Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T03:16:45.077Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Values in Science beyond Underdetermination and Inductive Risk

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Proponents of the value ladenness of science rely primarily on arguments from underdetermination or inductive risk, which share the premise that we should only consider values where the evidence runs out or leaves uncertainty; they adopt a criterion of lexical priority of evidence over values. The motivation behind lexical priority is to avoid reaching conclusions on the basis of wishful thinking rather than good evidence. This is a real concern, however, that giving lexical priority to evidential considerations over values is a mistake and unnecessary for avoiding the wishful thinking. Values have a deeper role to play in science.

Type
General Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank Ken Williford and the University of Texas at Arlington Philosophy Department; Martin Carrier, Don Howard, and the Center for Interdisciplinary Research (ZiF) at Bielefeld Universität; and Andrea Woody and the PSA for opportunities to present these ideas, as well as the audiences at those talks for their valuable feedback. I would especially like to thank Heather Douglas, Kevin Elliott, Kristen Intemann, Dan Hicks, and Philip Kitcher for their feedback and encouragement on this article.

References

Anderson, Elizabeth. 2004. “Uses of Value Judgments in Science: A General Argument, with Lessons from a Case Study of Feminist Research on Divorce.” Hypatia 19 (1): 124..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth 2010. “Dewey’s Moral Philosophy.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford, CA: Stanford University.Google Scholar
Biddle, Justin. 2013. “State of the Field: Transient Underdetermination and Values in Science.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 44 (1): 124–33..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Matthew J. 2012. “John Dewey’s Logic of Science.” HOPOS: Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 2 (2): 258306..Google Scholar
Brown, Matthew J. 2013. “The Source and Status of Values in Socially Responsible Science.” Philosophical Studies 163:6776. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-0070-x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewey, John. 1915. “The Logic of Judgments of Practice.” In The Middle Works, 1899–1924, Vol. 8, ed. J. A. Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Dewey, John 1939. “Theory of Valuation.” In The Later Works, 1925–1953, Vol. 13, ed. J. A. Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Douglas, Heather. 2000. “Inductive Risk and Values in Science.” Philosophy of Science 67 (4): 559–79..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elliott, Kevin C. 2011. Is a Little Pollution Good for You? Incorporating Societal Values in Environmental Research. Environmental Ethics and Science Policy Series. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1965. “Science and Human Values.” In Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, 8196. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Howard, Don A. 2006. “Lost Wanderers in the Forest of Knowledge: Some Thoughts on the Discovery-Justification Distinction.” In Revisiting Discovery and Justification: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives on the Context Distinction, ed. Schickore, Jutta and Steinle, Friedrich, 322. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Intemann, Kristen. 2005. “Feminism, Underdetermination, and Values in Science.” Philosophy of Science 72 (5): 1001–12..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, William. 1896. “The Will to Believe.” New World 5:327–47.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip. 2001. Science, Truth, and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip 2011. Science in a Democratic Society. Amherst: Prometheus.Google Scholar
Kourany, Janet A. 2003. “A Philosophy of Science for the Twenty-First Century.” Philosophy of Science 70 (1): 114..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kourany, Janet A. 2010. Philosophy of Science after Feminism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kourany, Janet A. 2013. “Meeting the Challenges to Socially Responsible Science: Reply to Brown, Lacey, and Potter.” Philosophical Studies 163 (1): 93103.. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-0073-7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1977. Objectivity, Value Judgment, and Theory Choice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 1990. Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 2002. The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 2004. “How Values Can Be Good for Science.” In Science, Values, and Objectivity, ed. Machamer, Peter and Wolters, Gereon, 127–42. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 2008. “Values, Heuristics, and the Politics of Knowledge.” In The Challenge of the Social and the Pressure of Practice: Science and Values Revisited, ed. Carrier, Martin, Howard, Don, and Kourany, Janet A., 6886. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magnus, P. D. 2003. “Underdetermination and the Claims of Science.” PhD diss., University of California, San Diego.Google Scholar
Magnus, P. D. 2013. “What Scientists Know Is Not a Function of What Scientists Know.” Philosophy of Science, in this issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. 1983. “Values in Science.” In PSA 1982: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, ed. Asquith, Peter D. and Nickles, Thomas, 328. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Nelson, Lynn Hankinson. 1990. Who Knows: From Quine to a Feminist Empiricism. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Norton, John D. 2008. “Must Evidence Underdetermine Theory?” In The Challenge of the Social and the Pressure of Practice: Science and Values Revisited, ed. Carrier, Martin, Howard, Don, and Kourany, Janet A., 1744. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rudner, Richard. 1953. “The Scientist qua Scientist Makes Value Judgments.” Philosophy of Science 20 (1): 16..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutte, Heiner. 1991. “The Philosopher Otto Neurath.” In Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle: Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath and the Vienna Circle, ed. Uebel, Thomas Ernst, 8194. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanford, Kyle. 2009. “Underdetermination of Scientific Theory.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N.. Stanford, CA: Stanford University.Google Scholar
Toulmin, Stephen. 1958. The Uses of Argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Welchman, Jennifer. 2002. “Logic and Judgments of Practice.” In Dewey’s Logical Theory: New Studies and Interpretations, ed. Burke, F. Thomas, Hester, D. Micah, and Talisse, Robert B.. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.Google Scholar