only a convenient assumption because it led to actions that were measurable in monetary terms. It is no surprise then that Marshall defined economics as “the study of man’s action in the ordinary business of life” (Reference Marshall1890, p. 1). His conception of the economic man matched his definition of economics.

Referring to all the economists we have discussed so far was John Neville Keynes’s The Scope and Method of Political Economy (Reference Keynes1891), a 350-page synthesis of the methodological debates on political economy in the nineteenth century.Footnote 14 Like Marshall, Neville Keynes adopted a conciliatory tone (Blaug Reference Blaug1992, p. 52). Neville Keynes supported the intimate connection between wealth and economics conceived as an abstract science, but he argued that the desire for wealth was only a shorthand for the desire to acquire “purchasing power” to satisfy one’s various wants (Blaug Reference Blaug1992, p. 117). In that perspective, economic man was conceived as acting toward his “own material advantage and the advantage of those immediately dependent upon [him]” (Blaug Reference Blaug1992, p. 115). Gone was the view of economic man as a greedy creature. In Neville Keynes’s view, the economic man was a real and enlightened self-interested man. He might wish to increase his fortune to care for his children or to give to charitable causes. Thus, from his utilitarian perspective, both egoism and altruism were compatible with a wealth-seeking vision of human beings.

IV. THE TURNING POINT: A VINDICATION OF THE EXPRESSION

Positive Views on Economic Man and Homo Œconomicus

By the 1880s, Jevonian mathematical economics had taken a firm hold in Britain (Schabas Reference Schabas1990, ch. 6). The next generation of neoclassical economists proudly reclaimed the economic man as the ordinary hero of their theories. Jevons’s conception of man was referred to as “a pleasure machine” by his devoted disciple, Edgeworth. In Mathematical Psychics (Reference Edgeworth1881, p. 55n1), Edgeworth used the expression only once in a footnote referring to Mill’s Logic and to Walker’s Wages. Footnote 15

Edgeworth later used the expression “economic man” to capture the essence of economics in some of the 115 entries he wrote for Robert H. I. Palgrave’s Dictionary of Political Economy (see Barbé Reference Barbé and Black2010, p. 173). The Dictionary also contained an entry on “economic man” written by the Cambridge logician and lecturer in psychology and moral sciences William Ernest Johnson. He defined the economic man as “a more or less imaginary being postulated for theoretical purposes by abstract political economy” and moved by his “material interests” (Johnson Reference Johnson and Palgrave1894, p. 676). In the entries “Functions,” “Gossen,” “Margin,” “Maximum Satisfaction,” and “Total Utility,” Edgeworth painted a portrait of the economic man more in line with the new mathematical economics. For instance, in the entry “Functions,” Edgeworth wrote: “It has been well said that every theory in economics may be regarded as the solution of a problem in the calculus of maxima and minima: to obtain the greatest satisfaction with the least effort and sacrifice being the aim of the economic man. The language of that calculus is the mother tongue of abstract economics” (Reference Palgrave1896). For Edgeworth, the “advantage” of the economic man is represented by a “function of several variables.” He strives to attain “maximum satisfaction,” to maximize his “net total utility” (Reference Palgrave1896; Reference Palgrave1899). Thus, at the turn of the century, the mathematical imagination of Jevons and Edgeworth had created an economic man very close to the modern microeconomics textbook account of the universal utility maximizing agent. The economic man was no longer merely attracted to wealth as Mill had postulated, and neither was he identified with the typical English businessman as Bagehot had argued.

In Principii di economia pura (Reference Pantaleoni1889), Maffeo Pantaleoni adopted the Latin expression of homo œconomicus in a constructive way.Footnote 16 For the first time, the expression was not used merely for criticizing English political economy but to explicitly characterize the subject of pure economics, just as Edgeworth would do a few years later in Palgrave’s Dictionary. Footnote 17

Pantaleoni devoted the first chapter of his Principii to the subject matter of the economic science. He described the specific characteristic of the homo œconomicus in terms of the “hedonic hypothesis,” that is, the desire “to obtain a given result with the smallest comparative means; or, conversely, to obtain any maximum result with any given means” (Reference Pantaleoni1889; Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 5).Footnote 18 In his view, it was possible to obtain true economic deductions from the hedonistic hypothesis, and thus to offer accurate practical prescriptions, since the hedonistic hypothesis was realistic. Pantaleoni found inspiration for his realism in Herbert Spencer’s reading of Darwin’s principle of natural selection, an idea that figured prominently in his thought (Mosca Reference Mosca2015; Sunna and Mosca Reference Sunna and Mosca2017). In Pantaleoni’s view, the hedonistic hypothesis was realistic because the ends of homo œconomicus necessarily coincided with the self-preservation of the individual and the species.

In his demonstration of the reality of homo œconomicus, Pantaleoni quoted Spencer’s Data of Ethics (Reference Spencer1874): “Sentient existence can evolve only on condition that pleasure-giving acts are life-sustaining acts” (Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 15). Pantaleoni argued that natural selection worked “through the elimination of individuals for whom life-sustaining acts [were] not productive of pleasure, and in whom acts prejudicial to life occasion no pain” (Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 16). Only those who acted like a homo œconomicus could survive. In this sense, homo œconomicus represented the empirical reality, if not already in the present, surely in the future. Behavioral discrepancies were destined to be eliminated by natural selection. He classified these discrepancies as “anti-economic” behaviors, like the acts of the anchorite, the preference for a lower remuneration, or the many forms of altruism (Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 19). Yet, there could also be discrepancies between individual egoism and the “tribal egoism,” that is, self-preservation of the species (Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 20). In this case, natural selection would again eliminate the discrepancy, since only species presenting a concordance between individual egoism and tribal egoism could survive.Footnote 19

The association of the homo œconomicus with the idea of preservation of the species suggests that Pantaleoni could have borrowed this Latin expression from the idea of Homo sapiens. Indeed, just before introducing the concept of homo œconomicus in his Principii, Pantaleoni quoted Patrick Geddes’s An Analysis of the Principles of Economics (Reference Geddes1885). In this book, Geddes discussed Darwin’s principle of natural selection and used the expression “Homo” for the human species.Footnote 20 Geddes referred to the works of Walker—who was also himself influenced by Darwin and Spencer (see Hodgson Reference Hodgson1992)—and used the expression “economic man,” but never “homo œconomicus.” It is plausible that Pantaleoni made the connection. In any case, Pantaleoni read the English expression of “economic man” in Walker, since he quoted his different works multiple times in the Principii. It is not clear, though, if Pantaleoni knew of Jannet’s work before writing his Principii. He would, at least, learn of Jannet’s Le capital, la spéculation et la finance au XXe siècle in 1892 when Pareto wrote a positive review of it for the Giornale degli economisti.

Cleansing the Concept: From Motives to Logic

The refinement of the concept of homo œconomicus, so proudly claimed by Pantaleoni, characterized the intellectual path of Vilfredo Pareto. On 4 July 1891, Pareto wrote to Pantaleoni that he had just met Jannet in Paris, a “very cultivated person” whose reasoning, however, seemed to be grounded on wrong “bases” (Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, p. 42).Footnote 21 In fact, Pareto met Jannet just after he finished reading Pantaleoni’s Principii. Four days later, Pareto wrote to Pantaleoni many critical comments on his book, most of them about the concept of homo œconomicus (Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, p. 43–49). Like Jannet, who had argued that neither homo economicus nor Rousseau’s natural man ever existed, Pareto wrote to Pantaleoni that the hedonistic homo œconomicus of political economy did “not exist in nature” (Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, p. 47). Although, contrary to Jannet, Pareto did not reject the abstract concept. He wanted to refine it. Pareto focused his criticisms on the method. When pure economics failed to describe reality, rather than invoking “anti-economic” motives of real individuals as Pantaleoni did, the homo œconomicus could be revised. This revision would require constant reference to the “naked experimental facts,” knowing that the amended hypothesis, even in the best case, would still remain an approximation of reality (Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, p. 49). For Pareto, pure economists should abandon any temptation to provide practical prescription based directly on abstract deductions (see Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, pp. 45–48).

Pareto outlined in this letter the steps that would characterize his intellectual path in the refinement of the concept of homo œconomicus. First, he compared pure economics to rational mechanics, arguing that rational mechanics did not introduce anti-mechanic criteria to explain the elasticity of matter but rather complemented it with a theory of elasticity (Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, pp. 46–47). Second, he found problems in the description of the economic motive. If pure economics led to deductions that were not observed, as Pantaleoni admitted, this could be due to a misguided conceptualization of economic motives in terms of utility. For example, contrary to what was assumed in pure economics, real individuals engaging in exchange could hardly calculate final degrees of utility before making their choices (pp. 47–49). They were probably acting “more out of habit than reasoning” (p. 48). This problem was linked to Pareto’s more fundamental criticism about the means–end relationship. Third, he argued that it was very hard to assume that the actions of real individuals would “only follow from their conscious will [deliberato volere]” (p. 48). Pure economics was implicitly assuming that real individuals were able to adapt their means to their ends, but this hypothesis had to be made explicit.

Pareto wrote this letter to Pantaleoni while he was finishing his article “Lasciate fare, lasciate passare” (Reference Pareto1891) for the Giornale degli Economisti. In this paper he developed the analogy between pure economics and rational mechanics as he would do in his Considerations on the Fundamental Principles of Pure Political Economy ([1892–93] Reference Pareto, Marchionatti and Mornati2007).Footnote 22 According to Pareto, abstraction was necessary for the scientific analysis of simple and artificially isolated aspects of reality, but before providing practical prescriptions, a synthesis of all these aspects of reality was needed (see Guala Reference Guala1998; McLure Reference McLure2001, pp. 21–27). Furthermore, since the phenomenon studied by science was always an ideal phenomenon—which could never coincide identically with reality—it was necessary to compare deductions with experience as often as possible (Pareto [Reference Pareto1892–93] Reference Pareto, Marchionatti and Mornati2007, pp. 7–8).Footnote 23

First, Pareto tried to clarify the concept of utility by introducing the concept of “ophelimity.” In his Cours d’économie politique (Reference Pareto1896), he pointed to the difference between the objective utility that parents see in a medicine for their child and the subjective utility felt by the child, who dislikes the medicine. Then, he made a distinction between subjective utility and ophelimity, understood as the capacity of something to satisfy needs or desires. The ascetics see utility in the annihilation of any satisfaction of needs and desires; their subjective utility therefore is not their ophelimity but rather the annihilation of any ophelimity (Pareto Reference Pareto1896, p. 6). Utility was economic, moral, or ethical, when it provided for the social aggregate material well-being, the development of more perfect morals, or ethical development, respectively. Ophelimity was economic, moral, or ethical, when it satisfied needs and desires of the individual of a material, moral, or ethical kind, regardless of whether they were useful (see McLure Reference McLure2007, pp. 26–27).Footnote 24 In Pareto’s Cours, the homo œconomicus was a hedonist who maximized pleasure and minimized pain by responding solely to the forces of economic ophelimity.

Over the years, however, Pareto emancipated himself from ophelimity by assuming that homo œconomicus had preferences whose origins need not to be investigated from an economic point of view. Pareto made it easier for economics to escape from psychology by economizing on the mental laws postulated by Jevons and Mill.Footnote 25 Once Pareto had discarded the necessity of inquiring into the motives of actions, he turned his attention to the relation between ends and means, the other issue he had raised in his 1891 letter to Pantaleoni. Between 1898 and 1900, by abandoning the idea of hedonism, Pareto reached his own definition of homo œconomicus. We find the clearest exposition of his new conception in the Summary of Some Chapters of a New Treatise of Pure Economics of Prof. Pareto,” a first draft of his Manual, published in the Giornale degli Economisti in 1900.

The “Summary” opened with a question of method, suggesting that deductions and inductions could complement each other with the aim of “cementing the fact to the idea” (Pareto [1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 455). Following this method, premises and deductions should be confirmed by experimental observations. In case of a discrepancy, the initial hypothesis would be modified since only premises approximating reality could generate deductions approximating reality. The “Summary” started with “the fact of choice,” a “direct outcome of experience” that did not need to be analyzing “entities such as the final degree of utility, rareté, or ophelimity, whose capability of being measured [was] a matter of controversy” ([1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 453). Pareto argued: “The fact that there can be choices relieves us from having to examine the motives” ([1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 457). We do not have to assume that “the blows afford [the ascetic] greater pleasure than a good dinner”; we just need to assume that he voluntarily “prefers ten strokes to the good dinner” ([1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 457–458). With a direct reference to Edgeworth’s idea of “pleasure machine,” Pareto argued that homo œconomicus was just a choice machine:

The abstraction based on the subject is the origin of what is called homo œconomicus. This is an abstract being which retains only a small number of the characteristics of men in the real world. If we adopt the point of view that pleasure is a quantity, man is reduced to a pleasure machine which seeks to procure the greatest sum total of pleasure on every occasion. If we look at the matter from the point of view of one of the choices, homo œconomicus becomes a machine to affect those choices, and this machine, given the circumstances, constantly makes the same. ([1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 463)

Homo œconomicus was an abstract agent making choices. Mill ([1836] Reference Mill2006) had postulated that the economic subject could judge the “comparative efficacy of means” to obtain wealth. For Pareto, what mattered was not the motives of the individuals but that they adopted actions that “tend logically to an end”—whatever these could be—and “change logically, with changing circumstances” (Pareto [1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 456). In this way, economists would have a science “which studies in what way the means are linked to the end, that is, to the choice carried out by the individual” ([1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 456).

The “Summary” was a turning point in Pareto’s reflection (see Bruni and Guala Reference Bruni and Guala2001; Bruni Reference Bruni2013), especially in his attempt to respond to the criticisms on the measurability of utility, pleasure, and ophelimity (Moscati Reference Moscati2018, pp. 79–116). Yet, his answers constituted only a step in the process of refinement of the concept of homo œconomicus. The “Summary” represented above all Pareto’s answers to the criticisms of the concept of homo œconomicus and to the method of pure economics that he had addressed to Pantaleoni in 1891. This accomplishment was the result of Pareto’s adoption of the “experimental method,” which he associated with the “deductive-concrete” method of Mill’s System of Logic, a work he had studied meticulously in his youth (see Mornati Reference Mornati2018, pp. 140–148; Marchionatti and Gambino Reference Marchionatti and Gambino1997).Footnote 26 The methodological explanation Pareto gave in the “Summary” of pure economics as an experimental science implicitly described his own intellectual development, situating himself in a historical process that started with Mill. Following Mill, economists first moved by induction from the fact to the idea. In this way, they observed an element common to a large number of phenomena: “men act logically in order to increase their pleasure as much as possible and to diminish their pain” (Pareto [1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 466). Then, they deduced some consequences, moving from the idea to the fact. Finally, they compared their deductions with experience. If any discordance was found, then pure economists like Pareto moved again from the fact to the idea, by modifying and completing the latter (Pareto [1900] Reference Pareto2008, pp. 466–467). This process led Pareto to reject the hedonistic hypothesis that all homo œconomicus aimed at increasing their pleasure and diminishing their pain. Even the ascetic could be a homo œconomicus. In this respect, Pareto broke away from Pantaleoni’s assumption that the ascetic had an anti-economic behavior that would be eliminated by natural selection (Pantaleoni Reference Pantaleoni1898, pp. 17–20), as well as from Bentham, who saw in ascetism a principle opposed to the principle of utility (Bentham Reference Bentham1789, p. vii). The cleansed hypothesis was that homo œconomicus acted logically, that is, that they could judge the comparative efficacy of means to obtain their aims, whatever these may be. Through this process, according to Pareto, pure economists approximated experimental facts by abstract ideas, and thus acted as experimental scientists.

Mill applied the deductive method to political economy, but at the same time he did not think that his concrete deductive method was applicable to this science. The concrete deductive method might be appropriate for social science as a whole, but the special branch of political economy proceeding deductively did not admit direct empirical verification. In contrast, for Pareto, pure economics could be an experimental science, like physics or astronomy (Pareto [1900] Reference Pareto2008, p. 466). The experimental method would help pure economics restrict itself to a narrow class of phenomena that would better approximate empirical observations.

Pareto’s surprising idea was that pure economics could follow the experimental method because it was also the method adopted by the homo œconomicus. Homo œconomicus could logically associate means to ends by adopting the experimental method. In his Manual, Pareto argued that “an objective phenomenon appears to our minds only in the form of a subjective phenomenon” ([1906] Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2004, p. 22). The objective phenomenon, however, could be approximated by the subjective phenomenon. In a similar way, the causal relation between two subjective phenomena could approximately coincide with the causal relation between two objective phenomena. Actions based on the subjective relations approximating the causal relation between two objective phenomena are logical. However, actions based on subjective relations that are far from the causal relation between two objective phenomena are only apparently logical, that is, non-logical. According to Pareto, the repetition of experiences could help to reduce possible errors, thereby gradually adapting actions to aims. This brought him to a noteworthy parallelism: repeated experiences in ordinary life could help to identify relations like “the relations a scientist discovers in his laboratory” ([1906] Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2004, p. 23). “Little by little, by constantly experimenting and comparing his theoretical deductions with reality,” a person in ordinary life will modify the subjective relations and replace them by other relations, “which will come closer to reality” ([1906] Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2004, p. 25). Pareto stated explicitly that the “scientist’s experimental studies are of this kind, as are many of man’s practical actions, including those studied by political economy” ([1906] Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2004, p. 25).Footnote 27 Thus, individuals acted as homo œconomicus by adopting the experimental method of scientists, that is, Mill’s concrete deductive method. Economists could not rely on controlled experiments, and “must be content with observation” ([1906] Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2004, p. 8). However, the observation of “the many logical, repeated actions” ([1906] Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2004, p. 72), like market transactions, could provide the material for empirical verification of the assumptions of economics, especially when these were stripped down to their purest form.

Mill ([1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006) considered political economy to be a separate branch of sociology. Pareto also encased pure economics in the larger discipline of sociology, but he articulated the relation between the two disciplines in a different way. The study of real persons could be obtained by adding to homo œconomicus the study of all “non-logical actions” originating from what he called “residues,” “derivations,” or “interests,” which he discussed extensively in his treatise on general sociology published in 1916 (see Pareto [1916] Reference Pareto and Livingston1935; see also McLure Reference McLure2001, pp. 50–58). As he wrote in his Manual: “The same man, whom I consider as a homo œconomicus for an economic study, may be considered as a homo ethicus for a moral study, as a homo religiosus for a religious study, etc.” Pure economics could thus be completed by other branches of social studies (Pareto [1906] Reference Pareto, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2004, p. 9).

V. CONCLUSION

Despite its changing physiognomy, the economic man was a persistent figure of nineteenth-century political economy. Mill defended a deductive method for political economy that would allow precise logical deductions against a stable social backdrop. His mental law that individuals strive for wealth was rearticulated in terms of utility maximization by Jevons. Criticisms of the possibility of this calculation ran parallel to criticisms of the deductive method of English political economy. The expression “economic man” emerged in the 1870s in this debate between defenders of the abstract method and more historically minded economists. Claudio Jannet, who probably coined the expression “homo œconomicus,” criticized English liberal individualism. Like some German and Irish political economists, he believed the future of political economy lay in a socio-historical study of organic communities like the family and the nation. A number of responses attempted to reconcile the two opposing approaches by broadening the concept of wealth and arguing that the economic man was not so far from reality.

The homo œconomicus was reappropriated by Pantaleoni, who argued that he was not an abstraction but the inevitable result of the evolution of species. Pareto preferred to purify Mill’s methodological proposal, removing the references to wealth and even to utility maximization. Thus, at the turn of the century, the economic man was no longer characterized by his attraction to wealth as Mill had originally postulated. He was merely a choice machine selecting the best means to achieve his ends.

While Mill announced a rigorous methodological program in the 1830s, his own political economy fell short of the standard he had advocated. In his Principles, he moved from the abstract to the concrete to the art of political economy. Inspired by Mill’s concrete deductive method, Pareto formulated methodological rules that made pure economics an empirical science. More specifically, he assumed that the homo œconomicus approximated the empirical reality by following themselves the up-and-down movements of the concrete deductive method.

When we look at the historical development of the concept of “economic man,” the marginal revolution is not a turning point. In the early 1870s, William Stanley Jevons, Carl Menger, and Léon Walras, each in their own way, proposed new foundations for the theory of value that relied on calculating at the margin. Jevons and Walras broadened the scope of mathematical reasoning and Menger proposed a sharp subjectivist critique of the classical theory of value (on this well-known part of the story, see Backhouse Reference Backhouse, Durlauf and Blume2008). However, for his reliance on a deductive method and for defining the core of economics as following a mental law, Jevons walked in the path opened by Mill in 1836. When looking at the economic man, the turning point lies elsewhere: he was painted as a straw man by critics of English political economy, before being reappropriated as the main character in the methodological discourse of Pantaleoni, Edgeworth, and Pareto.

We started our inquiry with Mill’s 1836 essay because it was the reference point for discussions on the method of political economy for the rest of the century. No other methodological text before generated such an echo. Whether this is a story of continuity or discontinuity hinges on which side of the classical/neoclassical fence we situate Mill.

Mill held on to a classical cost of production theory of value, but his methodological writing puts him closer to the next generation of economists. If we consider him as a classical political economist, then from the point of view of the economic agent, the adoption of marginalism is not a rupture. Neoclassical economists who reappropriated the homo œconomicus worked in the continuity of Mill’s scientific project. However, if we believe, as Margaret Schabas argued, that “Mill stood less at the summit of classical economics and more in the valley that rose up toward the neoclassical school” (Reference Schabas, Buchwald and Stewart2017, p. 154), then we could say that Mill anticipated the neoclassical homo œconomicus. In this line of reasoning, there is a rupture between classical and neoclassical economics, but it happened with Mill as he proposed to break away from the social class-based analysis typical of classical political economy. In any case, and despite the transformation it introduces in economic theory, marginal calculus does not constitute a rupture in the characterization of the economic man.

Footnotes

This paper was presented at the twenty-third annual ESHET Conference in Lille in May 2019, at the 2019 HES annual conference in New York City in June 2019, and at the fifty-first UK History of Economic Thought Conference in London in September 2019. We are grateful to the participants of these sessions for their feedback. We would like to thank especially Roberto Baranzini, Pascal Bridel, Luigino Bruni, Raphaël Fèvre, Gonçalo Fonseca, Catherine Herfeld, Harro Maas, Michael McLure, Fiorenzo Mornati, Manuela Mosca, Ivan Moscati, Malvina Ongaro, Huei-chun Su, and three anonymous referees for their constructive engagement with our work on the homo œconomicus.

1 Throughout the paper, we will refer to “economic man” rather than the gender-neutral “economic human being” because it is the historical term used by the economists we study. It reflects the use of the term “man” as a neutral gender but also the androcentric bias of many strands of economics. For elements of a feminist critique of the economic man, see Nelson (Reference Nelson, Ferber and Nelson1993).

2 Zouboulakis (Reference Zouboulakis1993, p. 113) argues that making Mill the father of the homo œconomicus puts too much stress on an absolutist reading of Mill’s [1836] Reference Mill2006 essay. Yet, the fact that generations of economists associated the economic man with Mill is of historical interest.

3 “L’économie [montre] comment se forment, se distribuent et se consomment les richesses” (Say Reference Say1803, p. i). See also Senior (Reference Senior1827, p. 7).

4 Following J-B Say, in his Principles, Mill ([1848a] Reference Mill2006, p. 45) will claim that we are ultimately interested in the “utilities” produced by labor, not the material objects that can be accumulated. To Schabas (Reference Schabas2005, p. 127), the plasticity of Mill’s conception of wealth is further evidence that he held political economy to be a mental science. See also Schabas (Reference Schabas2015, p. 105).

5 The only empirical test available in political economy would be indirect verification. That is, a theory should be able to “predict the present and the past” (Mill [1843] Reference Mill, McRae and Robson2006, p. 910). Mill never claimed that economists should reject a theory on the basis of an empirical test (Hands Reference Hands2001, p. 23). The role of verification in Mill’s methodology of economics is subject to contrasting interpretations. See Hollander (Reference Hollander1985); Hollander and Peart (Reference Hollander and Peart1999, Reference Hollander and Peart2000); and Hirsch (Reference Hirsch2000).

6 See Leslie (Reference Leslie, Ingram and Bastable1888, p. 57); Sidgwick (Reference Sidgwick1883, p. 33); Walker (Reference Walker1883, p. 16); and Neville Keynes (Reference Keynes1891, pp. 17–20). See also Winch (Reference Winch2009, p. 29). For a detailed reconstruction of Mill’s motivations in writing the Principles, see De Marchi (Reference De Marchi1974).

7 Jevons claimed that the “calculus of utility aims at supplying the ordinary wants of men at the least cost of labour” (Jevons Reference Jevons1871, p. 27). Echoing Mill, he remarked in the introduction to the Theory that “each labourer, in the absence of other motives, is supposed to devote his energy to the accumulation of wealth” (Jevons Reference Jevons1871, p. 27). While it is reasonable to assume that Jevons did not restrict wealth to material goods constrained by natural scarcity in the preceding quote (see Schabas Reference Schabas2005, pp. 16, 124), the concept of wealth no longer occupied in his Theory the central place it held in classical political economy up to Mill.

8 On the German historical school methodological criticism of English political economy, see Gide and Rist (Reference Gide and Rist1909, p. 455ff.).

9 On Social Catholicism at the time, see Solari (Reference Solari2010). Jannet was well connected in academic Catholic circles of his time. In 1880 he was awarded a doctorate honoris causa from the Université Laval in Québec, and in 1882 another one from the Université Catholique de Louvain (where the Catholic economist Charles Perrin had held the chair of political economy for many years). Jannet was admitted at the Société d’économie politique in 1885. He held the chair of political economy at the Institut Catholique de Paris until his death in 1894. See Savard (Reference Savard1990).

10 “En réalité, il en est de cette sorte d’homo economicus comme de l’homme de la nature de Rousseau : il n’a jamais existé!”

11 Jannet’s criticism of the homo œconomicus echoed the many voices who compared the economic agent to the fictional character of Daniel Defoe’s novel Robinson Crusoe. Already in Reference Whately1831, Richard Whately argued that an isolated man like Robinson could not be the subject of political economy for it was (or should be) a “science of exchanges” (Reference Whately1831, pp. 6–7). In the introduction to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy ([1857] Reference Marx and Dobb1970, p. 188), Karl Marx criticized the “Robinsonades” of Rousseau, Smith, and Ricardo, who postulated isolated individuals by nature independent as a starting point for history and thus for political economy. In the first chapter of Capital ([1867] Reference Marx1990), Marx came back to this theme to make the case for the social nature of labor. Neoclassical economists claimed back the character of Robinson in the narratives they told about their models. Robinson embodied the idea of production in isolation and eventually bilateral exchange after Edgeworth introduced Friday. Contrary to the homo œconomicus, Robinson is not invoked in discussions about human motivations and the definition of economics. On Robinson, see White (Reference White, Durlauf and Blume2008), Söllner (Reference Söllner2016), and Watson (Reference Watson2017).

12 Mill certainly believed that institutions could and should change, but his quest for natural laws might have made him less convinced by the full set of claims made by Darwin in the Origins of Species. Hull (Reference Hull, Creath and Maienschein2000, p. 58) pointed to a theoretical conflict between Mill’s belief in natural laws, such as the mental law defining the economic man, and the claim that specifies evolve, and thus that laws of nature themselves are not immutable.

13 William Cunningham also defended the economic man while at the same time agreeing with “the Comtist criticism of economic science”: “Thus the ‘economic man’ is not a constant type, but he is always relative to his social environment, both as concerns his habits and his ambitions” ([1889] Reference Cunningham and Smyth1962, p. 104).

14 Crespo (Reference Crespo2020) provides a reconstruction of key methodological positions on the economic method leading up to Neville Keynes’s synthesis, but he goes too far in projecting Neville Keynes’s tripartition of science, normative, and art on John Stuart Mill.

15 See also Edgeworth (Reference Edgeworth1884).

16 Charles Gide (Reference Gide1890) devoted most of his review of Pantaleoni’s Principii to a discussion of the “typical man” whom the author called “homo œconomicus.” The book was later translated into English in 1898. From 1890 to 1924, Maffeo Pantaleoni was one of the editors of Giornale degli Economisti, which was at the center of the debate between the German and the English school that exploded quite virulently in Italy in the 1870s (Augello and Guidi Reference Augello, Marco, Augello and Marco2001).

17 By the time he wrote his Palgrave entries, Edgeworth had read Pantaleoni’s Principii (see Edgeworth Reference Edgeworth1891).

18 Pantaleoni (Reference Pantaleoni1889) inserted himself in a tradition that went back to the law of the minimum of action of Maupertuis. On Pantaleoni’s intellectual sources, see also Bruni (Reference Bruni1997).

19 Tribal egoism is a “more complete, intense and perfect form of egoism” (Pantaleoni Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 21). In the long run, the tribal “eliminates” the individual egoism (see Bruni Reference Bruni1997, pp. 150–151) but only when the latter “tends exclusively to maximise his happiness, regardless of that of others” (Pantaleoni Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 20). Pantaleoni underlined that homo œconomicus “should first make sure of his own preservation and more perfect development, before he can benefit the species” (Pantaleoni Reference Pantaleoni1898, p. 22; see Sunna and Mosca Reference Sunna and Mosca2017, pp. 38–39).

20 Closson (Reference Closson1896) showed how after Linnæus the expression “Homo” (Europæus, Alpinus, Contractus, Acrogonus, etc.) was widespread for qualifying human species (see Mosca Reference Mosca2015).

21 On the same day, Pareto also wrote to Emilia Peruzzi that he was very heartily received by Jannet in Paris (Pareto Reference Pareto and Giacalone Monaco1968, p. 475). Pareto had heard of Jannet through Peruzzi as early as 1889 (Pareto Reference Pareto and Giacalone Monaco1968, p. 400).

22 On the evolution of the concept of homo œconomicus in relationship with the mechanical analogy, see Boianovsky and Tarascio (Reference Boianovsky and Tarascio1998) and McLure (Reference McLure2001, pp. 40–66). On some critical points about this analogy, see Donzelli (Reference Donzelli1997) and Marchionatti and Gambino (Reference Marchionatti and Gambino1997).

23 A few years later, but without apparent knowledge of Pareto’s work, Max Weber proposed a comparable abstraction from empirical reality. In economics, Weber argued that ideal types are constructed around a principle of means–end rationality to capture some typical features of social conduct. On Weber’s conceptualization of economic rationality in relation to the homo oeconomicus, see Demeulenaere ([1996] Reference Demeulenaere2003, p. 179ff.).

24 By introducing these distinctions, Pareto seems to anticipate the difference between homo oeconomicus, homo ethicus, or homo religious presented in the Manual. Two years after Pareto’s Cours was published, Léon Walras addressed explicitly the difference between homo oeconomicus and homo ethicus in his “Esquisse d’une doctrine économique et sociale” (Reference Walras, Dockès, Goutte, Hébert, Mouchot, Potier and Servet1898). He stated that man living in society, i.e., homo cœnonicus, embraced homo oeconomicus and homo ethicus, and for this reason “cénonique générale” was a rational and abstract science encompassing pure economics and pure ethics (Bee Reference Bee, Diemer and Potier2013).

25 On Pareto’s theory of choice, see Gross and Tarascio (Reference Gross and Tarascio1998). On whether Pareto completely emancipated from psychology, see Demeulenaere ([1996] Reference Demeulenaere2003, pp. 170–173); Bruni and Sugden (Reference Bruni and Sugden2007); Giocoli (Reference Giocoli2003, pp. 71–75); Moscati (Reference Moscati2018, pp. 79–116).

26 Pareto, however, thought that Mill “did not give due credit to the use of mathematics” ([1892–93] Reference Pareto, Marchionatti and Mornati2007, p. 142). Mathematics was a “complicated syllogism-making machine” that provided logical deductions (Pareto Reference Pareto and de Rosa1960, p. 74). On possible changes in Pareto’s attitude towards Mill’s methodology, see Cressati (Reference Cressati1985) and Bruni and Guala (Reference Bruni, Guala and Bouvier1999).

27 Political economy studied all the actions whose aims were subjectively and objectively logical, both when these aims coincided, as in logical actions, and when they did not coincide, as in some cases of non-logical actions; for example, the logical actions of entrepreneurs looking for profit under competition could lead to unintended logical consequences, i.e. the consumers’ benefit; see Pareto ([1916] Reference Pareto and Livingston1935, p. 86); see also McLure (Reference McLure, Montesano, Zanni, Bruni, Chipman and McLure2014, p. 534).

References

REFERENCES

Augello, Massimo M., and Marco, E. L. Guidi. 2001. “The Associations of Economists and the Dissemination of Political Economy in Italy.” In Augello, Massimo M. and Marco, E. L. Guidi, eds., The Spread of Political Economy and the Professionalisation of Economists: Economic Societies in Europe, America and Japan in the Nineteenth Century. Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 7990.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Backhouse, Roger E. 2008. “Marginal Revolution.” In Durlauf, Steven N. and Blume, Lawrence E., eds., The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Second edition. London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 38863888.Google Scholar
Bagehot, Walter. [1876] 1880. “The Postulates of English Political Economy.” In Hutton, Richard Holt, ed., Economic Studies. London: Longmans, Green & Co., pp. 171.Google Scholar
Bagehot, Walter. 1880. “The Preliminaries of Political Economy.” In Hutton, Richard Holt, ed., Economic Studies. London: Longmans, Green & Co., pp. 7294.Google Scholar
Barbé, Lluís. 2010. Francis Ysidro Edgeworth: A Portrait with Family and Friends. Translated by Black, Mary C.. Chelthenham: Edward Elgar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bee, Michele. 2013. “Homo cœnonicus. Le caractère naturel de la division du travail et la nécessité du progrès industriel dans la théorie de l’histoire de Léon Walras.” In Diemer, Antoine and Potier, Jean-Pierre, eds., Léon Walras: un siècle après (1910–2010). Bruxelles: Peter Lang, pp. 87106.Google Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy. 1789. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. London: T. Payne and Son.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy. [1800]. 1843. A Manual of Political Economy . Volume 3 of The Works of Jeremy Bentham. Edited by Bowring, John. Edinburgh: William Tait.Google Scholar
Blaug, Mark. 1992. The Methodology of Economics. Second edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boianovsky, Mauro, and Tarascio, Vincent J.. 1998. “Mechanical Inertia and Economic Dynamics: Pareto on Business Cycles.” Journal of the History of Economic Thought 20 (1): 523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruni, Luigino. 1997. “‘Principio economico’ e ‘fenomeno economico’ nel pensiero di Pantaleoni e Pareto. Uno studio sulla razionalità economica (1889–1899).Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Sociali 105 (2): 139179.Google Scholar
Bruni, Luigino. 2013. “The Paretian Turn: The Foundation of the Theory of Rational Choice, and Its Discontents.” Revue européenne des sciences sociales 51 (2): 4764.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruni, Luigino, and Guala, Francesco. 1999. “Pareto’s Theory of Action from the Cours to the Trattato: Idealization, Utility, Concrete Deductive Method.” In Bouvier, A., ed., Pareto aujourd’hui. Paris: PUF, pp. 171188.Google Scholar
Bruni, Luigino, and Guala, Francesco. 2001. “Vilfredo Pareto and the Epistemological Foundations of Choice Theory.” History of Politcal Economy 33 (1): 2149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruni, Luigino, and Sugden, Robert. 2007. “The Road Not Taken: How Psychology Was Removed from Economics, and How It Might Be Brought Back.” Economic Journal 117 (Jan.): 146173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cairnes, John Elliot. 1857. The Character and Logical Method of Political Economy. London: Longman & Co.Google Scholar
Castelot, Eloi. 1894. “Obituary [Claudio Jannet].” Economic Journal 4 (16): 745746.Google Scholar
Castelot, Eloi. 1896. “Jannet, Claudio.” In Palgrave, Robert Harry Inglis, ed., Dictionary of Political Economy. Volume 2. London: Macmillan, pp. 471472.Google Scholar
Claeys, Gregory. 2019. “Social Darwinism.” In Claeys, Gregory, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Nineteenth-Century Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 163183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Closson, Carlos C. 1896. “Social Selection.” Journal of Political Economy 4 (4): 449466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Comte, Auguste. 1839. Cours de philosophie positive. Volume 4. Paris: Bachelier.Google Scholar
Cook, Simon J. 2009. The Intellectual Foundations of Alfred Marshall’s Economic Science: A Rounded Globe of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cook, Simon J., and Tribe, Keith. 2016. “Historical Economics.” In Faccarello, Gilbert and Kurz, Heinz D., eds., Handbook on the History of Economic Analysis. Volume II. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 295312.Google Scholar
Crespo, Ricardo F. 2020. The Nature and Method of Economic Sciences: Evidence, Causality, and Ends. Abington: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cressati, Claudio. 1985. “Vilfredo Pareto e John Stuart Mill.” Il pensiero politico 18 (1): 3954.Google Scholar
Cunningham, William. [1889] 1962. “The Comtist Criticism of Economic Science.” Reproduced in Smyth, R. L., ed., Essays in Economic Method. Selected Papers Read to Section F of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, 1860–1913. London: Gerald Duckworth, pp. 98111.Google Scholar
De Marchi, Neil B. 1972. “Mill and Cairnes and the Emergence of Marginalism in England.” History of Political Economy 4 (2): 344363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Marchi, Neil B. 1974. “The Success of Mill’s Principles.” History of Political Economy 6 (2): 119157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demeulenaere, Pierre. [1996] 2003. Homo œconomicus: Enquête sur la constitution d’un paradigme. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devas, Charles S. 1883. Groundwork of Economics. London: Longmans, Green, & Co.Google Scholar
Donzelli, Franco. 1997. ‘Pareto’s Mechanical Dream.” History of Economic Ideas 5 (3): 127178.Google Scholar
Edgeworth, Francis Ysidro. 1881. Mathematical Psychics: An Essay on the Application of Mathematics to the Moral Sciences. London: C. Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Edgeworth, Francis Ysidro. 1884. “The Rationale of Exchange.” Journal of the Royal Statistical Society 47 (1): 167169.Google Scholar
Edgeworth, Francis Ysidro. 1891. “La théorie mathématique de l’offre et de la demande et le coût de production.” Revue d’économie politique 5 (1): 1028.Google Scholar
Fontana, Biancamaria. 1986. “Democracy and Civilization: John Stuart Mill and the Critique of Political Economy.” Économies et Sociétés, “Histoire de La Pensée Économique” Série PE (5): 324.Google Scholar
Geddes, Patrick. 1885. An Analysis of the Principles of Economics. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Gide, Charles. 1890. “Pantaleoni. Principii di economia pura.” Revue d’Economie Politique 4 (1): 323326.Google Scholar
Gide, Charles, and Rist, Charles. 1909. Histoire des doctrines économiques depuis les Physiocrates jusqu’à nos jours. Paris: J.B. Sirey.Google Scholar
Giocoli, Nicola. 2003. Modeling Rational Agents: From Interwar Economics to Early Modern Game Theory. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gross, Martin, and Tarascio, Vincent J.1998. “Pareto’s Theory of Choice.” History of Political Economy 30 (2): 171187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guala, Francesco. 1998. “Pareto on Idealization and the Method of Analysis-Synthesis.” Social Science Information 37 (1): 2344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guidi, Marco E.L. 2010. “Le Manuel d’économie politique de Jeremy Bentham au prisme de la traduction d’Etienne Dumont et des relectures de James Mill et de John Stuart Mill.Revue d’études benthamiennes 7. https://doi.org/10.4000/etudes-benthamiennes.205.Google Scholar
Hagemann, Harald. 2001. “The Verein Für Sozialpolitik from Its Foundation (1872) until World War I.” In Augello, Massimo M. and Marco, E. L. Guidi, eds., The Spread of Political Economy and the Professionalisation of Economists. Economic Societies in Europe, America, and Japan in the Nineteenth Century. Abingdon: Routledge, pp. 152175.Google Scholar
Hands, D. Wade. 2001. Reflection without Rules. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, Adolf. 1877. “Der volkswirthschaftliche Kongreß und der Verein für Socialpolitik.” In Jahrbuch für Gesetzgebung, Verwaltung und Volkswirtschaft im Deutschen Reich. LeipzigVerlag von Dunder und Humblot, pp. 159177.Google Scholar
Hirsch, Abraham. 2000. “Reply to Hollander and Peart’s ‘John Stuart Mill’s Method.’Journal of the History of Economic Thought 22 (3): 349360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodgson, Dennis. 1992. “Ideological Currents and the Interpretation of Demographic Trends: The Case of Francis Amasa Walker.” History of Behavioral Sciences 28 (1): 2844.3.0.CO;2-L>CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hollander, Samuel. 1985. The Economics of John Stuart Mill. Volume I: Theory and Method. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Hollander, Samuel, and Peart, Sandra J.. 1999. “John Stuart Mill’s Method in Principle and Practice: A Review of the Evidence.” Journal of the History of Economic Thought 23 (4): 369397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hollander, Samuel, and Peart, Sandra J.. 2000. “A Rejoinder to Abraham Hirsch.” Journal of the History of Economic Thought 22 (3): 361365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David L. 2000. “Why Did Darwin Fail?” In Creath, Richard and Maienschein, Jane, eds., Biology and Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 4863.Google Scholar
Hutchison, Terence. 1978. On Revolutions and Progress in Economic Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ingram, John K. 1878. The Present Position and Prospects of Political Economy. London: Longman & Co.Google Scholar
Ingram, John K. 1885. “Political Economy.” In Encyclopædia Britannica, Ninth edition. Volume 19. Edinburgh: Adam and Charles Black, pp. 346401.Google Scholar
Jannet, Claudio. 1878. “De l’état actuel de la science sociale.” Le Correspondant (112): 870889; 1062–1080.Google Scholar
Jannet, Claudio, Stiegler, Gasion, Gide, Charles, and Passy, Frédéric. 1890. Quatre écoles d’économie sociale. Conférences données à l’Aula de L’Université de Genève sous les auspices de la Société chrétienne suisse d’Économie sociale. Genève: Librairie Stapelmohr.Google Scholar
Jevons, W. Stanley. 1862. “Notice of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy.” Report of British Association for the Advancement of Science, Section F, London, pp. 158159.Google Scholar
Jevons, W. Stanley. 1866. “Brief Account of a General Mathematical Theory of Political Economy.” Journal of the Statistical Society of London 29 (2): 282287.Google Scholar
Jevons, W. Stanley. 1871. The Theory of Political Economy. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Jevons, W. Stanley. 1876. “The Future of Political Economy.” Fortnightly Review 20 (119): 617631.Google Scholar
Jevons, W. Stanley. [1879] 2013. The Theory of Political Economy. Second edition. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, William E. 1894. “Economic Man.” In Palgrave, Robert Harry Inglis, ed., Dictionary of Political Economy. Volume 1. London: Macmillan, pp. 676677.Google Scholar
Keynes, John Neville. 1891. The Scope and Method of Political Economy. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Koot, Gerard M. 1987. English Historical Economics, 1870–1926: The Rise of Economic History and Neomercantilism. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Leslie, T. E. Cliffe. 1888. Essays in Political Economy, edited by Ingram, J. K. and Bastable, C. F.. Second edition. Dublin: Hodges, Foster, & Figgis.Google Scholar
Maas, Harro. 1999. “Mechanical Rationality: Jevons and the Making of Economic Man.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 30 (4): 587619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macaulay, Thomas Babington. 1829. “Mill on Government.” In The Miscellaneous Writings of Lord Macaulay. Volume 1. https://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/macaulay-miscellaneous-writings-vol-1.Google Scholar
Marchionatti, Roberto, and Gambino, Enrico. 1997. “Pareto and Political Economy as a Science: Methodological Revolution and Analytical Advances in Economic Theory in the 1890s.” Journal of Political Economy 105 (6): 13221348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall, Alfred. 1885. The Present Position of Economics. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Marshall, Alfred. 1890. Principles of Economics. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. [1857] 1970. “Introduction” [Grundrisse]. In A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy. Edited by Dobb, Maurice. Moscow: Progress Publishers, pp. 188217.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. [1867]. 1990. Capital. Volume 1. London: PenguinGoogle Scholar
McLure, Michael. 2001. Pareto, Economics and Society: The Mechanical Analogy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
McLure, Michael. 2007. The Paretian School and Italian Fiscal Sociology. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLure, Michael. 2014. “Editors’ Note.” In Vilfredo Pareto, Manual of Political Economy. Edited by Montesano, Aldo, Zanni, Alberto, Bruni, Luigino, Chipman, John S., and McLure, Michael. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 513620.Google Scholar
Mill, James. 1820. “Government.” In The Supplement to The Encyclopædia Britannica. London: J. Innes.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1836] 2006. “On the Definition of Political Economy; and on the Method of Investigation Proper to It.” In The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Volume IV: Essays on Economics and Society. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, pp. 309339.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1838] 2006. “Bentham.” In The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Volume X: Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, pp. 77115.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1843] 2006. A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive, Part I and II. Edited by McRae, R. F. and Robson, John M.. Volumes VII and VIII of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1848a] 2006. Principles of Political Economy. Volume II of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1848b] 2006. Principles of Political Economy. Volume III of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1863] 2006. “Utilitarianism.” In The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Volume X: Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, pp. 205259.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. [1873] 2006. Autobiography and Literary Essays. Volume I of The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Morgan, Mary S. 2006. “Economic Man as Model Man: Ideal Types, Idealization and Caricatures.” Journal of the History of Economic Thought 28 (1): 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mornati, Fiorenzo. 2018. Vilfredo Pareto: An Intellectual Biography. Volume I: From Science to Liberty (1848–1891). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mosca, Manuela. 2015. “‘Io che sono darwinista’. La visione di Maffeo Pantaleoni.” Il Pensiero Economico Italiano 23 (1) : 2345.Google Scholar
Moscati, Ivan. 2018. Measuring Utility. From the Marginal Revolution to Behavioral Economics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, Julie A. 1993. “The Study of Choice or the Study of Provisioning? Gender and the Definition of Economics.” In Ferber, Marianne A. and Nelson, Julie A., eds., Beyond Economic Man: Feminist Theory and Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 2336.Google Scholar
O’Boyle, Edward J. 2009. “The Origins of Homo Economicus: A Note.” Storia Del Pensiero Economico 6 (1): 195199.Google Scholar
Palgrave, Robert Harry Inglis, ed. 1896. Dictionary of Political Economy. Volume 2. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Palgrave, Robert Harry Inglis. ed. 1899. Dictionary of Political Economy. Volume 3. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Pantaleoni, Maffeo. 1889. Principii di economia pura. Firenze: G. Barbèra.Google Scholar
Pantaleoni, Maffeo. 1898. Pure Economics. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1891. “Lasciate fare, lasciate passare.” Giornale degli Economisti (Sept.): 218–234.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1892. “Recensione a C. Jannet. Le capital, la spéculation et la finance au XXe siècle.Giornale degli Economisti (July): 81–83.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. [1892–93] 2007. “Considerazioni sui principi fondamentali dell’economia politica pura.” Giornale degli Economisti. Translated as Considerations on the Fundamental Principles of Pure Political Economy. Edited by Marchionatti, Roberto and Mornati, Fiorenzo. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1896. Cours d’économie politique professé à l’Université de Lausanne. Lausanne: F. Rouge Editeur.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. [1900] 2008. “Sunto di alcuni capitoli di un Nuovo trattato di economia pura del prof. Pareto.” Giornale degli Economisti. Translated as “Summary of Some Chapters of a New Treatise on Pure Economics by Professor Pareto.” Giornale degli Economisti e Annali di Economia, Nuova Serie 67 (3): 453504.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. [1906] 2004. Manuale di Economia politica con una introduzione alla scienza sociale. Translated as Manual of Political Economy. Edited by Montesano, Aldo, Zanni, Alberto, Bruni, Luigino, Chipman, John S., and McLure, Michael. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. [1916] 1935. Trattato sociologia generale. Translated as The Mind and Society. Edited by Livingston, Arthur. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1960. Lettere a Maffeo Pantaleoni. Edited by de Rosa, Gabriele. Volume 1. Roma: Banca Nazionale del Lavoro.Google Scholar
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1968. Lettere a Emilia Peruzzi. Edited by Giacalone Monaco, T.. Roma: Edizioni Storia e Letteratura.Google Scholar
Persky, Joseph. 1995. “Retrospectives: The Ethology of Homo Economicus.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 9 (2): 221231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Persky, Joseph. 2016. The Political Economy of Progress: John Stuart Mill and Modern Radicalism. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Philippovich, Eugen von. 1891. “The Verein Fur Sozialpolitik.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 5 (2): 220237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savard, Pierre. 1990. “Du lac Saint-Jean au Texas: Claudio Jannet à la recherche de l’Amérique idéale.” Revue française d’histoire d’outre-mer 77 (288): 319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Say, Jean-Baptiste. 1803. Traité d’économie politique. Paris: Crapelet.Google Scholar
Schabas, Margaret. 1990. A World Ruled by Number: William Stanley Jevons and the Rise of Mathematical Economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schabas, Margaret. 2005. The Natural Origins of Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schabas, Margaret. 2015. “John Stuart Mill: Evolutionary Economics and Liberalism.” Journal of Bioeconomics 17 (1): 97111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schabas, Margaret. 2017. “More Food for Thought: Mill, Coleridge and the Dismal Science of Economics.” In Buchwald, Jed and Stewart, Larry, eds., The Romance of Science: Essays in Honour of Trevor H. Levere. Cham: Springer, pp. 151162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Senior, Nassau W. 1827. An Introductory Lecture on Political Economy Delivered before the University of Oxford, the 6th of December, 1826. London: J. Mawman.Google Scholar
Senior, Nassau W. 1848. “J. S. Mill on Political Economy.” Edinburgh Review 88 (Oct.): 293339.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. 1883. The Principles of Political Economy. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Solari, Stefano. 2010. “The Corporative Third Way in Social Catholicism (1830 to 1918).” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 17 (1): 87113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Söllner, Fritz. 2016. “The Use (and Abuse) of Robinson Crusœ in Neoclassical Economics.” History of Political Economy 48 (1): 3564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spencer, Herbert. 1874. The Data of Ethics. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Sunna, Claudia, and Mosca, Manuela. 2017. “Heterogenesis of Ends: Herbert Spencer and the Italian Economists.” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 2 (1): 2557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, Richard A. 2016. “Behavioral Economics: Past, Present, and Future.” American Economic Review 106 (7): 15771600.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veblen, Thorstein. 1899. “The Preconceptions of Economic Science II.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 13 (4): 396426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walker, Francis A. 1874. “Cairnes’s Political Economy.” The Nation, 11 December.Google Scholar
Walker, Francis A. 1876. The Wages Question; A Treatise on Wages and the Wages Class. New York: H. Holt and Company.Google Scholar
Walker, Francis A. 1883. Political Economy. New York: H. Holt and Co.Google Scholar
Walras, Léon. [1898] 1992. “Esquisse d’une doctrine économique et sociale.” In Auguste Walras and Léon Walras, Œuvres économiques complètes. Volume X, edited by Dockès, P., Goutte, H., Hébert, C., Mouchot, C., Potier, J.-P., and Servet, J.-M.. Paris: Economica, pp. 405441.Google Scholar
Watson, Matthew. 2017. “Rousseau’s Crusoe Myth: The Unlikely Provenance of the Neoclassical Homo Economicus.” Journal of Cultural Economy 10 (1): 8196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whately, Richard. 1831. Introductory Lectures on Political Economy. London: B. Fellowes.Google Scholar
Whitaker, John K. 1975. “John Stuart Mill’s Methodology.” Journal of Political Economy 83 (5): 10331049.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Michael V. 2008. “Robinson Crusœ.” In Durlauf, Steven N. and Blume, Lawrence E., eds., The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. Second edition, London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Winch, Donald. 2009. Wealth and Life: Essays on the Intellectual History of Political Economy in Britain, 1848–1914. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zouboulakis, Michel S. 1993. La science économique à la recherche de ses fondements : la tradition épistémologique ricardienne, 1826–1891. Paris: PUF.Google Scholar