Skip to content
BY 4.0 license Open Access Published by De Gruyter Open Access June 22, 2021

‘You Are Gods’ (Ps 81:6): Jerome and the Legacy of Origen’s Anthropology

  • Sara Contini EMAIL logo
From the journal Open Theology

Abstract

The paper discusses Jerome’s attack against the belief that human beings share the same substance as the heavenly powers and even as the Trinity, according to the dignity (dignitas) of the soul: in polemical texts such as Ep. 124.14, Jerome attributes this belief to Origen. Jerome’s intent clearly to demarcate the difference in nature between human and divine beings is also reflected in his exegetical writings, especially when dealing with Psalm 81, where human beings are addressed as “gods.” The paper investigates Jerome’s understanding of the dignitas of humanity as it emerges from his Homily on Psalm 81: the comparison with Origen’s own passages on Psalm 81 reveals that Jerome closely follows Origen’s exegetical argument. However, through a careful definition of human dignitas Jerome intentionally distances himself from Origen when it comes to associating human beings with immortal beings, most notably Christ.

1 Aim of the article

The paper concerns Jerome’s Epistle 124 (Ep. 124),[1] written around 409 to an otherwise unknown Avitus, and Jerome’s Homily on Psalm 81 (Tract.81Ps.),[2] which has been dated either to around 397,[3] or after 410.[4] Both the epistle and the homily reveal the influence of a text by Origen: the letter is written by Jerome specifically to discuss the heretical views in Origen’s treatise De Principiis (Princ.), which he argues were concealed in the Latin translation made by Rufinus in 398;[5] the homily shows significant connections with Origen’s own Homily on Psalm 81 (Hom.81Ps.).

In both the epistle and the homily, Jerome mentions dignitas, “dignity,” attributed to humanity: he clarifies that, although human souls have been endowed with a great dignity at their creation, his definition of dignitas does not entail that human souls may share the same substance or nature as the angels, or as God or Christ. The clarification that human beings are markedly different from Christ because as creatures they do not share the same substance of the Father, as Christ does, is important to Jerome’s polemic against Arian subordinationism.[6] Arianism associated Christ with creatures and downplayed his divinity: the necessity to fight this belief was especially pressing for the exegetes of Psalm 81, where human beings are addressed as “gods.”

The paper investigates the significance of Jerome’s use of dignitas in the context of his reception of Origen’s views on humanity and its relationship with God, with the aim to assess Jerome’s strategy in dealing with Origen’s controversial legacy. The paper intends to show that Jerome is deeply aware of Origen’s exegetical discourse (as exemplified by their respective interpretations of Psalm 81), but that he polemically reconsiders Origen’s views on the theme of the participation of human beings in the divine through Christ. I will argue that Jerome’s use of dignitas in his Homily on Psalm 81 reveals both his reception of Origen’s universalising views on humanity and his eagerness to present himself as a defender of the homoousios.

2 Rufinus’ translation of Origen, Princ. 4.4.9 and Jerome, Ep. 124.14

Princ. 4.4.9 is part of the final recapitulation of the most important points raised in De Principiis and concerns the theme of the immortality of human souls.[7] The text is not extant in the original Greek, but, according to Rufinus’ translation, in Princ. 4.4.9 Origen defends the immortality of the soul based on the principle of participation of all reasonable beings in the divine.[8] Origen claims that “everyone who partakes (participiat) of anything is without doubt of one substance and one nature with another who is a partaker of the same thing.”[9] The terms substantia and natura are used in this text by Rufinus as synonyms,[10] as he often does in the treatise.[11] In this context, substantia and natura may be the translations of ousìa, understood as the common nature or essence, not as the individual, personal substance: in the case of Princ. 4.4.9, natura and substantia refer to the fact that different beings (i.e. the heavenly powers and human beings) all share the nature of intellectual or reasonable creatures.[12] Origen argues that if both human beings and the heavenly powers participate in intellectual nature – albeit not to the exact same degree, but rather “in a similar manner” (simili modo) – it logically follows that human beings and heavenly powers must be of one nature (unius sine dubio debet esse naturae). Thus, if the heavenly powers are immortal, then human beings must also be immortal. Furthermore, because every reasonable creature (universa creatura) participates – albeit with different intensity, depending on each one’s intellectual capacity – in the immortal nature of the Father, the Son, and the Spirit, it follows that every reasonable creature must also be immortal.

In Rufinus’ translation of Princ. 4.4.9, Origen focuses on what he calls the “inner human” (Rom 7:22), i.e. the part of the human being that is endowed with reason or logos since its creation “in the image” or Logos of God (cf. Gen 1:26–7)[13] and is thus capable of receiving the knowledge of God. Because human beings were negligent in the pursuit of God,[14] this capacity of the human mind to know God is now dormant, but all human beings always retain in themselves the possibility to awaken this intellectual potential and progress in the knowledge of God. Hence, it would be “impious” to believe that the “intellect that is capable of receiving God should receive the destruction of its substance” (Princ. 4.4.9):[15] this would be like saying that the relationship with God is not enough to grant immortality.

On the other hand, the version of Princ. 4.4.9 transmitted by Jerome, Ep. 124.14.3,[16] says that the Trinity, the angels, and the various heavenly powers, as well as the “inner human” created in the image and likeness of God, all “perceive,” or “are conscious of,” intellectual or reasonable nature. Hence, God and the creatures “are in some way of one substance.” This version of the text is much stronger than Rufinus’ translation of Princ. 4.4.9: Rufinus merely stated that the fact that all reasonable creatures, to different degrees, participate in intellectual divine nature means that their substance cannot be corruptible and claimed that human souls were consubstantial with other reasonable creatures such as the angels. In Jerome’s version of Origen, all creatures, including human beings and angels indistinctly, are somehow of one substance with God himself. Jerome comments that for Origen “even the human beings themselves according to the dignity of the soul are of one and the same substance” with the creator.[17]

In a work composed at the same time as the Epistle 124, namely his Commentary on Isaiah,[18] Jerome proves that he believes that human souls created in the images and likeness of God possessed dignitas and were immortal. However, Jerome shows in Ep. 124.14.2 that he finds the idea, which he attributes to Origen, that the dignity of the soul could entail that the soul shares the same substance as God scandalous and unacceptable. Jerome explicitly declares that he wants to show the “impiety” of Origen’s treatise, and also its lack of consistency, because, according to him, the same Origen who in another section of De Principiis went as far as to deny that the Spirit and the Son share the same substance as the Father and therefore have the same dignity,[19] is now awarding the substance of the creator to the creatures, including human souls, by virtue of their dignity.

Because the original Greek text of Princ. 4.4.9 is not extant, we cannot say for certain which version is closer to Origen’s original text. Thus, it is not clear whether Origen himself envisioned the dignity of human souls created in the image of God as it emerges from Jerome, Ep. 124.14, i.e. as determining the consubstantiality between humanity and God. Fernández[20] compares the sentence “God and these (scil. the creatures) are in some way of one substance,” transmitted by Jerome, with Greek passages by Origen referring to “a certain kinship” between the reasonable soul and God.[21] This comparison shows that the use of moderate expressions such as quodammodo, “in some way,” is typical of Origen’s language when discussing the natural affinity or kinship between human and divine: Jerome himself remarks that Origen added quodammodo “so as to escape the charge of sacrilege.”[22] According to Fernández, although Jerome’s presentation of Origen’s overall argument in Princ. 4.4.9 is not accurate, the sentence “God and these are in some way of one substance”[23] is a real quotation from Origen and not a polemical paraphrase by Jerome. Fernández concludes that, in order to prove his – likely incorrect – point that Origen argued for the consubstantiality between creature and creator, Jerome selected a sentence by Origen which, when read correctly, in fact confirms that Origen maintained that there is some natural affinity between the reasonable soul and God, rather than fully achieved consubstantiality.[24]

Simonetti[25] and Karpp[26] are also of the opinion that Jerome’s account of the text of Princ. 4.4.9 is not completely accurate. They point out that Jerome’s version interrupts the flow of the argument in Princ. 4.4.9 by not maintaining, as Rufinus does, the separation between two distinct claims on the immortality of the human soul. In Rufinus’ translation, Origen argues first that as they both participate in intellectual nature, heavenly powers and human beings must have the same substance,[27] and second, that because the intellect of human beings, created in the image of God, may be enlightened by God, then it must be fundamentally incorruptible.[28] The distinction between these two arguments is not as clearly demarcated in the version of the text transmitted by Jerome. Hence, even if a statement similar to “God and the creatures are in some way of one substance” might have been present in Origen’s Greek text,[29] overall Jerome’s account of Princ. 4.4.9 is not necessarily preferable to Rufinus’ translation, because it is possible that it puts together different parts of Origen’s discourse.

It is doubtful that Origen argued for the full consubstantiality between creatures and creator, as he was accused by some of his detractors such as Jerome and Theophilus of Alexandria,[30] but not by others such as Epiphanius.[31] Jerome himself is not consistent in his claims that Origen argued for the consubstantiality between creatures and creator.[32] Furthermore, outside of Jerome’s Ep. 124.14, the notion of the natural affinity between the intellect within human beings and the pure intellect of the divine is as far as we know not explicitly expressed by Origen in terms of human beings and God being of one and the same nature or substance.[33] Even in Greek passages where Origen discusses the kinship between the divine Logos and the reasonable substance of the human soul, such as Orat. 27.9,[34] his argument is closer to the discourse in Rufinus’ version of Princ. 4.4.9, namely, that human souls are immortal because of the participation of reasonable creatures in God through the Logos, rather than indicating that all creatures are of one and the same substance with the Father. In fact, in Hom.15Ps. 2.8, Origen remarks on the difference between the human soul of Christ and the divine ousìa of the Logos,[35] and the “consubstantiality” between the “unbegotten nature” of God and the creatures is condemned as “the greatest impiety” in Comm.Jo. 13.25.149.[36] This passage is explicitly directed against the Gnostic Heracleon, who, according to Origen, maintained that only some human beings were naturally endowed with divinity and thus predestined for salvation since their beginning;[37] conversely, as we will see in the next section, Origen maintains that all human beings are naturally capable of pursuing divinity as the end of their progress.

So, in Ep. 124.14, Jerome does not deny the existence of a dignity specific to human souls. He sees as highly problematic the idea, which he attributes to Origen, that this dignity entails that human souls share the same substance of God and of the heavenly powers. In the next section, we will see how Jerome defines the extent of the dignity bestowed on humanity by God, and how this correlates with Origen’s views on the relationship between human beings and Christ.

3 Jerome’s exegesis of Psalm 81 and its predecessors

Although Jerome’s claim that for Origen human beings shared one and the same substance with God can be doubted, it is true that Origen indicates in Rufinus’ translation of De Principiis that, because of their creation in the image or Logos of God, human beings could attain a very high level of participation in God through his Son. In Princ. 1.3.8,[38] Origen claims that all human beings received, through Christ as reason, that they are reasonable beings; additionally, God gave them the possibility of progressing in their participation in Christ as justice and wisdom, until, by the grace of the Spirit, they become “worthy of God.” In Princ. 3.6.1,[39] Origen says that all human beings received, through Christ as image of God, a “dignity of the image” that gives them the possibility of progressing in their participation in Christ until they become “like God;” by the intercession of Christ, finally in the eschaton human beings are made “one” with God.

In a text that Origen produced about two decades after De Principiis [40] and was preserved in the original Greek, the Homily on Psalm 81, Origen makes an even bolder statement. He claims that all human beings received, through Christ as God, a “gift” that allows them to become gods. Then, because of sin, human beings “fell down” (Ps 81:7) from the status of divinity into that of humanity, but those human beings who turn away from sin and receive in their soul the God Logos can be made gods again.[41] The verses in the Psalm that support Origen’s view that human beings were originally gifted with the possibility of achieving divinity through Christ are Ps 81:1a, “God stands in the assembly of the gods,” and Ps 81:6, “I said: ‘You are gods, and all children of the Most High’.”[42]

Christian exegetes from the second and early third centuries offered a multifaceted interpretation of the titles “gods” and “children” in Psalm 81. Some emphasized the universal dimension of these titles, bestowed on humanity at creation: for Justin,[43] since all human beings were indistinctly endowed with the possibility of becoming “gods” and “children of God” if they keep God’s commandments, every one of them will be judged by God like Adam and Eve if by breaking the commandments they do not fulfil this possibility.[44] Other exegetes, such as Clement of Alexandria,[45] stressed the element of worthiness, presenting the titles of “gods” and “children” in Ps 81:1,6 as attained by exceptionally progressed individuals, rather than as originally attributed to all of humanity, at least as potential.

For Origen, the title “gods” in Psalm 81 refers, on the one hand, to the entirety of humanity, and on the other, only to righteous human beings: all human beings are capable of restoring their divinity, but only the righteous deserve to be called “gods” when they actually fulfil this possibility by detaching themselves from the sins of the flesh and by receiving the Logos in themselves.[46] From this perspective, we may understand why in texts other than the Homily on Psalm 81 Origen had interpreted the “gods” in Psalm 81 as referring not to humanity but to angels and heavenly powers.[47] This interpretation does not deny that the Psalm may at the same time also refer to the human species, which possesses divinity as a potential: for Origen there was no difference in nature between the souls of human beings and the other reasonable creatures, such as the angels.[48] In passages on Psalm 81, such as Cels. 4.29,[49] Origen explains that it is up to human beings to either progress through the Logos in virtue and reason until they deserve the title of “gods” (Ps 81:6) that the angels already possess, or to give in to sin and thus remain “human beings” (Ps 81:7).[50]

Princ. 4.4.9 and Hom.81Ps. 1 are among the many passages where Origen describes the progress of human beings towards a close relationship with God as an achievement made possible in the future by an existing element of communion with God.[51] This element is understood by Origen as an intellectual capacity or potential that all of humanity received at creation through the Logos or “image” of God; furthermore, Origen indicates that the help of the Logos as well as individual merit is necessary to activate this potential in every human soul. In Origen’s Greek writings and in the Latin translations, we find the concept of the human capacity to pursue a higher degree of participation in the divine expressed in many ways: for instance, in Hom.81Ps. 1,[52] Origen refers to a “gift” (δωρεά) that calls human beings to become “gods” through Christ.

The belief that humanity received from God the possibility to progress in their relationship with God through Christ is also shared by Jerome: in his Homily on Psalm 81, Jerome refers to the high status bestowed on humanity as dignitas, which in his view stems from the fact that human beings may deserve to be adopted into the divine filiality of Christ.[53] However, as we will see, Jerome’s definition of human dignitas in the Homily on Psalm 81 shows significant differences from Origen’s views on the relationship between human beings and Christ.

In an epistle addressed to Augustine,[54] Jerome enumerates the Christian exegetes who dealt with the Psalter. Of the Greek authors Jerome mentions, we can now read only two complete works focusing on Psalm 81, namely the Homily on Psalm 81 by Origen and the Commentary on Psalm 81 by Eusebius of Caesarea, plus a few references to Psalm 81 in Didymus’ extant commentaries on other biblical texts. Of these works, Jerome’s Homily on Psalm 81 is closest to Origen’s homily. Capone argues that the influence of Origen on Jerome’s exegesis of the Psalter does not only mean that Jerome adopts some exegetical solutions by Origen,[55] but also that he directly challenges his views:[56] Jerome’s Homily on Psalm 81, compared to the one by Origen, confirms this.

In most of his works, Jerome refers Ps 81:1 or Ps 81:6 to angels or to exceptionally worthy human beings. In Comm.81Ps. ad 1a,[57] written before 393, Jerome had interpreted the “gods” in Ps 81:1 and Ps 81:6 solely as angels or saints; in Comm.Zach. 1 ad 3:6–7,[58] he interprets them as prophets, apostles, and other saints in the Church,[59] much like Didymus did in his own Comm.Zach. ad 3:6–7.[60] In Tract.115Ps. 12 and Tract.135Ps. 2,[61] Jerome refers Ps 81:6 to those human beings who are so holy, so progressed in the truth of God and removed from human sins, that they are not called human beings anymore, but gods.[62] In some cases, Ps 81:1 or Ps 81:6–7 are interpreted by Jerome as referring to people who possess the authority to judge other people: for example, in Comm.Ezech. 13 ad 44:23–4,[63] Jerome interprets the “gods” in Ps 81:1 as the priests, who were authorized by God to judge other human beings in this life, and who should be impartial because their actions will then in turn be judged by God himself.[64] Jerome’s interpretation of the title “gods” as referring primarily to a few selected human beings[65] is in line with the general tendency of the exegesis of Ps 81:1,6 as developed in the second half of the fourth century by both Greek and Latin authors, who tended to emphasize that the title denotes exceptionally progressed individuals, rather than highlighting how the Psalm may also refer to a universal human capacity for divinity.[66]

However, in Jerome’s Homilies on Psalms, we also find passages suggesting that the title “children” of God in Ps 81:6 was originally bestowed by God on humanity as a whole.[67] Jerome, Tract.89Ps. 16, conveys that because of sin, human beings have collectively lost their previous status as children of God,[68] so they should all pray to God to guide them in the right direction until they return to be children of God again. Furthermore, in his Homily on Psalm 81, Jerome interprets also the title “gods” in Ps 81:1,6 as referring to humanity in general: of all the extant texts by Jerome or others dealing with Psalm 81, this homily is the only one that features dignitas. Jerome exclaims: “Behold the dignity of the human being (vide hominis dignitatem). (…) He (scil. God) gives to us the name (scil. of gods, Ps 81:1), so that he may give also the reward,” and: “Behold how great is the dignity (videte quanta sit dignitas): we are called ‘gods’ and ‘children’ (Ps 81:6).”[69]

Jerome remarks that God bestowed this dignity of gods and children equally on all human beings, as indicated in Ps 81:6. Jerome explains that God gave equally to all human beings divinity and adoption,[70] and that: “We are all born equal (aequaliter), emperors and paupers; and we die as equal, for the creation is equal (aequalis enim conditio est).”[71] Capone translates the term conditio in this sentence as indicating the status of created beings; other translators understand conditio as the common “condition” or “quality” of all human beings.[72] Given that conditio indicates the creative act of God,[73] this sentence by Jerome can be understood as indicating that all human beings (and not all creatures in general) are created equal by God, and therefore equally share the dignitas of being called “gods” and “children” by God, regardless of their social status as “emperors” or “paupers.” Origen makes a similar observation: everyone is called by God to become god, not just “bishops, presbyters, and deacons” but also laypeople.[74] This observation that Ps 81:6 does not refer to the differences in social status[75] is only found in the two homilies by Jerome and Origen, and not in the other texts on Psalm 81 mentioned in this article. Jerome and Origen agree that the Psalm conveys that God wants human beings – all human beings – to become gods through Christ (as Jerome puts it: “I created the human being for this purpose, that from human beings they may become gods”),[76] and for Jerome this great favour that God bestows on humanity signals the high status or dignity (dignitas) of humanity.

However, Jerome feels compelled to clarify what exactly this dignitas of humanity entails: compared to Origen’s Homily on Psalm 81, Jerome appears more interested in stressing the distinction between the divinity that Christ possesses and the divinity that Christ bestows on human beings.[77] Origen describes the relationship between Christ and human beings as the one between a teacher and his disciples.[78] For Origen, the common objective that both the teacher and the disciples aim to achieve is that the disciples truly become what the teacher already is, by imitating him.[79] Hence, in this homily Origen does not produce definitive theological statements on the difference between the divinity of Christ and the divinity available to human beings. Instead, Origen claims that upon receiving the Logos “the whole human being becomes god,” in spirit, soul, and even body.[80]

Conversely, Jerome specifies that human beings are in fact not “children” and “gods” in a way similar (similiter) to how the Son of God is son[81] and god: human beings are gods not by nature (natura), but by grace (gratia).[82] Jerome indicates that this distinction is significant to counteract the views on the Son of God and his relationship with the creatures held by Arius and Eunomius. The need to interpret Psalm 81 in a way that defends the full divinity of the Son against Arianism is often expressed by fourth century exegetes: for instance, Athanasius claims that only the Son is truly God as he is one in essence with the Father, whereas human beings are called “gods” in Ps 81:6 not because of their nature, but because of their participation in the Son (οὐ τῇ ϕύσει, ἀλλὰ τῇ μετουσίᾳ τοῦ υἱοῦ).[83]

Jerome adopts this perspective also when dealing with Ps 76:14b, “Which god is great like our God?” Because this verse seems to imply that there are multiple gods, both Origen and Jerome associate Ps 76:14b with the reference to the “gods” in Ps 81:1,6;[84] this association is not found in other homilies or commentaries on Psalm 76, such as those by Eusebius or Augustine. Origen explains that the name “gods” is bestowed by God on the righteous who receive the Logos in themselves, recognize his divinity, and participate in him. For Origen, these just human beings truly “become gods;” he remarks that from a hierarchical standpoint Christ is “incommensurably superior to all of them,”[85] but Origen does not specify in his homily exactly in which way the divinity bestowed on human beings is different in nature from the divinity of Christ. On the other hand, Jerome briefly explains: “the saints are called ‘gods’,” and specifies: “they are gods depending on grace (secundum gratiam), while you,” meaning God, addressed in the Psalm, “are God by nature (natura).”[86] So, while Origen’s main purpose in Hom.76Ps. 2.5 was to demonstrate that Ps 76:14b and Ps 81:1,6 did not in fact support polytheism,[87] Jerome’s primary concern is to clarify exactly to what extent human beings may be called “gods,” and what is the difference from the true divinity of God.

The view that Ps 81:6 should not be interpreted as indicating that human beings are gods by nature is also present in Origen’s own Comm.Cant. prol. 2.34 and Hom.Exod. 6.5.[88] Origen claims that creatures are in the Psalm called “gods” by grace and because of their participation in God, not because they attain the very same nature and power of the uncreated, incorporeal, immutable Trinity.[89] These passages would seem to disprove the allegations made by Jerome in Ep. 124.14.2,[90] where he accuses Origen of attributing the same substance to God and to human souls. The passages in the Homilies on Exodus and in the Commentary on the Song of Songs are only extant in Rufinus’ translation, but the notion expressed in the Greek homilies by Origen, namely that human beings should strive to become “gods” (Ps 81:6) through Christ,[91] is not necessarily in contradiction to the caveat in the works translated by Rufinus that human beings are called gods by grace and not by nature.[92] In the Greek texts on Psalm 81, as well as in the Latin passages translated by Rufinus, divinity is presented by Origen as possessed by God and the Logos immutably and eternally, while human beings have lost it and can only regain it through Christ.

The distinction between the divinity that is God, the divinity possessed by the Logos, and the divinity achievable by human beings is further clarified by Origen in Comm.Jo. 2.2.17–3.24:[93] the Father is the God, i.e. divinity itself (ὁ θεός, αὐτόθεος), while the Logos is made God (θεός) immutably by the full participation in the Father.[94] The reasonable creatures may be assimilated to divinity by participation in the Logos: as in the present time each individual creature participates in the Logos to a different degree, each of them achieves a different degree of divinity. Thus, Origen does not indicate that the difference between the divinity of the Son and the divinity available to human beings is that only human beings attain it through participation, as was later argued by authors such as Athanasius and Jerome in the context of the fight against Arianism. Conversely, Origen states that the Son also receives divinity via participation. Nevertheless, Origen effectively conveys the hierarchy between the divinity of God and the Son, on one side, and the divinity achieved by human beings who “become gods,” on the other, by highlighting the mediating role of the Logos: only the Logos attains divinity eternally and directly from the Father himself, whereas the worthy creatures who imitate Christ attain a mediated form of divinity, through the intercession of the Logos.[95]

However, even with the specifications introduced in texts such as Comm.Jo. 2.1.17–3.24, in his exegesis of Psalm 81 Origen expressed his conviction that human beings can be assimilated to the divinity of Christ in bolder terms than Jerome ever did in his own writings. An indicator that Jerome is less confident than Origen in associating human beings with immortal beings, such as the devil, or with Christ, is their respective interpretations of Ps 81:2–3, “How long will you judge injustice, and receive the role of the sinner? Judge the orphan and the poor, give justice to the humble and destitute.” Origen first interprets this “role” in the context of the judgement mentioned in the Psalm, i.e. as indicating that, when we give preference to a wealthy sinner rather than to a poor but just person, we “receive the role of the sinner.”[96] Then, Origen offers another explanation: theatre performers are assigned specific roles that they have practiced; for example, an actor can “receive the role” of a king, a slave, a woman.[97] Origen explains that, when we have practiced justice, we “receive the role of Christ” and “the role of a holy angel;” thus, we should always aim to “receive the role of God” and never to receive the roles of the devil or his demons due to our sin.[98]

Jerome adopts the interpretation with the trial between the rich sinner and the poor righteous person;[99] then, like Origen, he adds that there is also a deeper, more recondite meaning[100] to this “role,” which refers to acting. However, while Origen spoke of human beings assuming the role of the devil or of Christ, Jerome speaks in more generic terms of people “receiving the role” of the lion when they are angry, of the wolf when they steal,[101] of the cruel person when they kill, of the clement person when they give alms, etc. So, Jerome closely follows Origen’s exegesis of Ps 81:2, with the double interpretation of “role” in reference both to the judgement and to the actor’s performance, but he diverges from it when Origen says that human beings may “receive the role” of Christ or of immortal beings such as the angels or the devil. This is further evidence both of Jerome’s reception of Origen’s exegesis of the Psalms and of his reluctance to follow Origen when the latter associates human beings with the heavenly powers and even with Christ without clearly establishing a difference in nature.

Additionally, Jerome distinguishes between the nature of human beings and the nature of heavenly powers. Jerome states that the devil was not created as an evil spirit by God; rather, he was an angel by nature and originally placed in heaven. The consequence of the devil’s sin was for Jerome different from the consequences faced by Adam: when Adam, a human being by nature, disobeyed the commandment of God, Adam fell and died;[102] conversely, the devil only fell because “the angelic dignity (angelica dignitas) cannot receive death, but only fall.”[103] In this text, Jerome further proves that for him human nature and dignity are fundamentally different from angelic nature and dignity.[104] Like Jerome, Origen, Eusebius, and Didymus[105] also identify the fallen ruler mentioned in Ps 81:7b with the devil, the angel who fell from heaven; however, these Greek authors do not mark the difference observed by Jerome[106] between the immortal nature of the angelic order and the nature of humanity.

4 Conclusion

Origen’s arguments are often more nuanced and articulated than as presented by Jerome in polemically charged texts such as Epistle 124. In particular, Jerome’s account of Origen frames the unity between all creatures, Christ, and God as a consubstantiality already achieved in the present, whereas this notion is presented by Origen (in Rufinus’ translation of De Principiis, but also in Greek works where Origen interprets Psalm 81) as a potential that each one must work to fulfill themselves, with the help of the Logos, who unlike the creatures, participates in God’s substance immutably.

This reflects on Jerome’s presentation of the dignity of humanity: Jerome believed that human souls created in the image of God were immortal and endowed by God with dignity. In his Homily on Psalm 81, Jerome argues that humanity has dignity because God created all human beings with the possibility of deserving the grace of becoming “gods” and “children” of God (Ps 81:6). However, Jerome feels compelled to find a way to speak of this great dignity of humanity without falling into what he presented in Ep. 124.14 as Origen’s error, i.e. merging into one and the same substance God, the immortal angels, and human beings based on the dignity of their soul, and without undermining the Nicene creed, which attributed to the Son the same substance as the Father and thus distinguished Christ from the creatures. Jerome accomplishes this by stating in Tract.81Ps. 6 that no human being is or will be so worthy as to deserve to truly become “god” and “child of God” in the same way as Christ is, i.e. in substance.

Jerome’s interpretation of Psalm 81 largely draws from Origen’s Homily on Psalm 81, especially in passages where Jerome highlights the universality of the title “gods” in the Psalm, which reveals the high dignity bestowed at creation on all of humankind. However, with his clear efforts to define this dignity in terms of grace rather than nature, Jerome consciously positions himself as part of an explicitly anti-Arian exegetical tradition on Psalm 81, represented by authors such as Athanasius.

  1. Funding information: This research has received funding from the DAAD – Deutscher Akademischer Austauschdienst. The publication has been financed by Carlsberg Foundation, grant number CF19-0832.

  2. Conflict of interest: Author states no conflict of interest.

References

Ayroulet, Élie. “Ego dixi: dii estis (Ps 82 [81], 6) Une exégèse théologique et dogmatique d’inspiration athanasienne au service d’une théologie de la grâce.” In L’exégèse de saint Jérôme, edited by Élie Ayroulet and Aline Canellis, 297–306. Saint-Étienne: Publications de l’Université de Saint-Étienne, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Behr, John. Origen. On First Principles, 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017.Search in Google Scholar

Berglund, Carl Johan. Origen’s References to Heracleon. A Quotation-Analytical Study of the Earliest Known Commentary on the Gospel of John. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2020.Search in Google Scholar

Capone, Alessandro. “Vim facere scripturae: spunti polemici nei Tractatus in Psalmos di Gerolamo.” Auctores Nostri 14 (2014), 315–34.Search in Google Scholar

Capone, Alessandro. Girolamo. 59 Omelie sui Salmi (1–115) – Omelia sul Salmo 41 ai neofiti. Rome: Città Nuova, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Capone, Alessandro. “Scomposizione e composizione dei Tractatus in psalmos di Gerolamo.” In L’exégèse de saint Jérôme, edited by Élie Ayroulet and Aline Canellis, 131–49. Saint-Étienne: Publications de l’Université de Saint-Étienne, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Caruso, Giuseppe. Ramusculus Origenis. L’eredità dell’antropologia origeniana nei pelagiani e in Girolamo. Rome: Institutum Patristicum Augustinianum, 2012.Search in Google Scholar

Chadwick, Henry. Origen. Contra Celsum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1953.Search in Google Scholar

Cocchini, Francesca. “Discorsi della cena: la ‘lavanda dei piedi’ (CIo 32, 56–140), un ‘gesto’ e un ‘testo’ da comprendere in profondità.” In Commento a Giovanni: Lettura origeniana, edited by Mario Maritano and Enrico Dal Covolo, 23–46. Rome: LAS – Libreria Ateneo Salesiano, 2006.Search in Google Scholar

Coppa, Giovanni. Origene – Gerolamo. 74 Omelie sul Libro dei Salmi. Milan: Paoline, 1993.Search in Google Scholar

Crouzel, Henri. Origène. Paris: Lethielleux, 1985.Search in Google Scholar

Curti, Carmelo. “Il linguaggio relativo al Padre e al Figlio in alcuni passi dei Commentarii in Psalmos di Eusebio di Cesarea.” Augustinianum 13:3 (1973), 483–506.10.5840/agstm197313336Search in Google Scholar

Dolbeau, François and Martine Dulaey. Œuvres de Saint Augustin 77A: Sermons Dolbeau 1–10. Paris: Institut d’Études Augustiniennes, 2020.Search in Google Scholar

Edwards, Mark J. “One Origen or Two: The Status Quaestionis.” Symbolae Osloenses. 89:1 (2018), 81–103.10.1080/00397679.2015.1030249Search in Google Scholar

Evers, Dirk. “Origen and Karl Barth on Universal Salvation.” Adamantius 25 (2019), 39–54.Search in Google Scholar

Fernández, Samuel. “Gli interventi dottrinali di Rufino nel De Principiis di Origene.” In L’Oriente in Occidente. L’opera di Rufino di Concordia, edited by Maurizio Girolami, 27–44. Brescia: Morcelliana, 2014.Search in Google Scholar

Fernández, Samuel. Orígenes. Sobre los Principios. Madrid: Ciudad Nueva, 2015.Search in Google Scholar

Fernández, Samuel. “‘That Man Who Appeared in Judaea’ (Prin II,6,2). The Soteriological Function of the Humanity of the Son of God According to Origen’s De Principiis.” In Origeniana Duodecima. Origen’s Legacy in the Holy Land. A Tale of Three Cities: Jerusalem, Caesarea, and Bethlehem, edited by Brouria Bitton-Ashkelony, Oded Irshai, Aryeh Kofsky, Hillel Newman, and Lorenzo Perrone, 563–72. Leuven/Paris/Bristol CT: Peeters, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Gers-Uphaus, Christian. Sterbliche Götter – göttliche Menschen: Psalm 82 und seine frühchristlichen Deutungen. Stuttgart: Verlag Katholisches Bibelwerk, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Görgemanns, Herwig and Heinrich Karpp. Origenes. Vier Bücher von den Prinzipien. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1976.Search in Google Scholar

Greer, Rowan A. Origen. An Exhortation to Martyrdom. New York: Paulist Press, 1979.Search in Google Scholar

Gronewald, Michael. Didymos der Blinde. Psalmenkommentar (Tura-Papyrus). Teil III (Kommentar zu Psalm 29–34). Bonn: Rudolf Habelt Verlag, 1969.Search in Google Scholar

Hušek, Vit. “Rebirth into a New Man: Deification in Jerome.” In Deification in the Latin Patristic Tradition, edited by Jared Ortiz, 153–68. Washington D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2019.10.2307/j.ctvcwntbb.13Search in Google Scholar

Lee, Justin J. “‘Seek and Ye Shall Find’. Rufinus and the Search for Origen’s trinitarian orthodoxy.” In Origeniana Duodecima. Origen’s Legacy in the Holy Land. A Tale of Three Cities: Jerusalem, Caesarea, and Bethlehem, edited by Brouria Bitton-Ashkelony, Oded Irshai, Aryeh Kofsky, Hillel Newman, and Lorenzo Perrone, 447–60. Leuven/Paris/Bristol CT: Peeters, 2019.Search in Google Scholar

Limone, Vito. Origene e la filosofia greca. Scienze, testi, lessico. Brescia: Morcelliana, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Malavasi, Giulio. “Sulla datazione dei Tractatus in Psalmos 89 e 90 series altera di Gerolamo.” Sacris Erudiri 58 (2019), 95–109.10.1484/J.SE.5.119447Search in Google Scholar

Maspero, Giulio. “The logos in Us and the Logos in the Beginning according to Origen.” In Origeniana Undecima. Origen and Origenism in the History of Western Thought, edited by Anders-Christian Jacobsen, 843–56. Leuven/Paris/Bristol CT: Peeters, 2016.Search in Google Scholar

Mosser, Carl. “The Earliest Patristic Interpretations of Psalm 82, Jewish Antecedents, and the Origin of Christian Deification.” The Journal of Theological Studies 56:1 (2005), 30–74.10.1093/jts/fli002Search in Google Scholar

Norelli, Enrico. “Marcione e gli gnostici sul libero arbitrio, e la polemica di Origene.” In Il cuore indurito del Faraone. Origene e il problema del libero arbitrio, edited by Lorenzo Perrone, 1–30. Bologna: Marietti, 1992.Search in Google Scholar

Orlandi, Elena. “Aspetti della rielaborazione delle omelie origeniane sui Salmi (Cod. Mon. Graec. 314) nei Tractatus in Psalmos di Gerolamo.” In L’exégèse de saint Jérôme, edited by Élie Ayroulet and Aline Canellis, 101–13. Saint-Étienne: Publications de l’Université de Saint-Étienne, 2018.Search in Google Scholar

Perrone, Lorenzo. La preghiera secondo Origene: L’impossibilità donata. Brescia: Morcelliana, 2011.Search in Google Scholar

Perrone, Lorenzo. “Un ‘ressourcement’ inattendu: les nouvelles Homélies d’Origène sur les Psaumes dans le codex de Munich.” In Le livre scellé, edited by Laurence Mellerin, 19–46. Turnhout: Brepols, 2017.Search in Google Scholar

Perrone, Lorenzo. “The Dating of the New Homilies on the Psalms in the Munich Codex: The Ultimate Origen?” Proche-Orient Chrétien 67 (2017), 243–51.Search in Google Scholar

Perrone, Lorenzo. “‘Et l’homme tout entier devient dieu’: La déification selon Origène à la lumière des nouvelles Homélies sur les Psaumes.” Teología y Vida 58:2 (2017), 187–220.10.4067/S0049-34492017000200003Search in Google Scholar

Perrone, Lorenzo. Opere di Origene IX/3a. Omelie sui Salmi. Rome: Città Nuova, 2020.Search in Google Scholar

Perrone, Lorenzo. “Mysteria in Psalmis: Origen and Jerome as interpreters of the Psalter.” In The Bible in the Patristic Period, edited by Mariusz Szram and Marcin Wysocki, 59–86. Leuven/Paris/Bristol CT: Peeters, 2021.10.2307/j.ctv1q26pp2.7Search in Google Scholar

Prinzivalli, Emanuela. “Discorsi della cena: la glorificazione del Figlio dell’uomo (CIo 32, 318–400).” In Commento a Giovanni: Lettura origeniana, edited by Mario Maritano and Enrico Dal Covolo, 135–56. Rome: LAS – Libreria Ateneo Salesiano, 2006.Search in Google Scholar

Puchniak, Robert. “Augustine’s Concept of Deification, Revisited.” In Theosis. Deification in Christian Theology, edited by Stephen Finlan and Vladimir Kharlamov, 122–33. Eugene, OR: Pickwick Publications, 2006.10.2307/j.ctt16wdm3x.10Search in Google Scholar

Rankine, Patrice. “Dignity in Homer and Classical Greece.” In Dignity. A History, edited by Remy Debes, 19–45. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199385997.003.0002Search in Google Scholar

Russell, Norman. The Doctrine of Deification in the Greek Patristic Tradition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.Search in Google Scholar

Savvidis, Kyriakos. Athanasius Werke I/1: Die dogmatischen Schriften 4. Epistulae I-IV ad Serapionem. Berlin/Boston: DeGruyter, 2010.Search in Google Scholar

Scardia, Daniela. “Ex parte totum: la sineddoche nei Tractatus in Psalmos di Gerolamo tra esegesi, polemica e retorica.” Bollettino della Badia Greca di Grottaferrata Terza Serie 13 (2016), 115–58.Search in Google Scholar

Scardia, Daniela. “Tractatus in Psalmum 15, 8 (series altera): Gerolamo tra rispetto dei modelli e autonomia esegetica.” Augustinianum 60:2 (2020), 427–52.10.5840/agstm202060223Search in Google Scholar

Scott, Alan. Origen and the Life of the Stars: A History of an Idea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198263616.001.0001Search in Google Scholar

Simonetti, Manlio. La crisi ariana nel IV secolo. Rome: Institutum Patristicum Augustinianum, 1975.Search in Google Scholar

Simonetti, Manlio. “Dio (Padre).” In Origene. Dizionario: La cultura, il pensiero, le opere, edited by Adele Monaci Castagno, 118–124. Rome: Città Nuova, 2000.Search in Google Scholar

Simonetti, Manlio. Origene. I princìpi. Turin: UTET, 2010.Search in Google Scholar

Squires, Stuart. “Jerome on Sinlessness: a Via Media between Augustine and Pelagius.” The Heythrop Journal 57:4 (2013), 697–709.10.1111/heyj.12063Search in Google Scholar

Stefanelli, Giovanna. “Cristiani, giudei e pagani: lessico, esegesi e polemica nei Tractatus in Psalmos di Gerolamo.” Augustinianum 57:1 (2017), 81–106.10.5840/agstm20175715Search in Google Scholar

Thomson, Robert W. Athanasius. Contra Gentes and De Incarnatione. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971.Search in Google Scholar

Received: 2021-04-29
Accepted: 2021-05-11
Published Online: 2021-06-22

© 2021 Sara Contini, published by De Gruyter

This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.

Downloaded on 7.5.2024 from https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/opth-2020-0158/html
Scroll to top button