Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-94d59 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T05:51:47.924Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Keeping track of what's right

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Laura Schroeter*
Affiliation:
Faculty of Arts, School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, The University of Melbourne, Parkville, Australia
François Schroeter
Affiliation:
Faculty of Arts, School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, The University of Melbourne, Parkville, Australia

Abstract

In this paper, we argue that ordinary judgments about core normative topics purport to attribute stable, objective properties and relations. Our strategy is first to analyze the structures and practices characteristic of paradigmatically representational concepts such as concepts of objects and natural kinds. We identify three broad features that ground the representational purport of these concepts. We then argue that core normative concepts exhibit these same features.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2018

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bird, Alexander, and Tobin, Emma. 2017. “Natural Kinds.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, E. N..https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/natural-kinds/.Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 1988. “Individualism and Self-Knowledge.” Journal of Philosophy 85: 649663. 10.5840/jphil1988851112CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, Tyler. 2010. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199581405.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, Alex, and Pryor, James. 2006. “Bad Intensions.” In Two-Dimensional Semantics: Foundations and Applications, edited by Garcia-Carprintero, M. and Macia, J., 3854. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dickie, Imogen. 2010. “We Are Acquainted with Ordinary Things.” In New Essays on Singular Thought, edited by Jeshion, Robin, 213245. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, Gareth. 1973. “The Causal Theory of Names.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 47: 187225. 10.1093/aristoteliansupp/47.1.187CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2007. Semantic Relationism. Oxford: Blackwell. 10.1002/9780470690826CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kölbel, Max. 2002. Truth without Objectivity. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, John. 2014. Assessment Sensitivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682751.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett. 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Murez, Michael, and Recanati, François. 2016. “Mental Files: An Introduction.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7: 265281. 10.1007/s13164-016-0314-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinillos, N. Ángel. 2011. “Coreference and Meaning.” Philosophical Studies 154: 301324. 10.1007/s11098-010-9543-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1970. “Is Semantics Possible?” In Language, Belief and Metaphysics, edited by Kiefer, H.E. and Munitz, M.K., 5063. New York: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1973. “Meaning and Reference.” The Journal of Philosophy 70: 699711. 10.2307/2025079CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Zenon. 1989. “The Role of Location Indexes in Spatial Perception: A Sketch of the FINST Spatial-Index Model.” Cognition 32: 6597. 10.1016/0010-0277(89)90014-0CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pylyshyn, Zenon. 2007. Things and Places: How the Mind Connects with the World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeter, Laura. 2007. “Illusion of Transparency.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85: 597618. 10.1080/00048400701654820CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeter, Laura. 2008. “Why Be an Anti-Individualist?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 105141. 10.1111/phpr.2008.77.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeter, Laura. 2012. “Bootstrapping Our Way to Samesaying.” Synthese 189: 177197. 10.1007/s11229-012-0099-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeter, Laura 2017. “Two Dimensional Semantics.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Zalta, E. N..https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/two-dimensional-semantics/.Google Scholar
Schroeter, Laura, and Schroeter, François. 2014. “Normative Concepts: A Connectedness Model.” Philosophers’ Imprint 14(25): 126.Google Scholar
Schroeter, Laura, and Schroeter, François. 2015. “Rationalizing Self-Interpretation.” In Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods, edited by Daly, Chris, 419447. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1990. “Narrow Content.” In Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Original edition, (C.A. Anderson and J. Owens, eds.) Propositional Attitudes. Stanford: CSLI.Google Scholar