Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-nr4z6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-20T13:03:05.826Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reconciling Cognitive and Perceptual Theories of Emotion: A Representational Proposal

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Louis C. Charland*
Affiliation:
Clinical Trials Research Group, Biomedical Ethics Unit, McGill University
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Clinical Trials Research Group, Biomedical Ethics Unit, Faculty of Medicine, 3690 Peel Street, McGill University, Montreal, Quebec, Canada H3A 1W9.

Abstract

The distinction between cognitive and perceptual theories of emotion is entrenched in the literature on emotion and is openly used by individual emotion theorists when classifying their own theories and those of others. In this paper, I argue that the distinction between cognitive and perceptual theories of emotion is more pernicious than it is helpful, while at the same time insisting that there are nonetheless important perceptual and cognitive factors in emotion that need to be distinguished. A general representational metatheoretical framework for reconciling cognitive and perceptual theories is proposed. This is the Representational Theory of Emotion (RTE). A detailed case study of Antonio Damasio's important new contribution to emotion theory is presented in defense of the RTE. The paper is intended for readers interested in the foundations of emotion theory and cognitive science.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank Evan Thompson and Andrew Wayne for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

Charland, L.C. (1989), Emotions and the Representational Mind: A Computationalist Perspective. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Western Ontario.Google Scholar
Charland, L.C. (1995), “Emotion as a Natural Kind”, Philosophical Psychology 8(1): 5984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charland, L.C. (1996), “Feeling and Representing: Computational Theory and the Modularity of Affect”, Synthese 105: 273301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P.M. (1984), Matter and Consciousness: A Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P.M. (1995), The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul: A Philosophical Journey into the Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, S.G. (1986), “Emotions: Rationality without Cognitivism”, Dialogue 25: 663674.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damasio, A.R. (1994), Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: G.P. Putnam's Sons.Google Scholar
De Sousa, R. (1987), The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1981), Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1981a), “Intentional Systems”, in Dennett 1981, 322.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1987), The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1987a), “True Believers”, in Dennett 1987, 1342.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1991), Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1995), “Our Vegetative Soul: The Search for a Reliable Model of the Human Self”, Times Literary Supplement August 25: 34.Google Scholar
Ekman, P. (1980), “Biological and Cultural Contributions to Body and Facial Movement in the Expression of Emotion”, in Rorty 1980, 73101.Google Scholar
Ekman, P. (1984), “Expression and the Nature of Emotion”, in Scherer and Ekman 1984, 319343.Google Scholar
Flanagan, O. (1991), The Science of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1981), Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1981a), “Three Cheers for Propositional Attitudes”, in Fodor 1981, 100123.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1983), The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frijda, N.H. (1988), “The Laws of Emotion”, American Psychologist 43: 349358.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Frijda, N.H. (1993), “The Place of Appraisal in Emotion”, Cognition and Emotion 7(3/4): 357387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gordon, R. M. (1987), The Structure of Emotions: Investigations in Cognitive Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Greenspan, P. (1989), Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional Justification. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Griffiths, P.E. (1990), “Modularity and the Psychoevolutionary Theory of Emotion”, Biology and Philosophy 5(2): 175196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, W. (1894), “What is an Emotion?”, Mind 9: 188205.Google Scholar
James, W. (1890), Principles of Psychology. New York: Holt.Google Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P.N. (1988), The Computer and the Mind: An Introduction to Cognitive Science. London: Fontana Press.Google Scholar
Johnson-Laird, P.N. and Oately, K. (1992), “Basic Emotions, Rationality, and Folk Theory”, Cognition and Emotion 6(3/4): 201223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kenny, A. (1963), Action, Emotion and Will. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. (1984a), “Cognition, Emotion and Motivation: The Doctoring of Humpty-Dumpty”, in Scherer and Ekman 1984, 221239.Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. (1984b), “Thoughts on the Relation Between Emotion and Cognition”, in Scherer and Ekman 1984, 247259.Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. (1991) Emotion and Adaptation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lazarus, R. and Lazarus, B. (1994), Passion and Reason: Making Sense of Our Emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
LeDoux, J.E. (1989), “Cognitive-Emotional Reactions in the Brain”, Cognition and Emotion 3(4): 267289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
LeDoux, J.E. (1996), The Emotional Brain, The Mysterious Underpinning of our Emotional Life. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Leventhal, H. (1984), “A Perceptual Motor Theory of Emotion”, in Scherer and Ekman 1984, 271291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leventhal, H. and Scherer, K.R. (1987), “The Relationship of Emotion and Cognition: A Functional Approach to a Semantic Controversy”, Cognition and Emotion 1: 328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, W. (1980), Emotion: Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Marr, D. (1982), Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Representation and Processing of Visual Information. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Oately, K. and Johnson-Laird, P.N. (1987), “Towards a Cognitive Theory of Emotions”, Cognition and Emotion 1: 2950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Panskepp, J. (1982), “Toward a General Psychobiological Theory of Emotions”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5(3): 407469.Google Scholar
Parrott, G.W. and Schulkin, J. (1993), “Neuropsychology and the Cognitive Nature of Emotions”, Cognition and Emotion 7(1): 4359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1984), Computation and Cognition: Toward a Foundation for Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V.O. (1960), Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, A.O. (1980), Explaining Emotions. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Schacter, S. and Singer, J.E. (1962), “Cognitive, Social and Physiological Determinants of Emotional State”, Psychological Review 69: 379399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scherer, K.R. and Ekman, P. (eds.) (1984), Approaches to Emotion. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Smolensky, P. (1988), “On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11: 174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solomon, R. (1976), The Passions: The Myth and Nature of Human Emotion. New York: Anchor Press, Doubleday.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1978), “Beliefs and Subdoxastic States”, Philosophy of Science 45: 499518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, E. (1995), “Colour Vision, Evolution, and Perceptual Content”, Synthese 104: 132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. (1995), Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varela, F.J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1991), The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zajonc, R. (1980), “Feeling and Thinking: Preferences Need No Inferences”, American Psychologist 39: 151175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zajonc, R. (1984a), “The Interaction of Affect and Cognition”, in Scherer and Ekman 1984, 239247.Google Scholar
Zajonc, R. (1984b), “On Primacy of Affect”, in Scherer and Ekman 1984, 259271.Google Scholar