Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-01T15:37:45.862Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Non-defensible Middle Ground for Experimental Realism: Why We Are Justified to Believe in Colored Quarks

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Experimental realism aims at striking a middle ground between scientific realism and anti-realism, between the success of experimental physics it would explain and the realism about scientific theories it would supplant. This middle ground reinstates the engineering idea that belief in scientific entities is justified on purely experimental grounds, without any commitment to scientific theories and laws. This paper argues that there is no defensible middle ground to be staked out when it comes to justifying physicists’ belief in colored quarks, and that experimental realism shifts, under analysis, into scientific realism.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am very grateful to Peter Lipton and Michael Redhead for insightful comments and suggestions on earlier drafts of this paper. I have much benefited from stimulating comments made by Steve Clarke, Mauro Dorato, Mary Leng, Robert Nola, and Mark Sprevak. I thank Emanuele Leonardi (CERN) for friendly help with the reference of the CDHS experiment and color confinement. The challenging and constructive criticisms of two anonymous referees helped me to clarify the ideas here exposed.

References

Altarelli, G. and Parisi, G. (1977), “Asymptotic Freedom in Parton Language”, Asymptotic Freedom in Parton Language B 126:298318.Google Scholar
Bjorken, J. D., and Paschos, E. A. (1969), “Inelastic Electron-Proton and γ-Proton Scattering and the Structure of Nucleon”, Inelastic Electron-Proton and γ-Proton Scattering and the Structure of Nucleon 185:19751982.Google Scholar
Buras, A. J., and Gaemers, K. J. F. (1978), “Simple Parametrization of Parton Distributions with Q 2 Dependence Given by Asymptotic Freedom”, Simple Parametrization of Parton Distributions with Q 2 Dependence Given by Asymptotic Freedom B 132:249267.Google Scholar
Callan, C. G., and Gross, D. J. (1968), “Crucial Test of a Theory of Currents”, Crucial Test of a Theory of Currents 21:311313.Google Scholar
Callan, C. G., and Gross, D. J. (1969), “High-energy Electroproduction and the Constitution of Electric Current”, High-energy Electroproduction and the Constitution of Electric Current 22:156159.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Steve (2001), “Defensible Territory for Entity Realism”, Defensible Territory for Entity Realism 52:701722.Google Scholar
Close, F. E. (1997), “Glueballs and Hybrids: New States of Matter”, Glueballs and Hybrids: New States of Matter 38:112.Google Scholar
de Groot, J. G. H., et al. (1979), “Inclusive Interactions of High-Energy Neutrinos and Antineutrinos in Iron”, Zeitschrift für Physik C, Particles and Fields 1:143162.Google Scholar
Feynman, Richard P. (1972), Photon-hadron Interactions. New York: Benjamin.Google Scholar
Franklin, Alan (1996), “There Are No Antirealists in the Laboratory”, in Cohen, R. S., Hilpinen, R., and Renzong, Q. (eds.), Realism and Anti-Realism in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 131148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gell-Mann, Murray (1961), “The Eightfold Way: a Theory of Strong Interaction Symmetry”, California Institute of Technology Synchrotron Laboratory Report CTSL-20. Reprinted in Murray Gell-Mann and Yuval Ne'eman (eds.), The Eightfold Way. New York: W. A. Benjamin, 1964, 1157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gell-Mann, Murray (1964), “A Schematic Model of Baryons and Mesons”, A Schematic Model of Baryons and Mesons 8:214–15. Reprinted in Murray Gell-Mann and Yuval Ne’eman (eds.), The Eightfold Way. New York: W. A. Benjamin, 1964, 168–169.Google Scholar
Gross, D. J., and Llewellyn Smith, C. H. (1969), “High-energy Neutrino-nucleon Scattering, Current Algebra and Partons”, High-energy Neutrino-nucleon Scattering, Current Algebra and Partons B 14:337347.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1982), “Experimentation and Scientific Realism”, Experimentation and Scientific Realism 13:7187.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1983), Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halzen, Francis, and Martin, Alan D. (1984), Quarks and Leptons: An Introductory Course in Modern Particle Physics. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Han, M. Y., and Nambu, Y. (1965), “Three-Triplet Model with Double SU(3) Symmetry”, Three-Triplet Model with Double SU(3) Symmetry B 139:10061010.Google Scholar
Kukla, André (1996), “Does Every Theory Have Empirically Equivalent Rivals?”, Does Every Theory Have Empirically Equivalent Rivals? 44:137166.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry (1990), “Demystifying Underdetermination”, in Savage, C. Wade (ed.), Scientific Theories. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 267297.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry, and Leplin, Jarrett (1991), “Empirical Equivalence and Underdetermination”, Empirical Equivalence and Underdetermination 88 (9): 449472..Google Scholar
Massimi, Michela (forthcoming), “What Demonstrative Induction Can Do against the Threat of Underdetermination: Bohr, Heisenberg, and Pauli on Spectroscopic Anomalies (1921–24)”, Synthese.Google Scholar
Martin, B. R., and Shaw, G. (1999) Particle Physics, 2d ed. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Musgrave, Alan (1996), “Realism, Truth, and Objectivity”, in Cohen, R. S., Hilpinen, R. and Renzong, Q. (eds.), Realism and Anti-realism in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1944.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ne'eman, Yuval (1961), “Derivation of Strong Interactions from a Gauge Invariance”, Nuclear Physics 26:222229. Reprinted in Murray Gell-Mann and Yuval Ne'eman (eds.), The Eightfold Way. New York: W. A. Benjamin, 1964, 58–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1975), “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’”, in Gunderson, K. (ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 7. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in H. Putnam, Mind, Language and Reality. Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975, 215271.Google Scholar
Resnik, David B. (1994), “Hacking’s Experimental Realism”, Hacking’s Experimental Realism 24:395412.Google Scholar
Sellars, Wilfred (1962), Science, Perception, and Reality. New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Shapere, Dudley (1982), “The Concept of Observation in Science and Philosophy”, The Concept of Observation in Science and Philosophy 49:485525.Google Scholar
Shapere, Dudley (1993), “Astronomy and Anti-Realism”, Astronomy and Anti-Realism 60:134–50.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar