Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-42gr6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-17T17:26:37.942Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Sherlock Holmes, Galileo, and the Missing History of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Neil Thomason*
Affiliation:
University of Melbourne

Extract

Much of the history of science is missing much of the time. The missing history I have in mind is not missing because of lost documents or state secrecy. Nor is it missing because it is obscure. I am talking about central episodes in the history of science and absolutely central issues in the logical structure and evidential support of those episodes. In fact, the episodes are so central and well known, and the missing history (once seen) so obvious, that one feels compelled to hold that there must be a widespread systematic bias among historians and philosophers against seeing certain explanatory patterns.

My explanation for this missing history of science is that there is a strong tendency among historians and philosophers of science toward what I will call “Psychological Predictivism” to distinguish it from “Logical Predictivism.” Logical Predictivism is the position that, if an observed phenomenon provides good evidence for a hypothesis, then that hypothesis (plus unproblematic auxiliary hypotheses), predicts the phenomenon.

Type
Part VIII. Historical Case Studies and Methodology
Copyright
Copyright © 1994 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This is an earlier version of a much modified (Thomason (forthcoming)). I am particularly grateful to Michael Ellis, Keith Hutchison, Ross Phillips, Brian Ellis, Len O'Neill, Martin Tamny, and the Victorian Centre for the History and Philosophy of Science.

References

Abetti, Giorgio (1954), The History of Astronomy translated by Betty Burr Abetti. London: Sidgwick and Johnson.Google Scholar
Ariew, R. (1987), “The Phases of Venus Before 1610”. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 18: 8192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casper, M. (1959), Kepler, translated by Hellman, C. Doris. New York: Abelard-Schuman.Google Scholar
Chalmers, A. (1982), What is this thing called Science?, second edition. St. Lucia: University of Queensland Press.Google Scholar
Clavelin, M., (1974), The Natural Philosophy of Galileo: Essay on the Origins and Formation of Classical Mechanics, translated by Pomerans, A. J.. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cohen, I.B. (1960), The Birth of a New Physics. Garden City: Doubleday and Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crombie, A.C. (1952), Augustine to Galileo. London: Falcon Educational Books.Google Scholar
Crombie, A.C. (1959), Augustine to Galileo, revised edition. Hammondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
, Diderot and D'Alembert, (eds.) (1772, 1774), Encyclopedie ou Dictionnaire Raisonneé Des Sciences, Des Artes et Des Metiers, A Livourne, De L'Imprimerie Des Editeurs.Google Scholar
Drake, S. (1957), Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo. Garden City: Doubleday - Anchor.Google Scholar
Drake, S. (1984), “Galileo, Kepler and Phases of Venus”, Journal of the History of Astronomy, XV: 198 - 208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreyer, J.L.E. (1906/1953), History of the Planetary Systems from Thales to Kepler. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted as A History of Astronomy from Thales to Kepler. Cambridge: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, M. (ed. and translator) (1989), The Galileo Affair: A Documentary History. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Galilei, G. (1632/1967), Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems — Ptolemaic & Copernican, translated by Drake, Stillman, second edition. Berkeley and Los-Angeles: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, M. R. (1983), “Realism and Instrumentalism in Pre-Newtonian Astronomy” in Earman, John (ed.) Testing Scientific Theories, Volume X in the series Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1991), Understanding Scientific Reasoning, third edition. Fort Worth: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Gingerich, O. (1986), “Galileo's Astronomy” in Wallace, W. (ed.) Reinterpreting Galileo. Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1957), The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I., and Zahar, E. (1978), “Why Copernicus's Programme Superseded Ptolemy's” in Worrall, J. and Currie, Greg (eds.) The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes: Philosophical Papers, Volume I. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Russell, B. (1961), History of Western Philosophy and Its Connection with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earliest Times to the Present Day, new edition. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.Google Scholar
Segre, M. (1991), In the Wake of Galileo. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Shea, W.R. (1972), Galileo's Intellectual Revolution. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Smith, A. (1795), The Principles Which Lead and Direct Philosophical Enquiries; Illustrated by the History of Astronomy, reprinted in Wightman, W.P.D., Bryce, J. C. and Ross, I.S. (eds.) (1980) Adam Smith: Essays on Philosophical Subjects. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Thomason, N. (forthcoming), “1543—The Year Copernicus Didn't Predict the Phases of Venus”, in Anthony Corones and Guy Freeland (eds.) 1543 and All That. In the series, Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Thomason, N. (1994), “The Power of ARCHED Hypotheses: Feyerabend's Galileo as a Closet Rationalist,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45: 255264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallace, W. (1992), Galileo's Logic of Discovery and Proof, Volume 137 in the series, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westfall, R.S. (1971), The Construction of Modern Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar